Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2019 Sep 22.
Published in final edited form as: Genet Med. 2019 Mar 21;21(10):2190–2198. doi: 10.1038/s41436-019-0483-4

Rethinking the “Open Future” Argument against Predictive Genetic Testing of Children

Jeremy R Garrett a,b, John D Lantos a,b, Leslie G Biesecker c, Janet E Childerhose d, Wendy K Chung e, Ingrid A Holm f, Barbara A Koenig g, Jean E McEwen c, Benjamin S Wilfond h,i, Kyle Brothers j, Clinical Sequencing Exploratory Research (CSER) Consortium Pediatrics Working Group
PMCID: PMC6754817  NIHMSID: NIHMS1525469  PMID: 30894702

Abstract

Professional consensus has traditionally discouraged predictive genetic testing when no childhood interventions can reduce future morbidity or mortality. However, advances in genome sequencing and accumulating evidence that children and families cope adequately with predictive genetic information have weakened this consensus. The primary argument remaining against testing appeals to children’s “right to an open future.” It claims that the autonomy of the future adult is violated when others make an irreversible choice to obtain or disclose predictive genetic information during childhood. We evaluate this argument and conclude that children’s interest in an open future should not be understood as a right. Rather an open future is one significant interest to weigh against other important interests when evaluating decisions. Thus, predictive genetic testing is ethically permissible in principle, as long as the interests promoted outweigh potential harms. We conclude by offering an expanded model of children’s interests that might be considered in such circumstances, and present two case analyses to illustrate how this framework better guides decisions about predictive genetic testing in pediatrics.

Keywords: Adult-onset conditions, children’s interests, pediatric genetic testing, right to an open future, secondary findings

Introduction

For more than two decades, professional consensus has discouraged predictive genetic testing of children for adult-onset conditions (hereafter, predictive genetic testing) when no interventions in childhood might reduce morbidity or mortality.18 More recently, this position has been extended to discourage disclosure of results produced by genome sequencing performed for other purposes. These professional recommendations are now being questioned. The ethical framework originally developed for single-gene testing requires re-evaluation given the ready availability of genome sequencing and the wealth of information it produces. Unlike single-gene testing, the use of genome sequencing to answer a clinical question can generate hundreds or even thousands of genetic findings. Many of these findings would not alter the care of the patient, and most fall well outside the indication for a test. Genome sequencing also has spurred studies of the psychosocial impacts of genetic information on pediatric patients and families that has deepened our understanding of those impacts. The time is ripe to re-examine the prevailing wisdom on this matter.

Historically, two primary ethical arguments have underpinned the consensus against predictive genetic testing in the position statements of leading professional societies.18 One is empirically-grounded and focused on the consequences of the decision. It warns of potential psychosocial harms resulting from children or parents learning about future risks for adult-onset conditions. However, accumulating evidence indicates such psychosocial harms are less common and less impactful than originally feared. Although important work is still ongoing, these preliminary data have begun to reduce concerns about the presumed psychological harms of this information.9,10

The second argument focuses on the special moral status of children as future adults. It invokes children’s “right to an open future,” which purportedly is violated when irreversible choices are made for them during childhood. Numerous literature reviews and qualitative surveys indicate that this argument is perhaps the most frequently cited objection to predictive genetic testing among clinicians and bioethicists.1114 Moreover, unlike the concern about immediate psychosocial harms, the violation of a moral right is a value claim that cannot be refuted by empirical evidence.13 Hence, this argument against predictive genetic testing likely will become even more important as the evidence base develops and shifts.

Given this evolution in justification for restricting predictive genetic testing, it is imperative to evaluate critically the conceptual basis for the right to an open future. We undertake this task by analyzing the concept of an open future and the nature of moral rights, both in theory and in the context of two clinical case scenarios. We argue that children’s interest in an open future can be protected adequately without imposing a strict ethical obligation to refrain from infringing that interest (i.e., a right). Rather, an open future should be regarded as one significant interest to weigh against other important interests when determining whether testing or disclosure would provide more benefits than harm.15 Considered this way, predictive genetic testing is ethically permissible in principle, as long as multiple important interests are considered and balanced. We conclude that this shift in ethical frameworks better guides decision-making about both genome sequencing and standard single-gene testing for children.

Historical Background

The philosopher Joel Feinberg is generally credited with coining the phrase, “the child’s right to an open future.” He did so in the context of a legal case, Wisconsin v. Yoder,16 which considered whether Amish communities should be exempted from compulsory school attendance laws.17 In his argument, Feinberg highlighted a category of rights held primarily by children – so-called “rights-in-trust,” which “look like adult autonomy rights” but cannot yet be exercised in childhood.17 Describing this class of rights further, Feinberg stated:

When sophisticated autonomy rights are attributed to children who are clearly not yet capable of exercising them, their names refer to rights that are to be saved for the child until he is an adult, but which can be violated “in advance,” so to speak, before the child is even in a position to exercise them… His right while he is still a child is to have these future options kept open until he is a fully formed, self-determining adult capable of deciding among them.17

For Feinberg, the Amish violated the rights-in-trust of the children whose formal education was cut short. He argued that this practice left children prepared for few careers or lifestyles outside of an Amish farm and, thus, curtailed many potentially desirable future options. Importantly, this argument did not carry the day in Yoder. The court decided in favor of the Amish. Nonetheless, the right to an open future took hold in numerous ethical contexts.1846

The consensus against predictive genetic testing based on this right took shape in the early to mid-1990s.47,48 Within the roughly twenty-year period that followed, the right to an open future became prominently ensconced in the official position statements of many leading professional societies around the world49 (Table 1). This restrictive consensus was endorsed and reinforced in the work of bioethicists as well. For example, Dena Davis, in both the 2001 and 2010 editions of her influential book, Genetic Dilemmas, argues that “[predictive genetic testing] is a decision each individual can make only for herself. Thus respect for the child’s right to an open future supports the growing consensus in the United States against allowing parents to choose such testing for their children.”20 This interpretation of the right to an open future has, in turn, shaped many arguments against predictive genetic testing in the medical and bioethics literature and in clinical settings over the past two decades.11,14,35,36,5058 For example, in a 2017 article written for an audience of genetic counselors, Fenwick and colleagues summarize the status quo as follows: “The recommendations from these guidelines are well-established and have not changed significantly over time. Their primary message is that unless testing has current medical benefit, it should be deferred until a child is old enough to make her/his own decision protecting what Feinberg called the child’s right to an open future.”14

Table 1.

Selected official position statements by leading professional societies restricting predictive genetic testing by appealing to the child’s future autonomy or right to an open future.

Professional Society Years Active Relevant Section
U.K. Clinical Genetics Society 1994–2010 The principle of “respect for autonomy” entails that “formal genetic testing should generally wait until the ‘children’ request such tests for themselves, as autonomous adults.2
American Society for Human Genetics & American College of Medical Genetics 1995–2015 “If the medical or psychosocial benefits of a genetic test will not accrue until adulthood, as in the case of carrier status or adult-onset diseases, genetic testing generally should be deferred…[with exceptions limited to adolescents who meet standards of competence, voluntariness, and adequate understanding of information]…The unique potential of presymptomatic genetic testing to predict a child’s future should be approached with great caution.”3
American Academy of Pediatrics 2001–2013 Predictive genetic testing “inappropriately eliminates the possibility of future autonomous choice by the person”; thus, “pediatricians should decline requests from parents or guardians …until the child has the capacity to make the choice.”4
Canadian Paediatric Society 2003-Present There is a “basic right for an individual to decide whether one wants genetic testing that will reveal genetic information…For genetic conditions that will not present until adulthood (susceptibility or predictive testing), testing should be deferred until the child is competent to decide whether they want the information.”5
European Society for Human Genetics 2009-Present “Presymptomatic and predictive genetic testing of minors for conditions with adult-onset is acceptable only if preventive actions (eg preventive surgery or early detection aimed at therapeutic interventions) can be initiated before adulthood. Otherwise presymptomatic and predictive genetic testing in minors for adult-onset disorders should be deferred until the person has the maturity and competence to understand the nature of the decision and its implications.”6
National Society of Genetic Counselors 2012-Present “[NSGC] encourages deferring predictive genetic testing of minors for adult-onset conditions when results will not impact childhood medical management or significantly benefit the child. Predictive testing should optimally be deferred until the individual has the capacity to weigh the associated risks, benefits, and limitations of this information, taking his/her circumstances, preferences, and beliefs into account to preserve his/her autonomy and right to an open future.”7
Human Genetics Society of Australasia 2014-Present “Pre-symptomatic and predictive testing in children and young people who cannot yet make a mature decision about testing removes the possibility for them to make an autonomous decision as an adult. It is for this reason that it is recommended that pre-symptomatic and predictive testing be limited to individuals assessed to have sufficient maturity to make an informed decision about testing.”8

Conceptual and Ethical Analysis

While the right to an open future has influenced pediatric bioethics significantly, we believe it is a principle that is apt to sow confusion and ambiguity rather than clarity.

First, what it means for a child’s future to be “open” or “closed” is not intuitively clear. Must future options be permanently inaccessible in order to be considered “closed”? Or is it sufficient that certain options are simply more difficult to access? Few decisions made during childhood permanently foreclose some future possibility. However, many decisions (including many standard parenting decisions) make certain futures more or less difficult to realize. It is, to take Feinberg’s example, not literally impossible for Amish youth with abbreviated formal education to realize futures outside their community farm.59 Indeed, a small proportion demonstrate this following their period of Rumspringa (the rite of passage for Amish teenagers preceding the choice between baptism within and separation from the Amish church), by deciding to leave the community and begin a new life. This first ambiguity, then, has real significance. If “closing” a child’s future requires making some future state of affairs literally impossible, then the right to an open future will have few applications within pediatrics or parenting more broadly. But if closing a child’s future refers to any decision that makes certain futures significantly more difficult, then this right will apply too widely, prohibiting many ordinary and even unavoidable parenting practices.60

A second ambiguity arises regarding what the right to an open future is intended to protect precisely. We might view this right as requiring fiduciaries to ensure children have the fundamental resources to make decisions as adults. This could include basic capacities like the ability to reason from means to ends, as well as basic preferences, since adult decision-making requires mature desires and values.61 Alternatively, we might determine specific skills, like learning a second language, to be vital to an open future.61 Finally, we might instead focus on preserving specific options and opportunities, like becoming an Amish farmer or attending college.61 Here again the choice of target matters. If the right to an open future merely requires preserving and developing children’s basic capacities, then few medical decisions, including predictive genetic testing, will seriously threaten this right. However, if the right forbids foreclosing specific options and opportunities, then it will be far too strong, implying that parents routinely violate their children’s open future by encouraging certain opportunities and discouraging others.

A third ambiguity relates to whether we should understand an open future quantitatively or qualitatively. Defenders of the right to an open future sometimes speak as if children have the right to “reach maturity with as many open options, opportunities, and advantages as possible”17 and at other times as merely the right to reach maturity without a “radical narrowing”18 of their options, opportunities, and advantages. However, defenders also sometimes focus less on the quantity of choices and more on their quality, entailing a right for children to reach maturity with certain vital options, opportunities, and advantages left open. Here again the choice of interpretation has important implications. A maximal ideal seems impossible to satisfy; parents make future-effecting choices for their children every day and cannot avoid doing so. A minimal threshold, on the other hand, is more defensible on its face, but also less relevant to pediatrics: few single decisions made for children, including predictive genetic testing, “radically narrow” their future. Focusing on the moral quality of specific choices seems more promising, but leaves us with the task of determining, in a non-arbitrary manner, which choices are vital to the adults whom children will become. And even there it is unclear whether parents can, or should, avoid shaping such choices for their children, especially when doing so serves other important interests.6264

Within the context of predictive genetic testing, these questions generate significant ambiguity. Obviously, any decision made for children in this context (to pursue testing or not) will affect their future. These decisions may even permanently close off certain options. Disclosing information about future risk does rule out the recipient not knowing that information. However, delaying testing/disclosure until adulthood is also a decision made for the child in childhood. Moreover, this decision to defer may close off important opportunities. We should emphasize that many test results alleviate anxiety and uncertainty, inform planning for a future health condition, enable children to begin—while in a stable and supportive environment—incorporating information into their developing identity and autonomy, or live out a limited lifespan in a way that prioritizes and maximizes what matters most to the child (i.e., meaningful time with family and friends, personal adventures, spiritual/religious pursuits, advocacy for political change or medical progress, and so on).53,63,64 Either way, a decision must be made for the child in childhood and each opens some future options and closes others.63,65,66

In light of these concerns, it seems inappropriate for health professionals to appeal to a “right” to an open future in order to encourage some decisions about predictive genetic testing, while fervently discouraging others. The right to an open future is traditionally regarded as a “negative claim-right.”67 Within our common morality, negative claim-rights constitute the strongest ethical constraint on the actions of others.68 This type of right protects an interest—in this case, the interest in having decisions deferred to make for and by one’s future self—by placing all moral agents, including parents and clinicians, under a strict obligation to refrain from infringing that interest.67 Violations of a negative moral right are permitted rarely and only under strict conditions. The 1994 Institute of Medicine report, Assessing Genetic Risks, proposes four conditions that would need to be met in order to justifiably override an individual’s autonomy in the context of predictive genetic testing (Table 2).1 Crucially, all four of these conditions will be met only in very rare circumstances. To assert that children have a negative moral “right” against such testing in childhood is to make a forceful moral claim, one that will override all other interests in nearly all realistic circumstances.

Table 2.

Proposed set of four conditions necessary to justify the breach of an autonomy-based right such as the child’s right to an open future.1

1. The action must be aimed at an important goal—such as the protection of others from serious harm—that outweighs the value of autonomy…in the particular instance.
2. [The action] must have a high probability of realizing that goal.
3. There must be no acceptable alternatives that can also realize the goal without breaching those principles.
4. The degree of infringement of the principle must be the minimum necessary to realize the goal.

Even setting aside these more theoretical concerns, the vast potential for misinterpretation and misuse by itself provides sufficient reason to refrain from rights language here. In our experience, many practicing clinicians and scientists have felt compelled to adopt the right to an open future but lack a nuanced understanding of the concept; for them, it is no more permissible to violate this “right” than to violate a child’s right to life or bodily integrity. Indeed, in at least two significant cases, recent updates to professional guidelines noted that many clinicians have interpreted prior guidance as more prohibitive of predictive genetic testing than was intended or explicitly stated.69,70 A significant factor contributing to this widespread misinterpretation is precisely the way in which concerns about the open future became ensconced within the language of rights.

Fortunately, the ethical construct of a “right” is unnecessary to identify and adequately protect the primary concern here – the child’s interest in an open future. Children are more likely, in general, to flourish when certain future options are left open. Most parents understand this. The notion that children have interests in an open future fits well with standard ethical guidance in pediatric bioethics.71 The child’s interest in an open future is one important, but not automatically the most important, interest to consider and balance in the process of shared decision-making.63 In other words, an open future is best understood not as a separate principle of pediatric bioethics, but instead as one component of its traditional focus on interests and balancing benefits and harms to children and families.62,72,73 There is a robust literature on the interests of children in pediatric ethics. While a comprehensive examination of this literature is beyond the scope of this paper, examining one promising account of children’s interests helps demonstrate how an open future interest can be weighed alongside other interests. This account, developed in 2009 by Malek74, utilizes extant statements about children’s needs and interests to propose a list of thirteen important interests that should be considered in pediatric decision-making (Table 3). Each interest is a capacity, activity, or state of affairs that contributes to the well-being of children, and most medical decisions will involve some tradeoffs among these interests. While an interest in an open future is not explicitly included in Malek’s list, we propose that it should be added, perhaps as one component of the interest in autonomy – i.e. an interest in preserving future autonomy.

Table 3.

Proposed list of interests that should be evaluated when making decisions for children (adapted from Malek74)

# Proposed interest
1 Life: To live and to anticipate a life of normal human length.
2 Health and healthcare: To have good health and protection from pain, injury, and illness. To have access to medical care.
3 Basic needs: To have an adequate standard of living, especially to be adequately nourished and sheltered.
4 Protection from neglect and abuse: To be protected from physical or mental abuse, neglect, exploitation, and exposure to dangerous environments. To be secure that they will be safe and cared for.
5 Emotional development: To experience emotion and have appropriate emotional development.
6 Play and pleasure: To play, rest, and enjoy recreational activities. To have pleasurable experiences.
7 Education and cognitive development: To have an education that includes information from diverse sources. To have the ability to learn, think, imagine, and reason.
8 Expression and communication: To have the ability to express themselves and to communicate thoughts and feelings.
9 Interaction: To interact with and care for others and the world around them. To have secure, empathetic, intimate, and consistent relationships with others.
10 Parental relationship: To know and interact with their parents.
11 Identity: To have an identity and connection to their culture. To be protected from discrimination.
12 Sense of self: To have a sense of self, self-worth, and self-respect.
13 Autonomy: To have the ability to influence the course of their lives. To act intentionally and with self discipline. To reflect on the direction and meaning of their lives. To have “future autonomy” protected by having future options and opportunities kept open.

A nuanced interest-based framework like this better serves pediatric clinical ethics than a rights-based approach for two important reasons (Table 4). First, unlike a rights-based approach, an interest-based framework is not rigidly committed to a predetermined conclusion and can nimbly incorporate and respond to an ever-evolving evidence base. Second, it enables a comprehensive and systematic, but also flexible and balanced, assessment of children’s many diverse interests. In particular, this framework facilitates better decisions about whether the full range of interests for any particular child are promoted more by opening or closing certain futures. The interest in preserving future autonomy is weighed alongside other interests identified by Malek, potentially supporting different conclusions in different circumstances. Foreclosing the opportunity to make certain choices later may promote a child’s overall interests in some circumstances. For example, many parental and pediatric decisions–like disclosing to an 11-year-old child that he was adopted or removing an infant’s supernumerary digit—could be delayed until the child reaches adulthood. However, while such delays might preserve one particular opportunity for autonomous choice, foreclosing those later decisions and proceeding with disclosure or surgery now will often open other opportunities that better serve the child’s overall interests.64 In other circumstances, though, producing or preserving openness may be most compelling. Decisions like career choice are frequently viewed this way: parents typically take measures to keep their child’s future career options open, even though it might serve other interests to radically narrow this range earlier (e.g., strongly funneling them into a lucrative family business). Individual families working with their chosen care providers are best positioned to identify and balance competing interests in particular circumstances.53,60,66,75,76 The presumed validity of a right to an open future has impeded that ideal approach for too long in too many pediatric contexts, including decisions about predictive genetic testing.

Table 4.

A comparative analysis of rights-based and interest-based ethical frameworks when applied to decisions about predictive genetic testing of children for adult-onset conditions.

RIGHTS-BASED
FRAMEWORK
INTEREST-BASED
FRAMEWORK
Focus Future adulthood Childhood/adolescence extending forward
Function Singling out one future-oriented autonomy interest for exceedingly strong protection until adulthood Weighing and balancing numerous competing interests comprising children’s present and future health and well-being
Flexibility Very low
(applied to all not-yet-autonomous minors at all stages, in all contexts, and irrespective of shifting evidence base)
High
(developmentally-contoured, contextually-tailored, and responsive to shifting evidence base)

The Advantages of an Interest-based Framework

In what follows, we use case-based reasoning to contrast rights-based and interest-based approaches to children’s open future. Admittedly, we cannot consider all factors that are ethically relevant to decisions about predictive genetic testing, such as the developmental status of the child, medical conditions, or clinical contexts. Nonetheless, the two vignettes we analyze represent commonly-encountered cases and, together, illustrate the value of an interests-based framework.

Case #1 - Ariel and Lynch syndrome.

Ariel is a ten year old girl with seizures but otherwise normal neurological development. Her neurologist specializes in the genetic basis of neurological conditions, and decided, after discussions with Ariel and her mother, to use genome sequencing to identify the cause of a seizure disorder, even though gene panels more narrowly focused on epilepsy are available. In analyzing the sequencing data, the neurologist determines that Ariel has a pathogenic variant in the MLH1 gene, which causes Lynch syndrome. Ariel has no contact with her father, and her mother was not sequenced. It is therefore not known from whom this variant was inherited or if it is de novo. When she reaches 20–25 years of age, Ariel should begin biennial colonoscopies to screen for cancer. Ariel does not have a family history of colon cancer or other Lynch syndrome cancers, but her mother was adopted and has no information about her own parents. If Ariel’s mother knew that Ariel had a pathogenic variant in MLH1, she could seek genetic testing for herself to determine whether she has that same variant, and thus pursue preventive measures that could provide substantial benefit. In fact, both Ariel and her mother might benefit if her mother’s risk of dying from early-onset colon cancer is decreased, which would decrease the chances of Ariel losing the care, attention, and financial stability her mother provides for her.

In this case, a clinician must decide whether to disclose a secondary (or “additional”77) finding that identifies a child’s predisposition for developing colon cancer. Although this information would not be clinically actionable for Ariel until adulthood, the clinician knows that Ariel’s positive finding means her mother may have the same variant. Given that her mother is unaware of her family medical history and adults do not routinely undergo pre-dispositional genetic testing, this “incidental” piece of information might provide her only warning.

If Ariel is understood to have a negative moral “right” to an open future, it would be irrelevant that her mother (and indirectly Ariel) might benefit from this information. After all, “rights” function as moral trump cards, overriding other competing interests.63,78 An interest-based standard, however, provides a framework within which multiple competing interests can be weighed. In deciding whether to share this information, the clinician should consider potential benefits to Ariel’s mother as a relevant interest, as well as potential benefits Ariel might receive from her mother avoiding morbidity and mortality.79 Keeping Ariel’s mother healthy could potentially support Ariel’s interest in having her basic needs met (#3), having support for emotional development (#5), and having a relationship with her parent (#10) (Table 3). Ariel’s interest in deferring the decision whether to receive this information until she can decide for herself as an adult is relevant, but it should be weighed alongside these other important interests.

Ariel’s case also highlights an important asymmetry when the right to an open future is applied to secondary genomic findings. Typically, claims about this right assume that the decision to seek or disclose genetic information can be made now, while the child is a minor, or later, when the child has reached adulthood. The options are not always so clear, however. If Ariel is still receiving care from the same physician when she reaches adulthood, then she may have an opportunity to decide for herself whether to receive secondary genetic results, including variants in the MLH1 gene. However, Ariel will not transition to adulthood for another eight years. In this time it is likely that Ariel’s family will have moved, their contact information will have changed, or her neurologist will have relocated or retired. Even if Ariel’s interests are, in principle, better served by deferring the decision until she reaches adulthood, nothing guarantees that she actually will be afforded this opportunity. An interest-based framework, however, can account for this possibility, weighing Ariel’s interest in deciding later with her interest in not missing an opportunity to receive important genetic information that otherwise may be unavailable.

Case #2 - Byron and Huntington’s disease.

Byron is an eleven year old male who has no chronic medical conditions. Byron’s paternal grandfather recently was diagnosed with Huntington’s disease. After discussing the issue with a genetic counselor and his family, Byron’s father decided to have a genetic test to determine whether he had inherited this condition. The test came back positive. Byron’s parents explained his father’s result to him, and all three decided to discuss genetic testing with his pediatrician and a genetic counselor. Although there were no pressing medical reasons for Byron to undergo testing, he and his parents agreed, after multiple conversations with his pediatrician and genetic counselor, that Byron should undergo genetic testing soon. The uncertainty was not causing psychosocial problems; indeed, all three were doing well in handling the uncertainty about Byron’s risk. However, all three saw value in not waiting until Byron reached adulthood to learn this information. Byron had decided that resolving this uncertainty would help him think about his future career, mainly because that could affect his choice of high school magnet programs. His parents, for their part, were already planning for his father’s long-term care, and wanted to understand how best to include Byron’s future health in that planning.

In contrast to Ariel’s case, neither Byron nor his parents have a time-sensitive medical interest in Byron undergoing genetic testing for Huntington’s disease as a minor. There is a strong argument for delaying testing until a person can decide for himself to undergo testing, especially since 85% of adults at risk for Huntington’s disease choose not to pursue testing.80,81 On the other hand, Byron already has decided he wants to pursue testing and no evidence indicates that he is likely to regret that decision later. Both Byron and his parents want to plan for the future, and these choices could be informed by genetic test results that establish whether Byron is likely to develop Huntington’s disease as an adult. Given the many other contingencies in life, it is debatable whether a possible diagnosis far in the future should be a determining factor in decisions such as which high school to attend. But on the other hand, the desire to plan ahead in this way is well within the bounds of reasonable (even laudable) behavior for parents and adolescents.

In theory, a rights-based approach is capable of accounting for the circumstance where a relatively mature minor and his parents agree about wanting testing. As the policy statements of the professional organizations referenced above demonstrate, the right to an open future has explicitly been construed as a right to have decisions delayed until the young person is capable of making autonomous decisions (an ethical concept), not necessarily until the young person gains the legal authority to make medical decisions when they reach the age of majority (a legal concept). Assent, for example, provides one strategy for legal minors to express their developing autonomy in medical decisions.82,83 In this case, Byron’s assent to Huntington’s testing would further justify the decision to obtain testing, while his parents’ permission would render it legally effective.

In practice, however, this is not how the right to an open future has been applied in clinical and research genetics. While strategies like assent can encourage minors to contribute meaningfully to medical decisions, the rights framing fosters the assumption that it is unnecessary, or even inappropriate, for parents to influence these decisions. If children have a right for decisions to be delayed until they can contribute to such choices, then children must also have a right for these decisions to be delayed even longer until no legal obligation requires including parents in the decision.

In contrast to the rights framing, interest-based approaches benefit from development in a range of applications in pediatric ethics,26,62 and thus provide a robust framework for balancing the developing autonomy of children with the authority of parents. In Byron’s case, an interest-based framework incorporates and weighs multiple factors, even interests that are not “clinically actionable,” such as Byron’s emotional development (#5) and sense of self and identity (#11 & #12), his desire to plan for his education and career (#7 & #13), his relationship with his parents (#10), and his parents’ desire to plan for long-term care (#2) (Table 3).

Within this framework, deliberation on multiple interests will not always generate identical guidance. In some cases, the child and his family may have compelling interests that override the child’s interest in preserving his future autonomy. On the other hand, there will be cases when the interests served by testing a minor will not be particularly compelling, and the child’s interest in an open future will remain the overriding interest. Consider what would happen if we changed the circumstances surrounding Byron’s case. If Byron were seven years old and perceived no personal utility in learning about his risk for developing Huntington’s disease, and his parents were simply curious or nervous about what his results might reveal, then the balance of interests could look quite different. His pediatrician or geneticist might be well-justified in declining the parents’ request for immediate genetic testing if the parents’ reason for wanting testing are outweighed by Byron’s interest in later making a decision for himself. This ability to discriminate among dissimilar cases is one notable advantage of the interests approach, and coheres with the intuition that compelling circumstances can override the child’s interest in an open future.60,63,64,69

In 2013, the American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP) and American College of Medical Genetics (ACMG) issued a joint policy statement on genetic testing in children. They recommended against predictive genetic testing unless interventions in childhood are likely to decrease morbidity and mortality. Departing from the former policy, however, they suggested that exceptions might be valid, and gave the example of “families for whom diagnostic uncertainty poses a significant psychosocial burden.”84 Our approach is consistent with the AAP/ACMG position, as well as a 2015 statement by the ASHG that makes a similar point.70 We are providing a more substantive framework than the concise policy statements could offer for considering when exceptions might be made.

Summary and Implications for the Future

In this paper, we noted how new understandings of predictive genetic information raise questions about the ethical foundations of predictive genetic testing. We think those questions are best answered by a shift in the basic approach to children’s open future from a rights-based to an interest-based framework. Childhood is inescapably subject to parental decisions that curtail and shape future choices in diverse and important ways. The idea of a right to an open future is thus impractical, ambiguous, and ripe for misinterpretation. Children need fiduciaries to make choices on their behalf, and nearly all such choices constrain a child’s future in some way.

To be clear, while we have argued that our interest-based framework improves upon the status quo, we recognize that it requires further development. Future research and collaboration should aim to:

  • develop a compelling account of how to evaluate, balance, and prioritize the interests on an unranked list like Malek’s (expanded to include a [future] autonomy interest);

  • translate this more detailed framework into specific professional guidelines that address the full spectrum of ethically challenging cases related to predictive genetic testing;

  • apply this framework in other domains where the right to an open future has been evoked, including within the field of genetics (germ-line modification of the mitochondrial genome and reproductive cloning) and beyond (the sterilization of minors, growth attenuation in children with developmental delay, and many others).

Still, our proposed framework provides a more fruitful and nuanced approach to the complicated ethical issues surrounding predictive genetic testing. We hope it will help guide those who must make these difficult decisions.

Acknowledgments

The CSER Consortium is funded by NHGRI and NCI (U01 HG006485 [Baylor College of Medicine], U01 HG006500 [Brigham and Women’s Hospital], U01 HG006546 [Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia], U01 HG006492 [Dana-Farber Cancer Institute], UM1 HG007301 [HudsonAlpha Institute], UM1 HG007292 [Kaiser Permanente], UM1 HG006508 [University of Michigan], U01 HG006487 [University of North Carolina], U01 HG006507 [University of Washington], R01 HG006615 [Boston Children’s Hospital], R21 HG006596 [Columbia University], R01 HG006600 [Columbia University], R21 HG006613 [Children’s Mercy Hospital], R21 HG006594 [Johns Hopkins University], R01 HG004500 [Mayo Clinic], R01 HG006618 [Seattle Children’s Hospital], R01 CA154517 [UC - San Francisco, Mayo College of Medicine, and University of Minnesota], R21 HG006612 [Vanderbilt University and McGill University], U01 HG007307 [University of Washington serving as the Coordinating Center]). ClinSeq (ZIA HG200387) is supported by the NHGRI Intramural Research Program.

The authors thank the coordinating center of the Clinical Sequencing Exploratory Research (CSER) Consortium (University of Washington) for their support, and in particular Jeffrey Ou BS, BA, who provided substantive support for this effort. Lucia Hindorff, PhD, MPH with the National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI) provided program staff support for this project. The authors also thank the following members of the CSER Consortium Pediatrics Working Group for participating in meetings to discuss the article as it was conceptualized and written: Benjamin Berkman JD, MPH (National Institutes of Health, Department of Bioethics); Barbara Bernhardt MS, CGC (University of Pennsylvania); Charlisse Caga-Anan, JD (National Cancer Institute (NCI)); Ellen Wright Clayton, MD, JD (Vanderbilt University Medical Center); Aaron Goldenberg, PhD, MPH (Case Western Reserve University); Sara Chandros Hull, PhD; (National Institutes of Health, Department of Bioethics); Steve Joffe, MD, MPH (University of Pennsylvania); Ian Krantz, MD (Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia); Michelle Lewis, MD, JD (John Hopkins Berman Institute of Bioethics); Wayne Liang, MD, MS, FAAP (University of Alabama at Birmingham); Nicole Lockhart, PhD (National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI)) Susana McCollum; Larry McCullough, PhD (Baylor College of Medicine); Amy McGuire, JD, PhD (Baylor College of Medicine); Ali Noorbaksh (Baylor College of Medicine); Sarita Panchang (Baylor College of Medicine); D. Will Parsons, MD, PhD (Baylor College of Medicine); Jacob Reiss, MD (Kaiser Permanente Northwest); Myra Roche, MS, CGC (University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill); Laura Rodriguez, PhD (National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI)); Edward Romasko, PhD (Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia); Lainie Friedman Ross, MD, PhD (University of Chicago); Richard Sharp, PhD (Mayo Clinic); Debra Skinner, PhD (University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill); Melody Slashinski, PhD, MPH (University of Massachusetts Amherst); Holly Tabor, PhD (Stanford University); Ashley Tomlinson, LSW (University of Pennsylvania); Susan Wolf, JD (University of Minnesota); Joon-Ho Yu, MPH, PhD (University of Washington). The authors also thank Leslie Ann McNolty, DPS (Center for Practical Bioethics) for helpful suggestions on revisions at several stages of the paper’s development, including the final draft. We would also like to thank Dena Davis, JD, PhD; Lehigh University who graciously served as a guest discussant for one of these meetings.

Footnotes

Conflict of Interest Statement: We have no commercial association or other financial interest that might pose or create a conflict of interest with information presented in this manuscript.

References

  • 1.Institute of Medicine 1994. Assessing Genetic Risks: Implications for Health and Social Policy. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press; 10.17226/2057. Accessed January 20, 2019. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Clarke A, Working Party of the Clinical Genetics Society (UK). The genetic testing of children. J Med Genet 1994;31:785–797. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.American Society of Human Genetics Board of Directors, American College of Medical Genetics Board of Directors. Points to consider: ethical, legal, and psychosocial implications of genetic testing in children and adolescents Am J Hum Genet 1995;57:1233–1241. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics. Ethical issues with genetic testing in pediatrics Pediatrics 2001;107:1451–1455. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Arbour L, Canadian Paediatric Society, Bioethics Committee. Guidelines for genetic testing of healthy children. Paediatrics & Child Health 2003;8:42–45. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.European Society of Human Genetics. Genetic testing in asymptomatic minors: recommendations of the European Society of Human Genetics Eur J Hum Genet 2009;17:720–721. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.National Society of Genetic Counselors. NSGC position statement: genetic testing of minors for adult-onset conditions. 2017. https://www.nsgc.org/p/bl/et/blogaid=860. Accessed January 20, 2019. [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Human Genetics Society of Australasia. Presymptomatic and predictive testing for children and young adults. 2014. https://www.hgsa.org.au/documents/item/272. Accessed January 20, 2019. [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Wade CH, Wilfond BS, McBride CM. Effects of genetic risk information on children’s psychosocial wellbeing: a systematic review of the literature. Genet Med 2010;12:317–326. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Wakefield CE, Hanlon LV, Tucker KM, et al. The psychological impact of genetic information on children: a systematic review. Genet Med 2016;18:755–762. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Fryer A Inappropriate genetic testing of children. Arch Dis Child 2000;83:283–285. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Duncan R, Savulescu J, Gillam L, et al. An international survey of predictive genetic testing in children for adult onset conditions. Genet Med 2005;7:390–396 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Mand C, Gillam L, Delatycki MB, Duncan RE. Predictive genetic testing in minors for late-onset conditions: a chronological and analytical review of the ethical arguments. J Med Ethics 2012;38:519–524. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Fenwick A, Plantinga M, Dheensa S, Lucassen A. Predictive genetic testing of children for adult-onset conditions: negotiating requests with parents. J Genet Couns 2017;26:244–250. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.McCullough LB, Brothers KB, Chung WK, et al. Professionally responsible disclosure of genomic sequencing results in pediatric practice. Pediatrics 2015;136:e974–982. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Wisconsin v. Yoder, et al. , 406 U.S 205(1972). [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Feinberg J The child’s right to an open future In: Feinberg J Freedom and fulfillment: philosophical essays. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; 1992:76–97. [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Davis DS. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Cent Rep 1997;27:7–15. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Davis DS. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Rutgers Law J 1997: 28: 549–592. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Davis DS. Genetic dilemmas: reproductive technology, parental choices, and children’s futures, 2nd ed New York: Oxford University Press, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Gooding HC, Wilfond B, Boehm K, Biesecker BB. Unintended messages: the ethics of teaching genetic dilemmas. Hastings Cent Rep 2002;32:37–39. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Hercher L, Uhlmann WR, Hoffman EP, Gustafson S, Chen KM, Public Policy Committee of NSGC. Prenatal testing for adult-onset conditions: the position of the National Society of Genetic Counselors. J Gen Couns 2016;25:1139–1145. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Mameli M Reproductive cloning, genetic engineering and the autonomy of the child: the moral agent and the open future. J Med Ethics 2007;33:87–93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Davis DS. The parental investment factor and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Cent Rep 2009;39:24–27. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 25.de Souza M Regulating preimplantation genetic diagnosis in Australia: disability and parental choice. J Law Med 2015;22:915–933. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26.Wilfond BS, Miller PS, Korfiatis C, et al. Navigating growth attenuation in children with profound disabilities: children’s interests, family decision-making, and community concerns. Hastings Cent Rep 2010;40:27–40. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Bredenoord AL, Dondorp W, Pennings G, De Wert G. Ethics of modifying the mitochondrial genome. J Med Ethics 2011;37:97–100. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Darby RJ. The child’s right to an open future: is the principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision? J Med Ethics 2013;39:463–468. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Hainz T The enhancement of children versus circumcision: a case of double moral standards? Bioethics 2015;29:507–515. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Camporesi S Bend it like Beckham! The ethics of genetically testing children for athletic potential. Sports Ethics Philos 2013;7:175–185. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Loland S Against genetic tests for athletic talent: the primacy of the phenotype. Sports Med 2015;45:1229–1233. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Camporesi S, McNamee MJ. Ethics, genetic testing, and athletic talent: children’s best interests, and the right to an open (athletic) future. Physiol Genomics 2016;48:191–195. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Graf WD, Nagel SK, Epstein LG, Miller G, Nass R, Larriviere D. Pediatric neuroenhancement: ethical, legal, social, and neurodevelopmental implications. Neurology 2013;80:1251–1260. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Krutzinna JI. Beyond an open future. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2017;26:313–325. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Yu JH, Jamal SM, Tabor HK, Bamshad MJ. Self-guided management of exome and whole-genome sequencing results: changing the results return model. Genet Med 2013;15:684–690. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Bredenoord AL, de Vries MC, van Delden JJ. Next-generation sequencing: does the next generation still have a right to an open future? Nat Rev Genet 2013;14:306. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Bredenoord AL, de Vries MC, van Delden H. The right to an open future concerning genetic information. Am J Bioeth 2014;14:21–23. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38.Hofmann B Incidental findings of uncertain significance: to know or not to know--that is not the question. BMC Med Ethics 2016;17:13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Sundby A, Boolsen MW, Burgdorf KS, et al. Hum Genomics 2018;12:12. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Kon AA. Ethical issues in decision-making for infants with disorders of sex development. Horm Metab Res 2015;47:340–343. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Cutas D, Hens K. Preserving children’s fertility: two tales about children’s right to an open future and the margins of parental obligations. Med Health Care Philos 2015;18:253–260. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Kranendork EJ, Ploem MC, Hennekam RC. Regulating biobanking with children’s tissue: a legal analysis and the experts’ view. Eur J Hum Genet 2016;24:30–36. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Mason PH. Personal genomic testing, genetic inheritance, and uncertainty. J Bioeth Inq 2017;14:583–584. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.Morissey C, Walker RL. The ethics of general population preventive genomic sequencing: rights and social justice. J Med Philos 2018;43:22–43. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Mintz RL, Loike JD, Fischbach RL. Will CRISPR germline engineering close the door to an open future. Sci Eng Ethics 2018. 10.1007/s11948-018-0069-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 46.Sziron M, Hildt E. Digital media, the right to an open future, and children 0–5. Front Psychol 2018;9:2137. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Bloch M, Hayden MR. Opinion: predictive testing for Huntington disease in childhood: challenges and implications. Am J Hum Genet 1990: 46: 1–4. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Harper PS, Clarke A. Should we test children for ‘adult’ genetic diseases? Lancet 1990;335:1205–1206. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Borry P, Stultiens L, Nys H, et al. Presymptomatic and predictive genetic testing in minors: a systematic review of guidelines and position papers. Clin Genet 2006;70:374–381. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Duncan RE. Predictive genetic testing in young people: when is it appropriate? J Paediatr Child Health 2004;40:593–595. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Duncan RE, Delatycki MB. Predictive genetic testing in young people for adult-onset conditions: where is the empirical evidence? Clin Genet 2006:69;8–16. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Borry P, Goffin T, Nys H, Dierickx K. Predictive genetic testing in minors for adult‐onset genetic diseases. Mt Sinai J Med 2008;75:287–296. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53.Wilfond B, Ross LF. From genetics to genomics: ethics, policy, and parental decision-making. J Pediatr Psychol 2009;34:639–647. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54.Parker M Genetic testing in children and young people. Fam Cancer 2010;9:15–18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Clarke A What is at stake in the predictive genetic testing of children? Fam Cancer 2010;9:19–22. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Fenwick J Are guidelines for genetic testing of children necessary? Fam Cancer 2010;9:23–25. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 57.Gilbar R Genetic testing of children for familial cancers: a comparative legal perspective on consent, communication of information and confidentiality. Fam Cancer 2010;9:75–87. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58.Anderson JA, Hayeems RZ, Shuman C, et al. Predictive genetic testing for adult-onset disorders in minors: a critical analysis of the arguments for and against the 2013 ACMG guidelines. Clin Genet 2015;87:301–310. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59.Mills C The child’s right to an open future? J Soc Philos 2003;34:499–509. [Google Scholar]
  • 60.Cohen CB. Wrestling with the future: should we test children for adult-onset genetic conditions? Kennedy Inst Ethics J 1998;8:111–130. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61.Millum J The foundation of the child’s right to an open future. J Soc Philos 2014;45:522–538. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 62.Ross LF. Children, families, and health care decision making. New York: Clarendon Press, 1998. [Google Scholar]
  • 63.Harris J, Keywood K. Ignorance, information and autonomy. Theor Med Bioeth 2001;22:415–436. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 64.Malpas P Predictive genetic testing on children and respect for autonomy. Int J Child Right 2005;13:273–285. [Google Scholar]
  • 65.Robertson S, Savulescu J. Is there a case in favour of predictive genetic testing in young children? Bioethics 2001;15:26–49. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 66.Rhodes R Why test children for adult-onset genetic diseases? Mt Sinai J Med 2006;73:609–616. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 67.Häyry M, Takala T. Genetic information, rights, and autonomy. Theor Med Bioeth 2001;22:403–414. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 68.Rights Wenar L.. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University; 2015. [Google Scholar]
  • 69.British Society of Human Genetics (BSHG). Report on the genetic testing of children. Birmingham, BSHG, 2010. Available at: https://www.bsgm.org.uk/media/678741/gtoc_booklet_final_new.pdf. Accessed January 20, 2019. [Google Scholar]
  • 70.American Society of Human Genetics Board of Directors, American College of Medical Genetics Board of Directors. Points to consider: ethical, legal, and psychosocial implications of genetic testing in children and adolescents Am J Hum Genet 2015;97:6–21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 71.Ross LF. Theory and practice of pediatric bioethics. Perspect Biol Med 2016;58:267–280. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 72.Diekema DS. Parental refusals of medical treatment: the harm principle as threshold for state intervention. Theor Med Bioeth 2004;25:243–264. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 73.Gillam L Children’s bioethics and the zone of parental discretion. Monash Bioeth Rev 2010;20:09.01–3. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 74.Malek J What really is in a child’s best interest? Toward a more precise picture of the interests of children. J Clin Ethics 2009;20:175–182. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 75.Clayton EW. Genetic testing in children. J Med Philos 1997;22:233–251. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 76.Lucassen A, Fenwick A. Testing children for adult onset conditions: the importance of contextual clinical judgment. J Med Ethics 2012;38:531–532. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 77.Tan N, Amendola LM, O’Daniel JM, et al. Is “incidental finding” the best term?: a study of patients’ preferences. Genet Med 2017;19:176–181. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 78.Dworkin R Rights as trumps In: Waldron J, editor. Theories of rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984: 153–167. [Google Scholar]
  • 79.Wilfond BS, Fernandez CV, Green RC. Disclosing secondary findings from pediatric sequencing to families: considering the “benefit to families”. J Law Med Ethics 2015;43:552–558. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 80.Creighton S, Almqvist EW, MacGregor D, et al. Predictive, pre-natal and diagnostic genetic testing for Huntington’s disease: the experience in Canada from 1987 to 2000. Clin Genet 2003;63:462–475. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 81.Morrison PJ, Harding-Lester S, Bradley A. Uptake of Huntington disease predictive testing in a complete population. Clin Genet 2011;80:281–286. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 82.Wilfond BS, Diekema DS. Engaging children in genomics research: decoding the meaning of assent in research. Genet Med 2012;14:437–443. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 83.Brothers KB, Lynch JA, Aufox SA, et al. Practical guidance on informed consent for pediatric participants in a biorepository. Mayo Clin Proc 2014;89:1471–1480. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 84.AAP Committee on Bioethics, AAP Committee on Genetics, ACMG Social Ethical and Legal Issues Committee. Ethical and policy issues in genetic testing and screening of children Pediatrics 2013;131:620–622. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES