Skip to main content
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America logoLink to Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America
. 2019 Oct 1;116(42):20886–20891. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1817444116

Declining CO2 price paths

Kent D Daniel a,b,1, Robert B Litterman c,1, Gernot Wagner d,1,2,3
PMCID: PMC6800385  PMID: 31575747

Significance

Risk and uncertainty are important in pricing climate damages. Despite a burgeoning literature, attempts to marry insights from asset pricing with climate economics have largely failed to supplement—let alone supplant—decades-old climate–economy models, largely due to their analytic and computational complexity. Here, we introduce a simple, modular framework that identifies core trade-offs, highlights the sensitivity of results to key inputs, and helps pinpoint areas for further work.

Keywords: climate risk, asset pricing, cost of carbon

Abstract

Pricing greenhouse-gas (GHG) emissions involves making trade-offs between consumption today and unknown damages in the (distant) future. While decision making under risk and uncertainty is the forte of financial economics, important insights from pricing financial assets do not typically inform standard climate–economy models. Here, we introduce EZ-Climate, a simple recursive dynamic asset pricing model that allows for a calibration of the carbon dioxide (CO2) price path based on probabilistic assumptions around climate damages. Atmospheric CO2 is the “asset” with a negative expected return. The economic model focuses on society’s willingness to substitute consumption across time and across uncertain states of nature, enabled by an Epstein–Zin (EZ) specification that delinks preferences over risk from intertemporal substitution. In contrast to most modeled CO2 price paths, EZ-Climate suggests a high price today that is expected to decline over time as the “insurance” value of mitigation declines and technological change makes emissions cuts cheaper. Second, higher risk aversion increases both the CO2 price and the risk premium relative to expected damages. Lastly, our model suggests large costs associated with delays in pricing CO2 emissions. In our base case, delaying implementation by 1 y leads to annual consumption losses of over 2%, a cost that roughly increases with the square of time per additional year of delay. The model also makes clear how sensitive results are to key inputs.


For over 25 y, the dynamic integrated climate–economy (DICE) model (13) has been the standard tool for analyzing CO2 emissions-reductions pathways, and for good reason. One attraction is its simplicity, turning a “market failure on the greatest scale the world has seen” (4) and “the mother of all externalities” (5) into a model involving fewer than 20 main equations, 3 representing the climate system (6). DICE has spawned many variants (7). It has also helped set the tone for what many consider “optimal” CO2 price paths. The core trade-off between economic consumption and climate damages leads to relatively low CO2 prices today rising over time.

DICE and models like it have well-known limitations, including how they represent climate risk and uncertainty (715). DICE, for example, is not an optimal-control model, as commonly understood by economists employing modern dynamic economic analysis, even though it lends itself to those extensions (912). The underlying structure all but prescribes a rising CO2 price path over time.

One important limitation is the form of the utility function. Constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) preferences, standard in most climate–economy models (1, 7, 16), assume that economic agents have an equal aversion to variation in consumption across states of nature and over time. Evidence from financial markets suggests that this is not the case (17). The risk premium (RP) of equities over bonds points to a fundamental difference in how much society is willing to pay to substitute consumption risk across states of nature compared to over time (18, 19). Some have explained the discrepancy by allowing for extreme events (2022), and others have looked to more flexible preferences (2326) or both (27). Our own preference specification follows Epstein and Zin (EZ) (24, 25).

EZ Preferences

Here, we use EZ preferences and focus on climate uncertainties. We approach climate change as an asset pricing problem with atmospheric CO2 as the “asset.” The value of an investment in reducing CO2 emissions depends on the state of nature, represented by its fragility θt. That, in turn, helps determine the discount rate applied to the damages that would have occurred without the investment.

Our representative agent maximizes a recursive utility Ut based on consumption ct and expectations Et over future utility for times t0,1,2,,T1 :

Ut=1βctρ+βEtUt+1αρα1ρ. [1]

Parameters α and ρ measure the agent’s willingness to substitute consumption across states of nature and across time, respectively. (See Methods for the final-period utility UT and further derivations.) CRRA preferences are a special case, with α=ρ. Unlike with CRRA, Eq. 1 implies that CO2 prices no longer collapse to zero with increasing risk aversion (RA) and equity risk premia (Fig. 1A). The same goes for the portion of CO2 prices explained by RA (Fig. 1B).

Fig. 1.

Fig. 1.

Risk calibration. A shows how using EZ preferences, unlike CRRA, results in increasing 2015 CO2 prices, in 2015 US$, with increasing RA, translated into the implied equity RP using Weil’s conversion (19), while holding implied market interest rates stable at 3.11%. B shows how the percentage of the 2015 CO2 price explained by RA, as opposed to expected damages (EDs), increases with equity RP for EZ utility, while decreasing for CRRA (Risk Decomposition).

EZ preferences have since found their way into the climate–economic literature (912, 2835). Some have embedded EZ into DICE (28, 35), and others employ supercomputers to solve (912). The complexity typically does not allow for analytic solutions (34). We here follow a simple binomial-tree model with a long history in financial modeling application (36). It is precisely this modeling choice—standard in financial economics but novel to climate–economic applications—that leads to our fundamentally differing CO2 price paths. Mitigating climate risk provides a hedge, leading to high CO2 prices early on. As uncertainties decline over time, so do CO2 prices.

Model

The setting for EZ-Climate is a standard endowment economy (37). In each period, the agent is endowed with a certain amount of the consumption good c¯t. However, she is not able to consume the full c¯t for 2 reasons: climate change and climate policy. In periods t1,2,,T, a portion of c¯t may be lost due to climate-change damages, which are, in turn, a function of cumulative radiative forcing (CRFt) up to time t and of fragility θt: DtCRFt,θt. Up to period T1, the agent may elect to spend some of c¯t to reduce her impact on the future climate, κt, which, in turn, depends on mitigation xt. The resulting consumption ct, after Dt and κt are taken into account, is given by:

c0=c¯01κ0x0, [2]
ct=c¯t1κtxt1DtCRFt,θt,fort1,2,,T1,and [3]
cT=c¯T1DT(CRFT,θT). [4]

CRFt is a function of mitigation, xs, in each period from 0 to t, calibrated to a combination of Representative Concentration Pathway (RCP) scenarios (Climate Damages).

The agent maximizes utility given by Eq. 1 in each of T periods by selecting, at each time and in each state, a level of mitigation xt, creating in essence a “2T+11”-dimensional optimization problem. Fig. 2A shows our base case, which uses a 7-period tree with decision nodes from 2015 through 2300. At each node, more information about θt and the resulting climate damages is revealed, before uncertainty is resolved at the beginning of the penultimate period in 2300. In the “easy” spirit of EZ-Climate, the limited number of decision points makes the solution both tractable and quickly solvable.

Fig. 2.

Fig. 2.

Model tree structure. A shows a diagram of the binomial tree structure (with probability p=12) used in solving the model for each state of nature θt across time t1,2,,T , corresponding to years 2015, 2030, 2060, 2100, 2200, 2300, and final period 2400. Note the “recombining” tree structure, highlighted in the first 2 periods: Damage functions in any particular state are independent of the path taken, but xt and the resulting Ut are path-dependent. B shows the CO2 price in the base case (peakT=6, disastertail=18, and EIS=0.9).

EZ-Climate provides an accessible, modular framework (7) that is dependent on key economic inputs—chiefly, RA and the elasticity of intertemporal substitution (EIS)—and 2 main climate-related ones: mitigation costs and climate damages. Costs depend primarily on assumptions around backstop technologies (38) and technological change. Damages depend on the full climate–economic chain from economic output to CO2 emissions, from emissions to concentrations, from concentrations to CRF, and from CRF to climate damages lowering economic consumption. While all of these calibrations are important, and uncertainties abound, a key addition is allowing for potentially catastrophic risk in form of climatic tipping points (TPs) (39, 40) (Climate Damages).

Results and Discussion

Fig. 2B shows CO2 prices for each node of the tree in our base case. The 2015 CO2 price comes from a single node in the tree. In each subsequent period, the price is set in expectation over all possible states of nature θt in that given period. All grouped nodes at a given time have the same θt and, thus, the same damage for a given amount of CRF. The price itself is path-dependent. Fig. 2B also shows the costs associated with bad θt draws in latter periods. Bad news is costly. Bad news late, when it is more difficult to counteract with more active policy, is worse. It is precisely the inability to know upfront when good or bad news arrives that accounts for the insurance value of early mitigation and, thus, the role that the resolution of risk over time plays in the declining CO2 price.

Declining CO2 Price.

Unlike most modeled CO2 price paths, ours typically rise briefly before declining over time. One partial explanation is the move from CRRA to EZ preferences. CRRA preferences duplicate the decline only with a RA=1091.1, when EZ collapses to CRRA. For higher RA, consistent with those estimated from models calibrated to financial-market data, early CRRA prices collapse to near zero (Fig. 3A). But going from CRRA to EZ preferences is not the only explanation, implied by the fact that CRRA price paths stay flat over time.

Fig. 3.

Fig. 3.

Declining CO2 price paths. A shows how EZ utility here leads to CO2 prices that start high and decline over time, regardless of assumed RA, a feature mimicked only by unrealistically low RA=1091.1, when EZ and CRRA utilities coincide (Economic Parameters). B and C show the importance of EIS and the rate of pure time preference (δ), respectively. B varies real interest rates from 2.74% (EIS = 1.2) to 3.77% (EIS = 0.6) to keep c¯=1.5%. C fixes EIS at 0.9, while δ varies from 0.25% to 0.75% (SI Appendix, Figs. S5 and S6).

Others have pointed to reasons for declining CO2 price paths including producer behavior (41), the need for directed technological change from “dirty” to “clean” sectors (42), or inertia (43). We here find 2 factors driving the declining CO2 price paths: the resolution of uncertainty, combined with technological progress that makes mitigation significantly cheaper over time.

Our base case assumes exogenous technological progress φ0=1.5% and endogenous progress φ1=0.015 per year, linked to average mitigation efforts to date (Eq. 19). The combination makes mitigation costs diminishingly small hundreds of years out, helping to drive the declining price paths (Fig. 4A and SI Appendix, Fig. S3).

Fig. 4.

Fig. 4.

CO2 price sensitivities. A shows the implications of technological change and TP assumptions. Setting φ0=0%φ1=0 increases early-year and final-period prices, flattening the price path. Multiple TPs act akin to fattening the tail of the damage function, steepening the price path. They also interact with the no-technological-change assumption, increasing final-period prices. B shows that 2015 CO2 prices depend crucially on “catastrophic” climate risk assumptions, set to peakT=6C and disastertail=18 in the base case (Climate Damages). C, by contrast, shows the minimal implications of extending the final period from 2300 to 2400 for t=6 and 7, respectively, in the base case to 2400 and 2700.

Another reason for declining price paths is the assumed nature of TPs in the base case. Each node has a certain probability of hitting a TP, given by Eq. 22. Once hit, there is no reversing the resulting damages. That structure increases prices in early years, decreasing them later, as it introduces a nonconcavity into the damage function (37). Allowing for multiple TPs exacerbates that result in the base case, as it fattens the tail of the damage function (Fig. 4A). Assuming no technological change, meanwhile, increases final-period prices, more so with multiple TPs.

While the declining CO2 price path is a persistent feature across model specifications (SI Appendix, Figs. S3, S5, and S6), the absolute CO2 price in early years depends crucially on a number of calibration choices. Fig. 3 shows the importance of economic parameters, chiefly, EIS and the pure rate of time preference (δ). Fig. 4B shows the sensitivity of the initial CO2 price to assumptions around “catastrophic” climate risk. Our base case assumes 6 °C for the “peak temperature” (peakT) and 18 for the disastertail calibrations. While there is seeming convergence around 6 °C as an upper bound for what could conceivably be quantified (see, for example, https://helixclimate.eu/), declaring it equivalent to a “global TP” is at best unduly conservative (11, 15, 40), at worst arbitrary. Much more work is needed to justify any one particular parameter value and, thus, any one CO2 price (7). Our goal with EZ-Climate is to provide a simple, modular framework to think about climate risks, uncertainties, TPs, and their implications for CO2 prices.

Social Cost of Delay.

The optimal-control nature of EZ-Climate also allows for a calculation of the social cost of delay in implementing CO2 prices. Unlike prior efforts (2, 7), we do not look to the CO2 price for estimating that cost. In fact, doing so can be positively misleading. After constraining the price to $0 in the first period, the price in the second period is lower than in the unconstrained case. The price reflects the marginal benefits of additional emissions reductions, which are now lower. We here instead quantify the cost of delay by constraining mitigation to zero in the first period and asking how much additional consumption would be required during that period in order to bring the utility of the representative agent to the level of the unconstrained solution.

Table 1 shows the annual consumption loss during the constrained first period. For a 10-y delay, the equivalent annual consumption loss over the first constrained period is ∼23%: Each year of delay increases the annual consumption loss over the entire constrained period by ∼2.3%. It also increases the time interval of the loss, thus leading to a slightly more than quadratic rate of increase in the deadweight loss of utility over time. In rough monetary terms, delaying implementation by only 1 y costs society approximately $1 trillion. A 5-y delay creates the equivalent loss of approximately $24 trillion, comparable to a severe global depression. A 10-y delay causes an equivalent loss in the order of $10 trillion per year, approximately $100 trillion in total.

Table 1.

Social cost of delay by first-period length

First-period Annual consumption impact
length, y during first period, %
5 11
10 23
15 36

Absolute annual household consumption numbers are around $40 trillion per year.

Conclusion

Our conclusion could mimic that of DICE, introduced over 25 y ago (1), with one crucial difference: Like with DICE, and despite crucial recent advances (7, 35), “it should be emphasized that this analysis has a number of important qualifications,” especially, ironically, “the economic impact of climate change” (1). Unlike DICE, EZ-Climate does not “[abstract] from issues of uncertainty” (1). It embraces them, following a simple binomial-tree framework long used in the finance literature (36). The simple, modular framework also highlights the sensitivity of CO2 prices to key inputs. There is no single, correct, “optimal” price path. One persistent feature, however, is declining price paths. That puts the focus on near-term action and on the large costs of delay.

Methods

Utility Specification.

Eq. 1 represents a special case of Kreps–Porteus preferences (23), following EZ (24, 25) for t0,1,2,,T1, with ct given by Eqs. 24. In t=T (=2400, in our base-case calibration), the representative agent receives utility from all present discounted consumption from T onward. Consumption grows at a constant rate r for tT:

ct=cT(1+r)tT, [5]

with cT given by Eq. 4. The resulting final-period utility is:

UT=1β1β(1+r)ρ1ρcT. [6]

Risk Decomposition.

Fig. 1B shows the split between EDs and the RP in explaining 2015 CO2 prices (44). To calculate the cost of an additional ton of CO2 emissions, we sum over all consumption damages, in every state of nature s at every future time t, multiplied by the value of an additional unit of consumption for each s and t. The 2015 CO2 price, thus, is:

t=1Ts=1S(t)πs,tms,tDs,t=t=1TE0m~tD~t, [7]

where S(t) denotes the number of states at time t, πs,t the probability of state s at time t, and pricing kernel ms,t=Ucs,t/Uc0. Eq. 7 can be further decomposed into ED and RP:

t=1TE0m~tE0D~tED+t=1Tcov0m~t,D~tRP. [8]

Note that Eom~t=1/Rf0,t, where Rf0,t is the payoff, at time t, to a $1 investment in a risk-free bond at t0. Alternatively, E0m~t is the risk-free discount factor between today and t. ED, thus, is the sum of marginal climate damages, discounted back to the present at the risk-free rate:

ED=t=1TE0D~t/Rf0,t. [9]

RP then is the difference between the CO2 price and ED.

Mitigation Costs.

Calibrating the mitigation cost requires specifying a relationship between the marginal cost of emissions reductions, equal to the per-ton tax rate τ, the resulting flow of emissions per year gτ, and the fraction of emissions reduced xτ .

Many modeling efforts have attempted to estimate the marginal abatement costs (MACs), often as part of integrated assessment models. See, for example, Stanford’s Energy Modeling Forum (https://emf.stanford.edu/). Perhaps the most influential, independent effort comes from McKinsey & Company in an attempt to estimate a bottom-up MAC curve (MACC) (45). McKinsey’s MACCs are, to a large extent, based on bottom-up “engineering” estimates. That makes them an easy target for critique by economists, who often focus on the large abatement opportunities with “negative” costs or the “energy-efficiency gap” (46, 47). We calibrate τ, gτ, and xτ based on McKinsey’s global MACC effort (48), with one crucial modification: We set xτ=0 for τ0; i.e., we assume no net-negative cost mitigation. SI Appendix, Table S1 shows the resulting modified point estimates, which we fit to a power function for xτ, yielding:

xτ=0.0923τ0.414. [10]

The corresponding inverse function, solving for τ to achieve x, yields the marginal cost of abatement:

τx=314.32x2.413. [11]

Ultimately, we are interested in the total cost to society κτ for each particular tax τ. We calculate κτ using the envelope theorem, assuming the representative agent chooses gτ so as to maximize consumption c given τ: dcτdτ=gτ. Consumption x associated with a particular τ, thus, equals:

cτ=c¯0τgsds. [12]

However, Eq. 12 is only correct if the government were to collect τ and then waste 100% of the proceeds gττ. Here, we assume instead that the proceeds are refunded in lump sum (49). Refunding gττ and rewriting Eq. 12 yields total mitigation costs of:

Kτ=0τgsdsgττ. [13]

The lump-sum refund does not allow for CO2 tax proceeds to be used to decrease other distortionary taxes, which would make the total costs smaller still (50, 51). Rewriting gτ=g01xτ, where g0 is the emissions baseline, we can rewrite Eq. 13 as:

Kτ=g0τxτ0τxsds. [14]

Substituting Eqs. 10 and 11 into Eq. 14 and dividing by current aggregate consumption yields the societal cost of a given level of mitigation as a percentage of initial consumption c0:

κx=g092.08/C0x3.413. [15]

Our base-case calibration assumes g0= 52 billion tons of CO2-equivalent emissions and c0= $31 trillion/year representing current 2015 global consumption in 2015 US$. Eq. 15 assumes no technological progress and no backstop technology.

Backstop Technology.

We also allow for a backstop technology in form of CO2 removal (38, 52) to become available at cost τ* at x0 and to be used exclusively for MACs τ~. The MACC including a backstop follows:

Bx=τ~kx1b. [16]

We calibrate Eq. 16 to set Bx0=τ*, and we impose a smooth-pasting condition at x0, resulting in:

k=x0τ~τ*τ~τ*(α1)τ*. [17]

Our base case assumes τ*=$2,000 and τ~=$2,500 in 2015 dollars. Under the most aggressive backstop scenario presented in Results and Discussion, we assume τ*=$300 and τ~=$350. SI Appendix, Fig. S1 shows the resulting 2015 τ(x).

Technological Progress.

SI Appendix, Fig. S1 is calibrated to t=0. In subsequent periods, we allow the MACC to decrease at a rate determined by a set of technological change parameters: a constant component φ0 and an endogenous component linked to mitigation efforts to date φ1Xt, where Xt is the average mitigation up to time t defined by:

Xt=s=0tgsxss=0tgs. [18]

Mitigation costs at time t are:

κtx=κx1φ0φ1Xtt. [19]

This functional form allows for easy calibration. For example, if φ0=0.005 and φ1=0.01, and with average mitigation Xt=50%, κtx decreases at a rate of 1% per year.

SI Appendix, Fig. S3 shows the implications of both backstop technology and technological progress on the CO2 price.

Climate Damages.

We derive DtCRFt,θt in 2 steps. Damages are a function of temperature changes ΔT, which, in turn, are a function of CRF. We calibrate ΔT over time based on the International Energy Agency’s (IEA’s) projections for ΔT100 using its “new policies scenario” (53), equating the values with t=100. We fit a displaced gamma distribution (54) around the IEA’s 2100 greenhouse gas (GHG) concentration projections for 450, 650, and 1,000 ppm. SI Appendix, Table S2 shows the calibration results. We translate ΔT100 into ΔTt for t=0 (year 2015) through t=385 (year 2400) using:

ΔTt=2ΔT10010.5t100. [20]

SI Appendix, Fig. S2 shows the results for ΔTt based on ΔT100 values. We then fit a log-normal distribution for equilibrium climate sensitivity (15, 55) around ΔT100 to generate distributions for ΔTt based on emissions-reduction pathways xt. One important possible extension is around timing, further probing our assumption of equating effects at ΔT100 with climate sensitivity (56).

We calibrate damages Dt based on ΔT considering 2 multiplicative components: a noncatastrophic loss function and a catastrophic hazard function (32). The noncatastrophic component is in the form of a displaced gamma distribution (54), resulting in the loss function:

LΔTt=e13.97γΔTt2. [21]

Parameter γ is drawn from a displaced gamma distribution with its 3 parameters a=4.5, d = 21,341, and p=0.0000746. That calibration, much like other econometrically based estimates extrapolating from past experience (57), all but rules out “catastrophic” damages and so-called climatic TPs or “tipping elements” (39, 40).

We augment this calibration with a “catastrophic” component, assuming a particular probability of hitting a climatic TP, ProbTP, in any given period, if temperature changes cross a peakT threshold:

ProbTP=11ΔTtmaxΔTt,peakT2period30. [22]

In the base-case calibration, we set peakT=6C (Fig. 3B). While ad hoc, the number is, if anything, unduly conservative (15, 39, 40, 55). SI Appendix, Fig. S4A shows the resulting probabilities for a 30-y period. Conditional on hitting a TP at time t*, the level of consumption for each subsequent tt* is reduced by the factor eTPdamage, where TPdamage is drawn from a gamma distribution with parameters α=1 and β=disastertail. SI Appendix, Fig. S4B shows the resulting probability of economic damages exceeding a particular percentage of total output.

We then generate distributions for DtCRFt,θt for each period for each of 3 maximum GHG concentration levels—450, 650, and 1,000 ppm—based on 6 million draws each. These 3 scenarios correspond roughly to constant mitigation of slightly over 90% for 450 ppm, almost 60% for 650 ppm, and the IEA’s “new policies scenario” (53) for 1,000 ppm. The mapping happens via CRF, interpolating and extrapolating across RCP scenarios (58). We fit a log-function, estimating radiative forcing based on GHG emissions in any 10-y interval as: 5.351logGHGlog278. Carbon absorption in any 10-y interval is given by 0.94835|GHG(285.6268+0.88414absorption)|0.741547. We then interpolate between the 3 GHG levels to find a smooth damage function for any particular level of CRFt. We assume a linear interpolation of damages between 650 and 1,000 ppm and a quadratic interpolation between 450 and 650 ppm, including a smooth pasting condition at 650 ppm. Below 450 ppm, we assume that climate damages exponentially decay toward zero, setting S=dp/(lln(0.5)), where d is the derivative of the quadratic damage interpolation function at 450 ppm and p=0.91667 is the average mitigation in the 450 ppm simulation, with l as damage levels (SI Appendix, Fig. S4C).

The representative agent knows the distribution of possible final states θT. She does not know θt for t<T. In line with the recombining tree structure (36), climate damages are the probability-weighted average of the interpolated damage function over all final climate states reachable from any one node:

DtCRFt,θt=θTPr(θT|θt)DtCRFt,θT. [23]

Introducing CO2 removal (38, 52) (Backstop Technology), combined with stochastic climate states θt, creates the possibility of GHG concentrations falling below preindustrial levels of 280 ppm. While we know of no analysis that estimates economic damages below 280 ppm, there clearly are costs, much like going (well) above 280 ppm. We introduce a penalty function of the form:

fx=1+ekxm1. [24]

We arbitrarily set m=200 as the GHG level resulting in half the total penalty. Scalar k=0.05 ensures a smooth penalty function. The combination ensures that f280 is almost zero, while still achieving a smooth surface. We further restrict Dt0 and xt0.

Economic Parameters.

Fig. 3A shows the CO2 price sensitivity to RA. With EZ, the CO2 declines regardless of RA. We choose RA = 7 in our base-case calibration, a value roughly in line with attitudes toward large income risk across wealthy countries (59): RA in the United States alone is often higher (>8), while RA in European welfare states can be as low as 3. Similar patterns as those displayed in Fig. 3A (and in Fig. 4B for climate damage parameters) hold for mitigation cost parameters (SI Appendix, Fig. S3) and an exhaustive list of other economic parameters. The most important of these parameters appear to be the EIS (Fig. 3B and SI Appendix, Fig. S5) and the pure rate of time preference δ=1β/β from Eq. 1 (Fig. 3C and SI Appendix, Fig. S6).

Our base case assumes an economic growth rate c¯=1.5 with the rate itself unaffected by climate change, an important assumption to probe in future work (60, 61). SI Appendix, Fig. S5A shows that varying it, while keeping EIS = 0.9, has little influence on prices. SI Appendix, Fig. S5 B and C, however, shows the large influence of EIS, regardless of assumed c¯. Note that EIS calibrations have changed widely over time, dependent on the type of risk modeled (62, 63). Modern comparable estimates range as high as 1.5 in a model with EZ preferences and consumption shocks (64), with significant implications for CO2 prices in early years. We choose a lower EIS = 0.9 for our base case, in part because the only shocks to consumption in our model stem from climate risk. Crucially, our model only captures societal risk. Epstein himself, writing with 2 coauthors, has since offered a potent critique of EZ preferences as applied to individual preferences (65).

Supplementary Material

Supplementary File

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments and discussions, we thank Jeffrey Bohn, V. V. Chari, Don Fullerton, Ken Gillingham, Christian Gollier, William Hogan, Christos Karydas, Dana Kiku, Gib Metcalf, Robert Socolow, Adam Storeygard, Christian Traeger, Martin Weitzman, Richard Zeckhauser, Stanley Zin, and seminar participants at American Economic Association meetings; the Environmental Defense Fund; ETH Zürich; Global Risk Institute; Harvard; the Journal of Investment Management conference; New York University; Tufts; University of Illinois Urbana–Champaign; and University of Minnesota. We also thank Oscar Sjogren, Weiyu Wan, and Shu Ye for helping prepare our code for distribution via https://gwagner.com/EZClimate.

Footnotes

The authors declare no competing interest.

This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.

This article contains supporting information online at www.pnas.org/lookup/suppl/doi:10.1073/pnas.1817444116/-/DCSupplemental.

References

  • 1.Nordhaus W. D., An optimal transition path for controlling greenhouse gases. Science 258, 1315–1319 (1992). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Nordhaus W. D., Revisiting the social cost of carbon. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 114, 1518–1523 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Nordhaus W., Evolution of modeling of the economics of global warming: Changes in the DICE model, 1992–2017. Clim. Change 148, 623–640 (2018). [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Stern N. H., The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, United Kingdom, 2007). [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Tol R. S., The economic effects of climate change. J. Econ. Perspect. 23, 29–51 (2009). [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Nordhaus W. D., Sztorc P., DICE 2013R: Introduction and User’s Manual (Yale University, New Haven, CT, 2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 7.National Academy of Sciences , Valuing Climate Damages: Updating Estimation of the Social Cost of Carbon Dioxide (National Academy of Sciences, Washington, DC, 2017). [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Burke M., et al. , Opportunities for advances in climate change economics. Science 352, 292–293 (2016). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Cai Y., Judd K. L., Lenton T. M., Lontzek T. S., Narita D., Environmental tipping points significantly affect the cost-benefit assessment of climate policies. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 112, 4606–4611 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Lontzek T. S., Cai Y., Judd K. L., Lenton T. M., Stochastic integrated assessment of climate tipping points indicates the need for strict climate policy. Nat. Clim. Chang. 5, 441–444 (2015). [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Cai Y., Lenton T. M., Lontzek T. S., Risk of multiple interacting tipping points should encourage rapid CO2 emission reduction. Nat. Clim. Change 6, 520–525 (2016). [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Cai Y., Lontzek T., The social cost of carbon with economic and climate risks. J. Polit. Econ. 10.1086/701890 (5 December 2018). [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Pindyck R. S., Climate change policy: What do the models tell us? J. Econ. Lit. 51, 860–872 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Stern N. H., The structure of economic modeling of the potential impacts of climate change: Grafting gross underestimation of risk onto already narrow science models. J. Econ. Lit. 51, 838–859 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Wagner G., Weitzman M. L., Climate Shock: The Economic Consequences of a Hotter Planet (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2015). [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Golosov M., Hassler J., Krusell P., Tsyvinski A., Optimal taxes on fossil fuel in general equilibrium. Econometrica 82, 41–88 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Shiller R., Irrational Exuberance (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2000). [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Mehra R., Prescott E. C., The equity premium: A puzzle. J. Monet. Econ. 15, 145–161 (1985). [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Weil P., The equity premium puzzle and the risk-free rate puzzle. J. Monet. Econ. 24, 401–421 (1989). [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Barro R. J., Rare disasters and asset markets in the twentieth century. Q. J. Econ. 121, 823–866 (2006). [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Martin I. W. R., On the valuation of long-dated assets. J. Polit. Econ. 120, 346–358 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Martin I. W. R., Disasters and the welfare cost of uncertainty. Am. Econ. Rev. 98, 74–78 (2008). [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Kreps D. M., Porteus E. L., Temporal resolution of uncertainty and dynamic choice theory. Econometrica 46, 185–200 (1978). [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Epstein L. G., Zin S. E., Substitution, risk aversion, and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: A theoretical framework. Econometrica 57, 937–969 (1989). [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Epstein L. G., Zin S. E., Substitution, risk aversion, and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: An empirical analysis. J. Polit. Econ. 99, 263–286 (1991). [Google Scholar]
  • 26.Weil P., Nonexpected utility in macroeconomics. Q. J. Econ. 105, 29–42 (1990). [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Barro R. J., Ursúa J. F., Stock-market crashes and depressions. Res. Econ. 71, 384–398 (2017). [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Ackerman F., Stanton E. A., Bueno R., Epstein–Zin utility in DICE: Is risk aversion irrelevant to climate policy? Environ. Resour. Econ. 56, 73–84 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Crost B., Traeger C. P., Optimal CO2 mitigation under damage risk valuation. Nat. Clim. Change 4, 631–636 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Hambel C., Kraft H., Schwartz E., Optimal carbon abatement in a stochastic equilibrium model with climate change, (NBER Working Paper 21044, National Bureau of Economic Research, Cambridge, MA, 2018).
  • 31.Jensen S., Traeger C. P., Optimal climate change mitigation under long-term growth uncertainty: Stochastic integrated assessment and analytic findings. Eur. Econ. Rev. 69, 104–125 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Lemoine D., Traeger C., Watch your step: Optimal policy in a tipping climate. Am. Econ. J. Econ. Policy 6, 137–166 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Pindyck R. S., Wang N., The economic and policy consequences of catastrophes. Am. Econ. J. Econ. Policy 5, 306–339 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Traeger C. P., Analytic Integrated Assessment and Uncertainty (Working paper, 2015). https://ssrn.com/abstract=2667972.
  • 35.Lemoine D., Rudik I., Managing climate change under uncertainty: Recursive integrated assessment at an inflection point. Annu. Rev. Resour. Econ. 9, 117–142 (2017). [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Cox J. C., Ross S. A., Rubinstein M., Option pricing: A simplified approach. J. Financ. Econ. 7, 229–263 (1979). [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Summers L., Zeckhauser R., Policymaking for posterity. J. Risk Uncertain. 37, 115–140 (2008). [Google Scholar]
  • 38.National Research Council , Climate Intervention: Carbon Dioxide Removal and Reliable Sequestration (National Academies Press, Washington, DC, 2015). [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Lenton T. M., et al. , Tipping elements in the earth’s climate system. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 105, 1786–1793 (2008). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Kopp R. E., Shwom R., Wagner G., Yuan J., Tipping elements and climate-economic shocks: Pathways toward integrated assessment. Earth’s Future 4, 346–372 (2016). [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Ulph A., Ulph D., The optimal time path of a carbon tax. Oxf. Econ. Pap. 46, 857–868 (1994). [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Acemoglu D., Aghion P., Bursztyn L., Hemous D., The environment and directed technical change. Am. Econ. Rev. 102, 131–166 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Lemoine D., Rudik I., Steering the climate system: Using inertia to lower the cost of policy. Am. Econ. Rev. 107, 2947–2957 (2017). [Google Scholar]
  • 44.Lemoine D., The climate risk premium. (Working Paper 15-01, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ, 2015). [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Gillingham K., Stock J. H., The cost of reducing greenhouse gas emissions. J. Econ. Perspect. 32, 53–72 (2018). [Google Scholar]
  • 46.Gillingham K., Palmer K., Bridging the energy efficiency gap: Policy insights from economic theory and empirical evidence. Rev. Environ. Econ. Policy 8, 18–38 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Allcott H., Greenstone M., Is there an energy efficiency gap? J. Econ. Perspect. 26, 3–28 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  • 48.McKinsey , Pathways to a low-carbon economy version 2 of the global greenhouse gas abatement cost curve (McKinsey & Company, Stockholm, 2009). [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Mankiw N. G., Weinzierl M., Yagan D., Optimal taxation in theory and practice. J. Econ. Perspect. 23, 147–174 (2009). [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Goulder L. H., Environmental taxation and the double dividend: A reader’s guide. Int. Tax Publ. Financ. 2, 157–183 (1995). [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Jorgenson D. W., Goettle R. J., Ho M. S., Wilcoxen P. J., Double Dividend: Environmental Taxes and Fiscal Reform in the United States (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 2013). [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Keith D. W., Holmes G., St. Angelo D., Heidel K., A process for capturing CO2 from the atmosphere. Joule 2, 1573–1594 (2018). [Google Scholar]
  • 53.International Energy Agency , “World energy outlook” (Tech. Rep., International Energy Agency, Paris, 2013).
  • 54.Pindyck R. S., Uncertain outcomes and climate change policy. J. Environ. Econ. Manag. 63, 289–303 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Weitzman M. L., On modeling and interpreting the economics of catastrophic climate change. Rev. Econ. Stat. 91, 1–19 (2009). [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Roe G. H., Bauman Y., Climate sensitivity: Should the climate tail wag the policy dog? Clim. Change 117, 647–662 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  • 57.Hsiang S., et al. , Estimating economic damage from climate change in the United States. Science 356, 1362–1369 (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58.Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change , “Fifth assessment report: Climate change” (Tech. Rep., Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Geneva, 2013).
  • 59.Schroyen F., Aarbu K. O., Attitudes towards large income risk in welfare states: An international comparison. Economica 85, 846–872 (2018). [Google Scholar]
  • 60.Bansal R., Ochoa M., Kiku D., “Climate change and growth risks” (NBER Working Paper 23009, National Bureau of Economic Research, Cambridge, MA, 2016). [Google Scholar]
  • 61.Heal G., Park J., Temperature stress and the direct impact of climate change: A review of an emerging literature. Rev. Environ. Econ. Policy 10, 1–17 (2016). [Google Scholar]
  • 62.Thimme J., Intertemporal substitution in consumption: A literature review. J. Econ. Surv. 31, 226–257 (2017). [Google Scholar]
  • 63.Havránek T., Measuring intertemporal substitution: The importance of method choices and selective reporting. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 13, 1180–1204 (2015). [Google Scholar]
  • 64.Bansal R., Yaron A., Risks for the long run: A potential resolution of asset pricing puzzles. J. Financ. 59, 1481–1509 (2004). [Google Scholar]
  • 65.Epstein L. G., Farhi E., Strzalecki T., How much would you pay to resolve long-run risk? Am. Econ. Rev. 104, 2680–2697 (2014). [Google Scholar]

Associated Data

This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

Supplementary Materials

Supplementary File

Articles from Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America are provided here courtesy of National Academy of Sciences

RESOURCES