Skip to main content
UKPMC Funders Author Manuscripts logoLink to UKPMC Funders Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2019 Dec 1.
Published in final edited form as: Nat Hum Behav. 2019 Apr 22;3(6):554–559. doi: 10.1038/s41562-019-0596-4

Shared Responsibility in Collective Decisions

Marwa El Zein 1,*, Bahador Bahrami 2,3, Ralph Hertwig 3
PMCID: PMC6570616  EMSID: EMS83171  PMID: 31011162

Abstract

Research investigating collective decision making has focused primarily on the improvement of accuracy in collective decisions and less on the motives that drive individuals to make these decisions. We argue that a strong but neglected motive for making collective decisions is minimizing the material and psychological burden of an individual’s responsibility. Making difficult decisions with others shields individuals from the consequences of negative outcomes by reducing regret, punishment, and stress. Considering shared responsibility as a another key motivation to join groups helps understand behaviors with societal implications such as political voting, committing norm violations, predicting natural disasters, and making health-related decisions.


People make many decisions collectively; these range from mundane choices such as where to have dinner to fateful ones such as how to vote in an important election or referendum. Collective decisions are also made by other social species, such as bees1, ants1, and fish2. These species make group decisions by mechanisms similar to voting and consensus1,2. In this Perspective, however, we focus on human collective decision making. Previous research in this field has concentrated on whether the accuracy of collective decisions surpasses that of individual decisions, and under which conditions this “wisdom of the crowd” can be harnessed313. Here, we shift the focus to a key issue that has received little attention to date: Why do individuals engage in collective decision-making behaviors in the first place?

One answer to this question is that collective decisions are often obligatory: numerous endeavors are only possible when people coordinate their efforts and act collectively (Figure 1A). Examples of this type of collective behavior include being part of a reproducing couple, hunting a large and dangerous prey14, and manufacturing a product that requires various specialized skills (although belonging to such a collective does not imply that, by necessity and across cultures15, decision making will always be participatory and collective). In these latter cases, individual members have no choice but to abide by the collective norm. However, there is another class of situations that arise when individuals with the same goal or incentives voluntarily choose to take a collective decision (Figure 1B). Examples of this type of collective behavior include friends starting a business, groups of doctors making medical decisions, and panels of experts predicting a financial crisis. Our focus is on this latter class of situations, in which collective decisions are voluntary.

Figure 1. Motives for collective decision making.

Figure 1

A framework for understanding individuals’ motives for engaging in collective decision-making behaviors. The first distinction is between circumstances in which collective decisions are A) obligatory versus B) voluntary. We focus on the latter (A). The second distinction is between motives that relate to a) the decision process itself and (b–c) its anticipated outcome. The different motives are linked back to the three categories identified in the main text: improving outcomes (underlined, Category 1); social inclusion and normative needs (in italic, Category 2); shared responsibility (in bold, Category 3). a) Under the process-related motives, individuals combine their efforts during the decision process (Effort), feel included in the group (Social inclusion), and fulfill their normative needs for fairness and procedural justice (Fairness). b) Under an anticipated positive outcome, individuals pool intelligence to reach a better/positive outcome (Pooling intelligence) and are able to claim credit for successful outcomes (Credit). c) Under an anticipated negative outcome associated with decision uncertainty or difficulty—our focus in the main text—sharing responsibility reduces Regret, Punishment, and Stress.

Why Voluntarily Join Collectives

For an individual, achieving admission to a group can be costly. Orchestrating a joint decision can exact costs such as loss of autonomy and time, and/or coordination costs16,17. Given these potentially substantial costs, what makes the collective approach to making decisions attractive? Motives for joining collectives can relate to the decision process itself or to its anticipated positive/negative outcomes (Figure 1).

We identify three main categories of motives for voluntary collective decisions (coded as underlined, italic, and bold in Figure 1). The first is improving outcomes by joining forces (underlined). Here, individuals can be driven by combining their efforts during the decision process (dividing their labor or sharing necessary materials, Figure 1a, Effort), increasing accuracy, acquiring veridical representations of reality18, obtaining higher rewards19, and learning from others20,21 (i.e., pooling intelligence to reach positive outcomes; Figure 1b, Pooling intelligence). These motives are not self-evident. The saying that “two heads are better than one” vies with contradictory maxims, such as “too many cooks spoil the broth.” Even in his legendary demonstration of collective wisdom, Francis Galton22 was surprised that the “vox populi” outperformed the individuals’ estimates. Likewise, individuals underestimate the improvement achieved in reasoning tasks when they act as a group23.

A second important category of motives for joining groups relates to social and normative needs, i.e., feeling included in a group or society and fulfilling needs for fairness (shown in italic in Figure 1). Social interactions can be intrinsically rewarding24, and being a member of a group can help to maintain a positive self-concept through positive shared social identity2527 (Figure 1a, social inclusion). Furthermore, people have various communal and normative needs: they care about emotional identification, moral values associated with cooperation19, and procedural justice28 (concern for fairness; Figure 1a, Fairness).

However, there is another, underappreciated and under-investigated third category of motives for joining groups: sharing responsibility for decisions (shown in bold in Figure 1). We argue that shared responsibility plays an important role in motivating collective decision making because its benefits are consistent and reliable, even in the absence of improved outcomes. In the next three sections of the perspective, we advance this thesis in three steps: (1) We provide evidence that responsibility is indeed shared in collective behaviors, allowing individuals to claim credit for positive outcomes (Figure 1b, Credit) while avoiding blame for negative outcomes. (2) We identify conditions and contexts under which sharing responsibility with others can benefit the individual. (3) We argue that sharing responsibility benefits the individual by decreasing the risk of internal sanctioning (regret), external sanctioning (punishment) and stress (Figure 1c). Because few empirical studies have directly addressed the motives underlying collective decision-making we draw on evidence is, by necessity, predominantly circumstantial. We believe, however, that the evidence we present from studies on responsibility, agency, group behaviors, and delegation supports our thesis and highlights the relevance of this previously neglected facet of group decisions. Let us also mention that we base our argument on studies not only of collectives but also of individual behavior, as the latter shed light on the individual’s perspective when making the decision to join a group. We hope that the framework we propose to systematize the motives underlying collective decision-making will encourage researchers across disciplines to directly address the central question driving this investigation: Why do people voluntarily join collectives?

Decreased Responsibility in Groups

The thesis that individuals make collective decisions for sharing responsibility involves a prerequisite: that individuals feel less responsibility and relatedly, less agency, when they are in the group as compared to alone. But do they?

Diffusion of Responsibility in Groups

Early studies on diffusion of responsibility showed that people feel less responsible when performing an action as a group than when acting alone2935. These pioneering works demonstrated that when individual contributions are ambiguous and group members are not assigned particular roles (such as “leader”), attributions of responsibility follow a self-serving rule: individuals tend to claim more credit for successes (Figure 1b, credit) and avoid responsibility for failures3235. Research has shown that the decreased sense of responsibility in groups can promote adverse and undesirable behaviors36, such as free-riding1,3739, groupthink40, social loafing41, abstaining in elections42, inaction in emergency situations (known as the bystander effect 4345). Such behaviors may emerge because individuals in groups act as if they delegated responsibility and agency to others1,37. As these behaviors illustrate, the individual benefits of shared responsibility do not necessarily coincide with the collective good: while the individual ends up with a better outcome or avoids effortful actions, the collective outcome is hindered (less cooperation, worse decisions). In a similar way, the individual benefit of improving accuracy and rewards can be disconnected from the collective improvement of accuracy: Lorenz and colleagues46 found that the communication of opinions between members of a group reduces the diversity of opinion, rendering the collective opinion (i.e., the average of the individual opinions) less accurate. However, a reanalysis of the same data47 showed that individual participants’ accuracy and rewards were, on average, improved by converging towards the others’ opinion. The discrepancy shows how individual- and group-level outcomes may not converge48. Importantly, this divergence highlights how engaging in socially interactive, collective decision may prove useful for individuals without benefiting the group48.

Modulated Sense of Agency in Groups

The sense of agency is a subject of growing attention in cognitive science49. A person’s sense of agency49 refers to their perceived control over their actions and, ultimately, the world around them. It has been described as a “mental and neural state of cardinal importance in human civilization” that “underpins the concept of responsibility”49. Experimental evidence shows that a reduced feeling of responsibility is associated with a reduced sense of agency, offering further support for an intimate link between agency and responsibility50.

Previous studies suggest that acting in a group decreases the sense of individual agency and responsibility for the collective outcome. Even conditions such as merely being in the presence of another agent who does not causally contribute to the outcome51, receiving orders from others50, and performing actions with others52 decreases an individual’s sense of agency. By the same token, people report feeling less responsible for harming others if they are acting on orders50 and less responsible for probabilistic outcomes if they gamble collectively rather than individually53,54. In addition, acting in cooperation with others can foster a sense of joint agency via the emergence of a “we-mode,” which consists in a shift from self-agency to we-agency in collective actions52,5560. The literature on joint agency shows that entering this we-mode is context dependent: it depends on factors such as the structure and scale of a joint action55, the distribution of roles52,60, and the capacity to make joint predictions57. Consequently, individuals in a group may not always feel as if they are acting as a unified group and, by extension, as if they share responsibility. But even if individuals do not enter the we-mode during an action or decision, they can still retrospectively hold others in the group responsible for undesirable outcomes.

When it is Beneficial to Share Responsibility

When do people decide to join groups in order to share responsibility? This is not a trivial question, as being in a group commonly exacts the cost of giving up some autonomy—and people value their autonomy as, for instance, the following findings demonstrate. Humans seek it as a reward in its own right61, similar to food or mating opportunities. Even in rodents, autonomy fosters resilience62. Likewise, civil servants who have more control over their job are more resistant to ischemic heart disease63. Moreover, people seem to insist on making decisions for themselves even when this autonomy comes with emotional costs64,65. In contrast, research on delegation and advice seeking has shown that people prefer to give up their autonomy or parts of it when faced with difficult choices66,67. They do so by procrastinating6871, opting for the default option72,73, or delegating the choice to someone else67,74. Similarly, every time individuals join a group, they relinquish at least some of their autonomy.

So when and why do individuals give up some of their autonomy—along with its tangible and intangible benefits—to join collectives? Embedding oneself in a collective structure may be a good compromise between retaining full autonomy and thus responsibility (which, if the outcome is negative, could be very costly) and surrendering all autonomy, thereby renouncing responsibility. In other words, collective decisions preserve some autonomy while offering protection when things go awry and blame is apportioned.

Joining collectives to share responsibility—at the price of having less control—can be useful in the following two conditions. First, when individuals face choices whose outcomes are uncertain and potentially detrimental. Blowing the whistle on a powerful individual’s misconduct or investing in a new business are real-life examples of uncertainty-ridden choices that can have dramatic consequences. In many such cases, the consequences of solitary versus collective decisions can be asymmetric: a single negative report on a powerful individual’s behavior can destroy the whistleblower’s career and livelihood, whereas a cluster of such reports can validate the complaint, increase the chance of change, and reduce the risk of individual-specific retribution. In group decision making, individual members tend to defer risky decisions to other members of the group, a kind of responsibility aversion75. When faced with important decisions that run a high risk of errors, people voluntarily seek advice to share responsibility for their judgments76. More generally, descriptive norms (what most other people do or say they do77) can be used to justify choices retrospectively78. Descriptive norms allow decision makers to attribute some of the responsibility to others, thereby protecting themselves from the potential consequences of errors.

Second, it may make sense to join groups to share responsibility when the outcome of a decision is not uncertain, but rather when the momentous potential impact of the decision may have detrimental consequences for those who took it individually. For example, in the admittedly extreme case of execution by firing squad, the squad members are usually instructed to fire simultaneously, making impossible to know who fired the lethal shot and is, therefore, ultimately responsible for the condemned person’s death. Also, even when the outcome is predictable, the process of making the decision itself can be emotionally distressing, as in the case of end-of-life medical decisions made by surrogate decision makers79. Sharing responsibility for such decisions can be beneficial for individuals as it might help mitigate the associated distress. Indeed, people facing tragic choices, such as parents deciding whether to discontinue their baby’s life support, have a weakened desire for decision autonomy80; however, they hesitate to completely relinquish their option to choose. As suggested before, a collective decision could be a good way to combine conflicting objectives: sharing responsibility with others allows an individual to take less responsibility for the decision outcome without surrendering their autonomy altogether. In contrast with the decreased desire for autonomy for stressful choices80, other studies show that people prefer autonomy over delegation even if the final experience is more negative64,65. Interestingly, the latter studies examined consumers’ choices about food options, which involved little uncertainty or stress, and thus did not fall into either of the conditions we describe. This context-dependency of the preference to forgo autonomy reinforces our claim that people will choose to share responsibility only under specific conditions.

Our discussion of motives for engaging in collective decisions focuses on the perspective of the individual decision maker and does not consider how an outcome and its effects may or may not be shared between the individual and the collective. Various allocations are possible: (1) The outcome may affect only the individual, such as when an investor heeds the advice of an advisory panel; (2) the outcome may affect both the individual and the collective, such as when members of a family invest in a property together; and (3) the outcome may only affect the decision maker(s) indirectly by affecting their reputation, for example, such as when a group of doctors reach a decision about a patient’s diagnosis and treatment. Without wanting to underestimate the differences between these scenarios, we suggest that, from the individual’s point of view, they all represent situations in which being a member of a group decreases the individual responsibility for a decision’s outcome.

Why it is Beneficial to Share Responsibility

How does shared responsibility benefit individual group members in the conditions outlined in the previous section: (i) when outcomes are uncertain and potentially detrimental (ii) the decision process and/or the certain outcome are emotionally distressing? In the former condition, the costs of errors can be high. These costs may be psychological (e.g., regret) or material (e.g., loss of money or reputation); they can be self-imposed or imposed by others. Sharing responsibility in collective decisions can protect against these internal and external costs. In the latter condition, sharing responsibility can help mitigate this emotional toll. In all these cases, individual group members benefit from the collective structure independently of any potential improvements in outcome. This property constitutes the robust benefit of sharing responsibility in collective decision making. Dividing and distributing responsibility thus serves as a kind of an “insurance policy,” similar to diversification in risk management. In social animals, a comparable “insurance mechanism” is observable in the “dilution effect”: animals congregate in groups to protect themselves from predators, thus “diluting” the risk of being attacked81.

We discussed that individuals do indeed feel less responsibility and agency in a group setting. If the decision outcome is successful, the difficulty of responsibility attribution in a group structure allows individuals to claim credit for this outcome (Figure 1b, credit). We next turn to—admittedly circumstantial—evidence that suggests that people can reap tangible benefits from sharing responsibility in terms of attenuation of regret, punishment, and stress in the case of a negative outcome (Figure 1c).

Reducing Internal Self-Sanctioning

Regret is a common emotion that strongly influences decision making82. People experience regret when thinking about counterfactual, preferable outcomes that could have occurred had another choice been made83,84. Studies on the link between regret and responsibility suggest that regret is conditional on feeling responsible for an outcome85 and even that feeling responsible for a decision or an action is the “constitutive element of regret”86 (but see debate on this issue85,8789). The availability of counterfactual outcomes increases the individual sense of agency90, and the feeling of responsibility is conditional on an awareness that one could have decided differently91. Being part of a group distributes the responsibility for decision outcomes among more than one individual; consequently, the members of groups are likely to feel less regret than if they had made the same decision alone. In fact, subjective ratings of both responsibility and regret are lower in the wake of majority votes54. Moreover, people are prone to anticipate regret and do their best to avoid it by making regret-minimizing choices66,9295. Consistent with our thesis, anticipated regret leads people to delegate difficult decisions to others67, suggesting that making collective decisions may be one way to regulate and reduce both anticipated and experienced regret.

Reducing External Sanctioning

Formal and informal institutions of justice that enforce norms and punish violations of norms are crucial for individual and collective welfare. Humans are even willing to bear personal costs to punish others who violate norms96. Punishment can also be social, such as loss of reputation or ostracism. The Chinese government has even implemented a social credit system in which citizens’ behavior and trustworthiness is measured, and when found lacking on the governmental benchmarks results in a lowering of citizens’ scores97. A critical factor in determining whether an individual should be punished for an action is not only whether they were the agent of that action but also whether they were responsible for it91. There is evidence suggesting that responsibility deferral is a strong motive for delegation of a decision to another person as it protects against punishment98. The collective sharing of responsibility for a decision’s detrimental outcome is likely to result in collective punishment. Yet how a collective can be held responsible is a much debated question in moral philosophy, given that a collective lacks the psychological capacities attributed to an individual99. As long as the penalty for a collective act is distributed across agents, it is likely to be less severe than for a “solo offender” perpetrating the same act. The difficulty of determining who did what is also likely to attenuate punishment in a group. Identifying an individual’s personal contribution to a deed is essential in ensuring that crime and punishment are proportional, a cornerstone of any fair legal system100.

Although indirect, there is some evidence that collectives are held less responsible than individuals for harmful or unfair acts and therefore might be punished less harshly. For instance, people in a group display free-riding behaviors38,39, possibly because they think they are more likely to get away with it in a group than as individuals. A group is judged less responsible101 and punished less severely102 if it is perceived as consisting of a collection of distinct agents (low-cohesive group) than as a unified agent (high-cohesive group).

The “insurance policy” of becoming part of a group is, of course, not fail-safe. Whether or not responsibility is attributed to individuals in a group depends on several factors31,103107: the status of the individual (e.g., explicit leader)31,32,106, the contribution of the individual to both actual and counterfactual outcomes107, the order of contributions (e.g., whether the individual was the last person to act)103, and the extent to which contributions were pivotal105. If the group structure is sufficiently transparent, differential responsibility attributions are possible. In such cases, some or all of the protection bestowed by group membership is annulled. However, as long as a lack of transparency guarantees that there is “no soul to damn, no body to kick”108, responsibility and blame cannot be assigned to individuals.

The issue of how to hold a collective responsible for harmful acts is highly relevant to criminal justice. For example, proponents of the joint enterprise doctrine applied in England and Wales109,110 argue that any person involved in a crime, even if they did not actually commit it, is just as responsible as the person who did—and that they are to be punished just as severely. The heated discussion around this long-contested legal precedent highlights the fact that it is much harder to know who to blame when several people are involved. The problems inherent in attributing individual responsibility to members of a group, and the associated weakening of the deterrent function of potential punishment, may help to explain why collective protests sometimes culminate in unexpected levels of violence (e.g., France’s recent “yellow vest” protests111).

Mitigating Stress

Besides buffering against regret and punishment in situations where the outcome is uncertain, collective distribution of responsibility can be beneficial in situations where the outcome is predictable but emotionally distressing. For instance, it can help to mitigate the stress associated with thorny choices that require difficult trade-offs112 or result in tragic outcomes80. When faced with choices associated with grave risks, such as whether to prescribe a drug that could cause a fatal adverse reaction74, people will be more likely to procrastinate and defer responsibility to others if they are held accountable for their decision. Sharing responsibility in order to mitigate stress is therefore particularly relevant in the domain of medical decision making, when people need to make decisions on behalf of others. Examples include parents having to decide whether to discontinue life support for a terminally ill child80 or family member surrogates making treatment decisions for relatives incapacitated by life-threatening conditions113. In the case of end-of-life decisions, both patients and surrogates much prefer shared surrogate decision making among family members to other forms of decision making (with the sole exception of patient-designated surrogates)113,114. This finding is consistent with our hypothesis that shared responsibility can buffer against the psychological distress of making these difficult decisions by minimizing the burden of individual responsibility. It is also likely the reason why it has been suggested that pooling expert opinions on emergency situations (e.g., predicting the outbreak of a volcano) would not overburden a single expert with the responsibility for making a potentially highly consequential forecast115.

Conclusion

To date, research on collective decision making has focused primarily on the potential gains in accuracy that are obtained from collective (rather than individual) decisions. We believe that this focus has both diverted researchers from asking what motivates people to join groups in the first place and largely ignored other, more reliable and tangible, benefits of collective decision making. Drawing on evidence and concepts from psychology, behavioral economics, cognitive science, and philosophy of law, we suggest that individuals engage in collective decision making for at least two additional categories of motives: minimizing sanctioning and reducing emotional distress. First, they can share responsibility for uncertain and potentially detrimental outcomes, thus minimizing post-decisional regret (internal sanctioning) and punishment (external sanctioning). Second, they can share the emotional distress caused by the process of making grave decisions and experiencing their predictable outcomes.

Issues of regret, responsibility, and altruistic punishment are relevant across a wide range of societal domains, including medicine, law, and business. It remains an open and crucial question how different motives (e.g., pooling intelligence, sharing responsibility for negative outcomes, and social inclusion; Figure 1) interact in prompting people to engage in collective decision-making behaviors. We hope that recognizing the motives for collective decision making (beyond accuracy gains and obligatory collective decisions) will foster a more comprehensive understanding of the conditions under which collective decision making is preferable to individual decision making—in other words, that it will help to determine the ecological rationality of collective intelligence116.

Acknowledgments

M.E.Z. is supported by the Wellcome Trust (grant number 538149). B.B. was supported by a starting grant from the European Research Council (NEUROCODEC, 309865), the NOMIS Foundation and and the Humboldt Foundation. We would like to thank Susannah Goss and Deborah Ain for editing the manuscript.

Footnotes

Author contributions

M.E.Z., B.B and R.H wrote the perspective.

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

References

  • 1.Kameda T, Wisdom T, Toyokawa W, Inukai K. Is consensus-seeking unique to humans? A selective review of animal group decision-making and its implications for (human) social psychology. Group Process Intergroup Relat. 2012;15:673–689. [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Sumpter D, Krause J, James R, Couzin ID, Ward A. Consensus Decision Making by Fish. Curr Biol. 2008;22:1773–1777. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2008.09.064. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Surowiecki J. The Wisdom of Crowds: Why the Many Are Smarter Than the Few. Abacus. 2005 [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Sunstein CR, Hastie R. Wiser: Getting Beyond Groupthink to Make Groups Smarter. Harvard Business Press; 2015. [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Bahrami B, et al. What failure in collective decision-making tells us about metacognition. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2012;367:1350–1365. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2011.0420. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Bang D, Frith CD. Making better decisions in groups. R Soc Open Sci. 2017;4 doi: 10.1098/rsos.170193. 170193. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Koriat A. When Are Two Heads Better than One and Why? Science. 2012;336:360–362. doi: 10.1126/science.1216549. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Mahmoodi A, et al. Equality bias impairs collective decision-making across cultures. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2015;112:3835–3840. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1421692112. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Bahrami B, et al. Optimally Interacting Minds. Science. 2010;329:1081–1085. doi: 10.1126/science.1185718. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Kurvers RHJM, et al. Boosting medical diagnostics by pooling independent judgments. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2016;113:8777–8782. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1601827113. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Prelec D, Seung HS, McCoy J. A solution to the single-question crowd wisdom problem. Nature. 2017;541:532–535. doi: 10.1038/nature21054. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Navajas J, Niella T, Garbulsky G, Bahrami B, Sigman M. Aggregated knowledge from a small number of debates outperforms the wisdom of large crowds. Nat Hum Behav. 2018;2:126–132. [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Herzog SM, Litvinova A, Yahosseini KS, Tump AN, Kurvers RHJM. Hertwig R, Pleskac TJ, Pachur T, The Center for Adaptive Rationality . Taming uncertainty. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; The ecological rationality of the wisdom of crowds. (in press) [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Packer C, Ruttan L. The Evolution of Cooperative Hunting. Am Nat. 1988;132:159–198. [Google Scholar]
  • 15.LeFebvre R, Franke V. Culture Matters: Individualism vs. Collectivism in Conflict Decision-Making. Societies. 2013;3:128–146. [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Becker GS, Murphy KM. The Division of Labor, Coordination Costs, and Knowledge. Q J Econ. 1992;107:1137–1160. [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Battalio R, Samuelson L, Huyck JV. Optimization Incentives and Coordination Failure in Laboratory Stag Hunt Games. Econometrica. 2001;69:749–764. [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Toelch U, Dolan RJ. Informational and Normative Influences in Conformity from a Neurocomputational Perspective. Trends Cogn Sci. 2015;19:579–589. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Tyler TR. Why People Cooperate: The Role of Social Motivations. Princeton University Press; 2011. [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Hoppitt W, Laland KN. Social Learning: An Introduction to Mechanisms, Methods, and Models. Princeton University Press; 2013. [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Heyes C. What’s social about social learning? J Comp Psychol Wash DC 1983. 2012;126:193–202. doi: 10.1037/a0025180. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Galton F. Vox Populi. Nature. 1907;75:450–451. [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Mercier H, Trouche E, Yama H, Heintz C, Girotto V. Experts and laymen grossly underestimate the benefits of argumentation for reasoning. Think Reason. 2015;21:341–355. [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Pfeiffer UJ, et al. Why we interact: On the functional role of the striatum in the subjective experience of social interaction. NeuroImage. 2014;101:124–137. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.06.061. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Tajfel H, Turner JC. The Social Identity Theory of Intergroup Behavior. Psychology Press; 2004. [Google Scholar]
  • 26.Robbins JM, Krueger JI. Social Projection to Ingroups and Outgroups: A Review and Meta-Analysis. Personal Soc Psychol Rev. 2005;9:32–47. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr0901_3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Stevens M, et al. Leaders promote attendance in sport and exercise sessions by fostering social identity. Scand J Med Sci Sports. 2018 doi: 10.1111/sms.13217. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Tyler TR. APA handbook of personality and social psychology, Volume 2: Group processes. American Psychological Association; 2015. Social justice; pp. 95–122. [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Darley JM, Latane B. Bystander intervention in emergencies: Diffusion of responsibility. J Pers Soc Psychol. 1968;8:377–383. doi: 10.1037/h0025589. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Guerin B. The Encyclopedia of Peace Psychology. Blackwell Publishing Ltd; 2011. Diffusion of Responsibility. [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Forsyth DR, Zyzniewski LE, Giammanco CA. Responsibility Diffusion in Cooperative Collectives. Pers Soc Psychol Bull. 2002;28:54–65. [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Caine BT, Schlenker BR. Role Position and Group Performance as Determinants of Egotistical Perceptions in Cooperative Groups. J Psychol. 1979;101:149–156. [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Forsyth DR, Schlenker BR. Attributing the causes of group performance: Effects of performance quality, task importance, and future testing. J Pers. 1977;45:220–236. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-6494.1977.tb00148.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Leary MR, Forsyth DR. Group processes. Sage Publications, Inc; 1987. Attributions of responsibility for collective endeavors; pp. 167–188. [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Miller RS, Schlenker BR. Egotism in Group Members: Public and Private Attributions of Responsibility for Group Performance. Soc Psychol Q. 1985;48:85–89. [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Baumeister RF, Ainsworth SE, Vohs KD. Are groups more or less than the sum of their members? The moderating role of individual identification. Behav Brain Sci. 2016;39 doi: 10.1017/S0140525X15000618. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Feng C, et al. Diffusion of responsibility attenuates altruistic punishment: A functional magnetic resonance imaging effective connectivity study. Hum Brain Mapp. 2016;37:663–677. doi: 10.1002/hbm.23057. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38.Morgan PM, Tindale RS. Group vs Individual Performance in Mixed-Motive Situations: Exploring an Inconsistency. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 2002;87:44–65. [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Wildschut T, Pinter B, Vevea JL, Insko CA, Schopler J. Beyond the group mind: a quantitative review of the interindividual-intergroup discontinuity effect. Psychol Bull. 2003;129:698–722. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.129.5.698. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Turner ME, Pratkanis AR. Twenty-Five Years of Groupthink Theory and Research: Lessons from the Evaluation of a Theory. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1998;73:105–115. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1998.2756. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Simms A, Nichols T. Social Loafing: A Review of the Literature. J Manag Policy Pract. 2014;15:58–67. [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Levine DK, Palfrey TR. The Paradox of Voter Participation? A Laboratory Study. Am Polit Sci Rev. 2007;101:143–158. [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Hortensius R, de Gelder B. The neural basis of the bystander effect — The influence of group size on neural activity when witnessing an emergency. NeuroImage. 2014;93:53–58. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.02.025. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.Fischer P, et al. The bystander-effect: a meta-analytic review on bystander intervention in dangerous and non-dangerous emergencies. Psychol Bull. 2011;137:517–537. doi: 10.1037/a0023304. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Martin KK, North AC. Diffusion of responsibility on social networking sites. Comput Hum Behav. 2015;44:124–131. [Google Scholar]
  • 46.Lorenz J, Rauhut H, Schweitzer F, Helbing D. How social influence can undermine the wisdom of crowd effect. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2011;108:9020–9025. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1008636108. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Farrell S. Social influence benefits the wisdom of individuals in the crowd. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2011;108:E625–E625. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1109947108. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Rauhut H, Lorenz J, Schweitzer F, Helbing D. Reply to Farrell: Improved individual estimation success can imply collective tunnel vision. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2011;108:E626–E626. [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Haggard P. Sense of agency in the human brain. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2017;18:196–207. doi: 10.1038/nrn.2017.14. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Caspar EA, Christensen JF, Cleeremans A, Haggard P. Coercion Changes the Sense of Agency in the Human Brain. Curr Biol. 2016;26:585–592. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2015.12.067. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Beyer F, Sidarus N, Bonicalzi S, Haggard P. Beyond self-serving bias: diffusion of responsibility reduces sense of agency and outcome monitoring. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci. 2016;2:138–145. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsw160. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Dewey JA, Pacherie E, Knoblich G. The phenomenology of controlling a moving object with another person. Cognition. 2014;132:383–397. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2014.05.002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53.Li P, et al. The influence of the diffusion of responsibility effect on outcome evaluations: electrophysiological evidence from an ERP study. NeuroImage. 2010;52:1727–1733. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.04.275. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54.Nicolle A, Bach DR, Frith C, Dolan RJ. Amygdala involvement in self-blame regret. Soc Neurosci. 2011;6:178–189. doi: 10.1080/17470919.2010.506128. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Pacherie E. Intentional joint agency: shared intention lite. Synthese. 2013;190:1817–1839. [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Pacherie E. How does it feel to act together? Phenomenol Cogn Sci. 2014;13:25–46. [Google Scholar]
  • 57.Gallotti M, Frith CD. Social cognition in the we-mode. Trends Cogn Sci. 2013;17:160–165. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2013.02.002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58.Obhi SS, Hall P. Sense of agency and intentional binding in joint action. Exp Brain Res. 2011;211:655. doi: 10.1007/s00221-011-2675-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59.van der Wel RPRD, Sebanz N, Knoblich G. The sense of agency during skill learning in individuals and dyads. Conscious Cogn. 2012;21:1267–1279. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2012.04.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 60.van der Wel RPRD. Me and we: Metacognition and performance evaluation of joint actions. Cognition. 2015;140:49–59. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2015.03.011. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61.Murayama K, et al. How Self-Determined Choice Facilitates Performance: A Key Role of the Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex. Cereb Cortex. 2015;25:1241–1251. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bht317. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 62.Dworkin SI, Mirkis S, Smith JE. Response-dependent versus response-independent presentation of cocaine: differences in the lethal effects of the drug. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 1995;117:262–266. doi: 10.1007/BF02246100. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 63.Marmot MG, Bosma H, Hemingway H, Brunner E, Stansfeld S. Contribution of job control and other risk factors to social variations in coronary heart disease incidence. Lancet Lond Engl. 1997;350:235–239. doi: 10.1016/s0140-6736(97)04244-x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 64.Botti S, Lyengar SS. The psychological pleasure and pain of choosing: when people prefer choosing at the cost of subsequent outcome satisfaction. J Pers Soc Psychol. 2004;87:312–326. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.87.3.312. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 65.Botti S, McGill AL. When Choosing Is Not Deciding: The Effect of Perceived Responsibility on Satisfaction. J Consum Res. 2006;33:211–219. [Google Scholar]
  • 66.Anderson CJ. The psychology of doing nothing: forms of decision avoidance result from reason and emotion. Psychol Bull. 2003;129:139–167. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.129.1.139. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 67.Steffel M, Williams EF, Morwitz V, Morales A. Delegating Decisions: Recruiting Others to Make Choices We Might Regret. J Consum Res. 2018;44:1015–1032. [Google Scholar]
  • 68.Dhar R. The Effect of Decision Strategy on Deciding to Defer Choice. J Behav Decis Mak. 1996;9:265–281. [Google Scholar]
  • 69.Tversky A, Shafir E. Choice under Conflict: The Dynamics of Deferred Decision. Psychol Sci. 1992;3:358–361. [Google Scholar]
  • 70.Novemsky N, Dhar R, Schwarz N, Simonson I. Preference fluency in choice. J Mark Res. 2007;44:347–356. [Google Scholar]
  • 71.Dhar R, Nowlis SM. The effect of time pressure on consumer choice deferral. J Consum Res. 1999;25:369–384. [Google Scholar]
  • 72.Luce MF. Choosing to Avoid: Coping with negatively emotion-laden consumer decisions. J Consum Res. 1998;24:409–433. [Google Scholar]
  • 73.Redelmeier DA, Shafir E. Medical decision making in situations that offer multiple alternatives. JAMA. 1995;273:302–305. doi: 10.1001/jama.1995.03520280048038. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 74.Tetlock PE, Boettger R. Accountability amplifies the status quo effect when change creates victims. J Behav Decis Mak. 1994;7:1–23. [Google Scholar]
  • 75.Edelson MG, Polania R, Ruff CC, Fehr E, Hare TA. Computational and neurobiological foundations of leadership decisions. Science. 2018;361 doi: 10.1126/science.aat0036. eaat0036. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 76.Harvey N, Fischer I. Taking Advice: Accepting Help, Improving Judgment, and Sharing Responsibility. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1997;70:117–133. [Google Scholar]
  • 77.Kallgren Carl A, Reno Raymond R, Cialdini Robert B. A Focus Theory of Normative Conduct: When Norms Do and Do not Affect Behavior. Pers Soc Psychol Bull. 2000;26:1002–1012. [Google Scholar]
  • 78.Mercier H, Sperber D. The Enigma of Reason. Harvard University Press; 2017. [Google Scholar]
  • 79.Vig EK, Starks H, Taylor JS, Hopley EK, Fryer-Edwards K. Surviving surrogate decision-making: what helps and hampers the experience of making medical decisions for others. J Gen Intern Med. 2007;22:1274–1279. doi: 10.1007/s11606-007-0252-y. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 80.Botti S, Orfali K, Iyengar SS. Tragic Choices: Autonomy and Emotional Responses to Medical Decisions. J Consum Res. 2009;36:337–352. [Google Scholar]
  • 81.Lehtonen J, Jaatinen K. Safety in numbers: the dilution effect and other drivers of group life in the face of danger. Behav Ecol Sociobiol. 2016;70:449–458. [Google Scholar]
  • 82.Connolly T, Zeelenberg M. Regret in Decision Making. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2002;11:212–216. [Google Scholar]
  • 83.Frith CD, Metzinger TK. What’s the use of consciousness? How the stab of conscience made us really conscious (2016) In: Engel AK, et al., editors. The Pragmatic Turn: Toward Action-Oriented Views in Cognitive Science. MIT Press; 2016. [Google Scholar]
  • 84.Gilovich T, Medvec VH. The experience of regret: what, when, and why. Psychol Rev. 1995;102:379–395. doi: 10.1037/0033-295x.102.2.379. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 85.Zeelenberg M, van Dijk WW, Manstead ASR. Regret and Responsibility Resolved? Evaluating Ordóñez and Connolly’s (2000) Conclusions. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 2000;81:143–154. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1999.2865. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 86.Bourgeois-Gironde S. Chapters. Edward Elgar Publishing; 2017. How regret moves individual and collective choices towards rationality; pp. 188–204. [Google Scholar]
  • 87.Connolly T, Ordóñez LD, Coughlan R. Regret and Responsibility in the Evaluation of Decision Outcomes. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1997;70:73–85. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1997.2695. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 88.Ordóñez LD, Connolly T. Regret and Responsibility: A Reply to Zeelenberg et al. (1998) Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 2000;81:132–142. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1999.2834. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 89.Zeelenberg M, van Dijk WW, Manstead ASR. Reconsidering the Relation between Regret and Responsibility. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1998;74:254–272. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1998.2780. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 90.Kulakova E, Khalighinejad N, Haggard P. I could have done otherwise: Availability of counterfactual comparisons informs the sense of agency. Conscious Cogn. 2017;49:237–244. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2017.01.013. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 91.Frith CD. Action, agency and responsibility. Neuropsychologia. 2014;55:137–142. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.09.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 92.Camille N, et al. The involvement of the orbitofrontal cortex in the experience of regret. Science. 2004;304:1167–1170. doi: 10.1126/science.1094550. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 93.Coricelli G, et al. Regret and its avoidance: a neuroimaging study of choice behavior. Nat Neurosci. 2005;8:1255–1262. doi: 10.1038/nn1514. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 94.Zeelenberg M, Beattie J, van der Pligt J, de Vries NK. Consequences of Regret Aversion: Effects of Expected Feedback on Risky Decision Making. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1996;65:148–158. [Google Scholar]
  • 95.Zeelenberg M, Beattie J. Consequences of Regret Aversion 2: Additional Evidence for Effects of Feedback on Decision Making. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process. 1997;72:63–78. [Google Scholar]
  • 96.Fehr E, Fischbacher U. Third-party punishment and social norms. Evol Hum Behav. 2004;25:63–87. [Google Scholar]
  • 97.Dai X. Toward a Reputation State: The Social Credit System Project of China. Social Science Research Network. 2018 Available at SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3193577. [Google Scholar]
  • 98.Bartling B, Fischbacher U. Shifting the Blame: On Delegation and Responsibility. Rev Econ Stud. 2012;79:67–87. [Google Scholar]
  • 99.Williams G. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Responsibility. ISSN 2161-0002. Available: http://www.iep.utm.edu/responsi/ [Google Scholar]
  • 100.Edwards J. Theories of Criminal Law. In: Edward NZ, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab; Stanford University: 2018. [Google Scholar]
  • 101.Waytz A, Young L. The Group-Member Mind Trade-Off: Attributing Mind to Groups Versus Group Members. Psychol Sci. 2012;23:77–85. doi: 10.1177/0956797611423546. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 102.Newheiser A-K, Sawaoka T, Dovidio JF. Why do we punish groups? High entitativity promotes moral suspicion. J Exp Soc Psychol. 2012;48:931–936. [Google Scholar]
  • 103.Gerstenberg T, Lagnado DA. When contributions make a difference: explaining order effects in responsibility attribution. Psychon Bull Rev. 2012;19:729–736. doi: 10.3758/s13423-012-0256-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 104.Zultan R, Gerstenberg T, Lagnado DA. Finding fault: Causality and counterfactuals in group attributions. Cognition. 2012;125:429–440. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2012.07.014. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 105.Lagnado DA, Gerstenberg T, Zultan R. Causal responsibility and counterfactuals. Cogn Sci. 2013;37:1036–1073. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12054. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 106.Duch R, Stevenson R, Przepiorka W. Responsibility Attribution for Collective Decision Makers. Am J Polit Sci. 2011;59 [Google Scholar]
  • 107.Gerstenberg T, Lagnado DA. Attributing responsibility: Actual and counterfactual worlds (2014) In: Knobe J, Lombrozo T, Nichols S, editors. Oxford Studies of Experimental Philosophy. Oxford University Press; 2014. pp. 91–130. [Google Scholar]
  • 108.Coffee JC. “No Soul to Damn: No Body to Kick”: An Unscandalized Inquiry into the Problem of Corporate Punishment. Michigan Law Review. 1981;79(3):386–4. [Google Scholar]
  • 109.Ohlin JD. Three Conceptual Problems with the Doctrine of Joint Criminal Enterprise. J Int Crim Justice. 2007;5:69–90. [Google Scholar]
  • 110.Jacobson J, et al. Joint enterprise: Righting a wrong turn? Prison Reform Trust. 2016 [Google Scholar]
  • 111.Grossman E. France’s Yellow Vests – Symptom of a Chronic Disease. Political Insight. 2019;10:30–34. [Google Scholar]
  • 112.Hogarth RM. What’s a “Good” Decision? Issues in Assessing Procedural and Ecological Quality. In: Keren G, Wu G, editors. The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd; 2015. pp. 952–972. [Google Scholar]
  • 113.Frey R, Hertwig R, Herzog SM. Surrogate Decision Making Do We Have to Trade Off Accuracy and Procedural Satisfaction? Med Decis Making. 2014;34:258–269. doi: 10.1177/0272989X12471729. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 114.Frey R, Herzog SM, Hertwig R. Deciding on behalf of others: a population survey on procedural preferences for surrogate decision-making. BMJ Open. 2018;8:e022289. doi: 10.1136/bmjopen-2018-022289. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 115.Aspinall W. A route to more tractable expert advice. Nature. 2010;463:294–295. doi: 10.1038/463294a. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 116.Hertwig R, Pleskac TJ, Pachur T, the Center for Adaptive Rationality . Taming uncertainty. Cambridge: MIT Press; (in press) [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES