Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2020 Oct 9.
Published in final edited form as: Neuron. 2019 Oct 9;104(1):25–36. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2019.09.017

The Life of Behavior

Alex Gomez-Marin 1,*, Asif A Ghazanfar 2,3,*
PMCID: PMC6873815  NIHMSID: NIHMS1543024  PMID: 31600513

Abstract

Neuroscience needs behavior. However, it is daunting to render the behavior of living organisms intelligible without suppressing most, if not all, references to life. When animals are treated as passive stimulus-response disembodied identical machines, the life of behavior perishes. Here we distill three biological principles —materiality, agency, and historicity—, spell out their consequences for the study of animal behavior, and illustrate them with various examples from the literature. We propose to put behavior back into context: with the brain in a species-typical body and with the animal's body situated in the world; to stamp Newtonian time with nested ontogenetic and phylogenetic processes that give rise to individuals with their own histories; and to supplement lineal cause-and-effect chains and information processing with circular loops of purpose and meaning. We believe that conceiving behavior in these ways is imperative for neuroscience.

In brief.

When animals are treated as identical, disembodied, passive stimulus-response machines, the life of behavior perishes. Gomez-Marin and Ghazanfar distill three biological principles—materiality, agency, and historicity—and elaborate upon their consequences for the neuroscience of behavior.

Introduction

Living systems have self-sustaining properties that distinguish them from inert physical systems (Goldenfeld et al., 2017; Longo and Montévil, 2012; Maturana and Varela, 1987). They are typically composed of cells, maintain a stable internal state (homeostasis) by converting food into usable energy (metabolism), and they grow and reproduce. Energy is acquired by the organism to keep its entropy low, defying for a time the inexorable march of the Second Law of Thermodynamics. The morphology and physiology of living organisms facilitate their ability to acquire energy for sustenance. Constrained by morphology and physiology, another self-sustaining property of living systems is adaptive behavior. Behavioral strategies that improve an individual’s ability to acquire energy, and convert it to produce successful offspring, ultimately help its lineage proliferate over evolutionary time through the process of natural selection (Pontzer, 2015). The latter is the ultimate goal of every animal (Darwin, 2004). This goal-directedness of animal behaviors is a feature that is absent in purely physical systems (Dawkins, 1976; Mayr, 1997; Wilson, 2000).

In the following, we will distill three essential principles for biological behavior. For each one, we will first provide its theoretical articulation followed by illustrative examples in the domain of behavior. The three principles are a subset of features arguably unique to life. We claim their necessity to understanding living organisms and reformulate them as fundamental principles in behavior rather than as mere characteristics. The principles are: (i) materiality, (ii) agency and (iii) historicity. Behaviorally, they account for the constitutive role of: (1) morphology and environment, (2) action-perception closed-loops and purpose, and (3) individuality and historical contingencies. These factors make up “the life of behavior”. We hope that these considerations will shed light on our typical approach to understanding the mechanisms of behavior and why it is inadequate. We will elaborate upon this later but here’s a summary.

First, we often presume that the mechanisms of behavior will come more sharply into relief if the context in which the animal is placed is sterile (like a vat: e.g., fMRI scanner, Skinner box, empty Petri dish, monkey chair), if the stimuli presented to the animal were simplistic and passively delivered (e.g., oriented lines, tone-pips, tastants), and with the body considered simply as a container for the brain or the passive interface for the brain to control (body as another vat). The presumption is that by doing so, many variables are controlled for, and thus factored out, so that one can focus on just the neural or other physiological data (Figure 1A). However, there is no avoiding the fact that body and brain are inseparable in their function (Chiel and Beer, 1997; Tytell et al., 2011), and that they operate in a world that is unique to the organism under study (Thompson and Cosmelli, 2011; Von Uexküll, 2013)(Figure 1B,C). Second, we often take up the formulation that perception and action are the beginning and end of a lineal process, a stimulus-response arc or “sensorimotor transformation” (Figure 1D). The organism, however, has goals (energetics, survival, reproduction) and agency (it initiates actions, rather than just respond to "irritations"). Its behavior is more akin to a control loop with inputs modifying outputs which in turn modify the next set of inputs, etc., to achieve a life-sustaining goal (Figure 1E,F). Finally, behaviors are variable. This is inconvenient to the scientist, but averaging across trials and groups of animals eschews the individual (Gallistel et al., 2004). Along the same lines, repeatedly presenting the same input signals in a temporally structured manner in order to repeatedly produce the same motor output obscures the fact that, in the real world, no such thing could ever occur (Figure 1G). From the perspective of the animal, variable motor outputs are the means by which to achieve invariant perceptions which can satisfy the animal's goals (Bell, 2014; Powers, 1973). Specific goals are not static but vary in time and each animal has a history on multiple timescales that determine its behavior (Figure 1H,I).

Figure 1. Accounting for the Life of Behavior.

Figure 1.

What “vats”, “arcs”, and “stats” miss (top part), and three fundamental principles (bottom part) for the behavior of living organisms: materiality, agency and historicity. Panels (A-C) concern embodiment and meaningful space. Panels (D-F) deal with causality and real time. Panels (G-I) depict concrete history and individuality. (A) Within the pervasive (and at times pernicious) information processing metaphor, life is nothing but information run in dull mater as disposable hardware. (B) Yet, the brain is embodied and the body is not a mere neural placeholder. (C) Moreover, the brain and its body live in the real world, under the constraints of physical surroundings (Umgebung) but also in the meaningful environment of the animal (Umwelt). In sum, materiality matters. (D) Inertia is the default state of inert objects, whose motion is the result of reactive push-pull forces. Along with (A), brains are computers that transform stimuli into responses, which are equated with behavior. (E) However, beyond lineal causality, a feedback loop goes through the world and back. Behavior then is not simple production of “output” but rather control of “input”. (F) Servomechanisms fail to do justice to the fact that animals are proactive and have purposes in mind. Agency is intrinsic to life. (G) Having de-contextualized space (A) and linearized time (D), the study of behavior falls prey to the “manipulate and measure” approach, where variability is deemed noise to be tamed with statistics. (H) Yet, from the perspective of the animal, variable output serves to achieve intended invariant inputs. Living beings harness stochasticity. (I) These iterative processes take place on multiple nested timescales, from actual-genesis, to onto-genesis to phylo-genesis. Animals are individuals.

An integrative example: Tool use in chimpanzees.

Chimps use sticks to gather honey, termites and ants from the ground or trees in order to eat them without getting stung, bit or pinched (Whiten et al., 1999). We can use this behavior to illustrate how materiality, agency and historicity contribute to an explanation. The goal of tool-using in this case is to acquire energy. This goal belongs to a hierarchy of goals: a higher level than having enough energy is the goal of not-dying; a level below acquiring energy is the goal of finding a tool, and then using it properly, which in turn entails the goal of approaching the potential food source. Levels above answer why; the levels below answer how. Depending on the task (breaking, prodding or collecting), the stick can be held in various ways including the precision grip (that is, between any two fingers but without the use of the palm). This illustrates an equifinality: chimps will diverge in the means but converge in the goal. To perform a precision grip requires specific hand biomechanics (e.g., thumbs that rotate around a joint (Napier and Napier, 1985)). All Old World primates (and one New World monkey) can perform a precision grip; other animals cannot. Tool use also requires specialized neural circuitry operating in conjunction with those biomechanics in a goal-directed manner: The precision grip is correlated with extensive cortico-motoneuronal terminations in the ventral horn of the spinal cord (Bortoff and Strick, 1993; Lemon and Griffiths, 2005), and motor planning and coordination are associated with neocortical areas 2 and 5, which are enlarged in tool-using primates (Padberg et al., 2005). Finally, tool use is also a learned behavior; young chimpanzees learn by watching older chimpanzees combined with trial-and-error (Tomasello et al., 1987). Thus, tool use is a behavior bound to the body and brain circuits, and that emerges on evolutionary and developmental timescales.

In the analysis of tool use behavior, the body and the environment can't be added later. They may be literally peripheral, but not conceptually. The behavior only emerges because of the organism's worldly and bodily activities. In terms of the world, for example, chimpanzee populations exhibit differences in ant-foraging as tree branches usable as tools for gathering ants are present at some sites but not in others (Whiten et al., 1999). Even the species of ants can influence tool use (Möbius et al., 2008; Schöning et al., 2008); more aggressive ant species, for instance, necessitate longer tools by chimpanzees to avert biting of their hands (Humle, 2011). In light of all this exquisitely rich evidence about the myriad of spatial and temporal dimensions that constitute tool use in chimps, one may wonder to what extent a purely neural explanation of such behavior—one that would successfully map its circuitry completely and exhaustively dissect all the so-called necessary and sufficient neurons involved; something not too far, it seems, from the neuroscientist’s dream (Dawkins 1976)—could become an explanation of the behavior (Krakauer et al., 2017).

Now, we will elaborate upon each of the three principles of life as they relate to behavior.

Part I — Materiality: Brains enjoy an embodied life in the real world

Natural behaviors are inescapably contingent on context (space) and history (time). The “space” for any animal is its body and environment. This context is explanatorily inseparable from the content; it is always constitutive of the behavioral phenomenon itself. Attempting to control the space by placing animal (Skinner box, restraint chair, or using an “anesthetized” preparation) or human (e.g., fMRI scanner) in an “impoverished” arena, while delivering isolated, reduced and/or arbitrary sensory signals to elicit stereotyped bodily actions, is effectively attempting to create a vat in which it is presumed that greater understanding of the brain and behavior will emerge. On the contrary, it is more like attempting to do the brain’s job for it. The brain has a body that evolved and developed together as a unit embedded in the world (Figure 1A).

The brain-body.

We typically treat the body as if it is simply the carrier of the brain, with the brain being the central computing device for processing unfiltered inputs from the outside to generate platonic forms of motor outputs. What we forget is that the body, and its species-typical structure, is constitutive in this process. Different parts of the body act as filters for both incoming and outgoing signals (Chiel and Beer, 1997; Tytell et al., 2011). Thus, the way we interact with the environment—the way we acquire sensorimotor knowledge—is in part inextricably dependent upon the shape of our bodies (Noë, 2004). Animals with differently shaped bodies interact with the world differently and thus acquire behavioral capacities in different ways. This is not just about differences, however: Without a body, behavior and cognition are impossible (Brooks, 1991).

Every part of a species’ anatomy potentially exhibits both species-specific specializations as well as individually-specific variation. The outer ear, for instance, is extremely variable in size, shape and mobility even among just primates and these factors determine how one hears (Fleagle, 2013). In nocturnal primates that rely primarily on hearing to catch prey, the ears are very large (relative to head size) and mobile. Mobility is conferred through a special set of muscles. In humans, the ear is small and does not move very much. The shape of the ear—its ridges and valleys—filter sounds before they hit the eardrum (Batteau, 1967). Critically, which parts of a given sound get louder or softer according to this filtering also depend on whether the sound is hitting the outer ear from above or below. Through learning, we learn to associate those acoustic differences with the vertical location of the sound source.

The constitutive role of our bodies’ physical conformation to behavior and experience is reflected in how it changes and guides the nervous system during development. Continuing with the ear example, we localize sounds well at a very young age but since our ears are still growing and changing shape, the developing brain must recalibrate itself to account for these bodily changes (King and Moore, 1991). Contrary to what one would assume, the neural circuits of the auditory system are dependent upon the shape of the ears to guide their function. Auditory cortical neurons in very young ferrets encode spatial location poorly (Mrsic-Flogel et al., 2003). The standard presumption to explain this poor tuning would be that the neural circuits are still developing (e.g., perhaps lacking refined inhibitory inputs) and/or need to time to be molded by experience. However, the coarse spatial tuning is actually because the shape of the ears (the body) is still developing and not yet adult-like. Experimentally providing the same young ferrets the ears of an adult (via virtual acoustics) can immediately drive those auditory cortical neurons to encode sound location with adult-like accuracy (Mrsic-Flogel et al., 2003). Thus, the developing body is guiding the sensory functions of the nervous system in this case, not the other way around.

The developing body also shapes motor output. Human newborns, for instance, are able to make well-coordinated stepping movements when held upright but these movements disappear by the time they reach ~2 months of age (Thelen et al., 1984). While it was assumed by many that the change in stepping behavior was due solely to the developing nervous system (e.g., the behavior disappeared because their was too much inhibition that had not been “pruned” back yet (McGraw, 1945)), Thelen and colleagues hypothesized that the loss of stepping behavior was due to body growth: the infants’ legs typically fatten up postnatally and they do not yet have the strength to move heavier legs. To test this hypothesis, they submerged the infants’ legs in water, effectively decreasing their mass. This resulted in the reappearance of stepping and thus falsified the alternative hypothesis that neural change was necessary (Thelen et al., 1984). The change in behavior was due to changes in the body.

Along similar lines, it would typically (and reasonably) be presumed that changes in vocal production over the course of development are the results of learning and, thus, changes in the nervous system. In growing marmoset monkeys, however, computational modeling and experiments placing infants in helium-oxygen environments revealed that, as lungs grow bigger, their changing sensory feedback onto vocal central pattern generators results in the disappearance of the production of context-inappropriate vocalizations without any need for concomitant changes in central nervous system structure (Zhang and Ghazanfar, 2018). The developing body can create distinct behavioral changes by itself and their reduce the computational and energetic burden on the nervous system (a strategy that is often exploited by roboticists (Pfeifer et al., 2007).

The Body-World.

All animals share a common world, however not all animals have a world in common. Each organism has its own "Umwelt" (meaningful environment) and not just an “Umgebung” (physical surroundings) (Von Uexküll, 2013). The Umwelt is a foundational concept in zoology, with theoretical implications for neuroscience's anthropomorphism (Gomez-Marin, 2019). Every animal species (and, within it, every individual) experiences the world differently. The world, considered as a physical fact, is the objective space in which we observe animals behave. As a biological fact, however, the relation between organism and environment is such that the former not only submits to the latter but actually carves it out. For psychologists, the Gibsonian translation is "affordance". It means, for example, that a stone is not simply a stone but a-stone-for-a-snail as an opportunity to climb, or a-stone-for-a-human as an opportunity to throw and hit something far way.

As scientists, no doubt, we can act on an organism. Umwelts (or “Umwelten”, in proper German) are not just parallel universes, they intersect: cut a tree, and the birds must leave. Yet, the physical excitation we present to animals as part of our experimental design not only needs to occur but it also has to be noticed. What the organism cares about is what it will attend to, thus dictating its perceptions (and the actions, by virtue of which it will manage those perceptions). In other words, the Umwelt is “an elective extraction from the Umgebung” (Canguilhem, 2008)(pg. 112). Paradoxically, in the typical behavioral or neuroscience experiment, the Umgebung (which is alien to the animal) is in turn nothing other than the Umwelt of the scientist (scientists are humans, and humans are also animals), who are operating in the symbolic universe of abstractions (coding, entropy, statistical significance, etc.). The Umwelt thus reveals a strong and concealed “conflict of interests” in biology. If behavior is a functional loop that is enacted in a meaningful context, then animals (the objects of study of the scientist) are also subjects (studied by other subjects: us). This creates what could be called “a clash of Umwelts”. The almost uncountable variety of worlds—all seemingly as far away from each other that they become almost non-overlapping, even incommunicable (Calvo, 2017; Nagel, 1974)—are actually in conflict with one another. What is meaningful from the point of view of the organism need not be from the point of view of the scientist studying it, and vice-versa. As Canguilhem puts it: “Hedgehogs as such do not cross roads….On the contrary, it is man-made roads that cross the hedgehog’s milieu.”(Canguilhem, 2008)(pg. 22)

The biology of animals thus poses a conundrum to the object-subject separation that allowed so much progress in physics in particular, and in science in general. The underlying mission of physics is to establish laws between objects that are valid regardless of the point of reference, which implies and necessitates the absence of any absolute center. Yet, biology is a historical science, whose objects of study are individuals. To be objective would then entail to decenter oneself (the scientist) while keeping the organism at the center. We neuroscientists, rightly concerned with anthropomorphism in our interpretations, should revisit the notion of objectivity in favor of zoomorphism: to study animal behavior from the perspective of the animal. This, of course, has immediate practical consequences for the design of our experiments. The use of artificial, “simplified” stimuli in behavioral and neural experimentation is common place (oriented lines, tones, moving dots, etc.) (Hauber et al., 2015; Rust and Movshon, 2005), but every choice made by us with our own goals in mind is making assumptions about the perception and goals of the animal under study. A paradigmatic example is when a scientist says that "no stimuli were presented to the animal" (an approach that seeks to control or limit sensory experience), whereas any human prisoner in isolation knows that there can hardly be a bigger perceptual experience than that.

Lahti (Lahti, 2015) dubbed these assumptions about what an animal may or may not care about as the “Umwelt gamble”. By gambling, one ignores the fact that animals are biased towards certain modalities and signals within them, and may interpret such signals in a way an experimenter cannot guess at. Even the manner in which we mark individuals for purely identification purposes (e.g., collars, tags, dyes, bands) can influence behavioral patterns that we may think are isolated only to the experimental variables of our own choose. For example, a study in which male zebra finch were individually identified through the use of colored leg-bands (a widely used practice) unexpectedly found that those leg-bands influenced female choice (Burley et al., 1982). Similarly, unexpected influences of colors occur in humans as well. Across a range of sports, wearing red is consistently associated with a higher probability of winning indicating that we respond to different colors differently without even realizing it (Hill and Barton, 2005). It is thus more appropriate to conceive the world as a forum for action than as a place of things.

Umwelts are not only unique to species, but they are unique to individuals as well. How you engage with the world is different from how others do, and this difference, of course, can be related to an individual’s body in non-trivial ways. For example, in both the visual and auditory domains, objects with a looming motion towards an observer (i.e., are rapidly approaching versus receding) have a perceptual priority. When observers are asked to estimate the arrival of looming sound sources, for instance, they consistently respond too early, perceiving them as closer than they actually are (Rosenblum et al., 1987). In a natural environment, this underestimation results in more time to act—evade or engage the source—and thus affords a “margin of safety” that may provide a selective advantage (Neuhoff et al., 2012). This idea is consistent with comparative work on the perceptual biases towards looming sounds (Ghazanfar et al., 2002; Maier et al., 2004), and with neuroimaging data showing that looming sounds preferentially activate motor planning areas (Seifritz et al., 2002). However, perceiving and acting in response to looming sounds depend not only on perceptual abilities and the neural activity it elicits, but also on the motor capabilities of the listener. Listeners with less physical strength and lower aerobic fitness respond sooner to looming sounds and with a larger margin of safety than listeners in better health (Neuhoff et al., 2012). This shows that, within a species, the Umwelt and the individual body form a system that enables adaptive behavior.

Note that, like the world itself, the individual body changes over time and, as a result, so does an individual’s Umwelt and the behavior exhibited. In human infancy, for example, there are changes in the ways the body moves in and interacts with the environment (e.g., sitting up to crawling to walking). These changes, in turn, impact the development of skills and experiences that play a role in the emergence of other behaviors such communication (Iverson, 2010). Learning to sit upright without support allows deeper breathing that increases the power for producing longer, less noisy vocalizations like babbling (consonant-vowel combinations) (Yingling, 1982). The production of babbling results in more frequent contingent responses from caregivers (Gros-Louis et al., 2006), which acts as a ratchet for further vocal learning by the infant (Goldstein and Schwade, 2008), and thus leading to new forms of communication with increasing complexity. An infant that can sit up has also changed the way she observes the world and engages with caregivers (e.g., joint attention), now being able to freely rotate the head and trunk. Moreover, the hands are now more able to grasp and manipulate objects, providing greater opportunities to share with caregivers who, in turn, facilitate further communicative development (e.g., by naming objects held by infants) (Iverson, 2010). In these scenarios, caregivers (part of the Umwelt) adjust to the infant’s changing behavior. The developing body and motor skill acquisition results in an ever-changing meaningful environment.

Part II — Agency: Behavior is not an arc, but a loop in service of a goal

It may seem like a truism to claim that behavior is the ultimate output of the nervous system. Although it is difficult to define what constitutes “behavior” (Levitis et al., 2009), most would argue that it is some sort of “output”. Having access to the neural level does not modify this position (Gomez-Marin, 2017). Even Tinbergen (Tinbergen, 1951), one of the founders of ethology, defined behaviors as the “total movements made by the intact animal”. Typically, this end-product is considered the result of a sensory-motor transformation. “Behavior” in the form of this arc then allows the experimenter to vary the sensory inputs (manipulate) and observe the motor output (measure) to estimate a “transfer function” of behavior, followed by an investigation of the neural mechanisms that may be the implementation this computation (Calhoun and Murthy, 2017).

A first caveat with this methodological "manipulate & measure" ideology is the inapplicability of the assumption "all else being equal". We set up our experiments and interpret the data under the scruple that the results are valid under that assumption. But there is no ceteris paribus in biology (Figure 2). This means we cannot copy and paste the conceptual presuppositions and experimental approaches we use in physics (Figure 2A). Experimentation in behavior needs to account for, first, the specificity of different animal forms across species (Figure 2B), second, the diversity of individuals within species (Figure 2C), third, the totality of the organism and its environment (Figure 2D), and finally, the irreversibility of lived experience (Figure 2E). We will come back to some of these points later.

Figure 2. There is no “ceteris paribus” in experimental behavioral biology.

Figure 2.

The principle “the same produces the same” is inapplicable in experimental biology since the covert assumption “other other things being equal” actually fails. (A) Inert systems can be treated as indistinguishable —they have no history, no agency, no personality, (B) Despite the existence of common biological mechanisms and shared principles of behavior, humans are not a collage of a handful of laboratory animals. Organisms with fewer neurons are not necessarily “simpler” organisms either. And “organism models” are not “model organisms” (Katz, 2016). (C) Laboratory wild-type animals are often everything but wild, nor exact controls for transgenic animals. Average group behavior may not coincide with any of the behavior of the individuals in that group. Individuality is real and relevant. (D) Behavior studied in animals whose bodies and worlds have been truncated can be misleading and not generalize (the behavior of a paralytic cat in an empty arena is far from cat behavior). (E) During development, animals undergo major changes not only in their behavior but also in their bodies. Despite our sequential measurements, behavior is generated serially. History matters.

There is a second related conceptual caveat to the behavioral arc: once the animal is engaged, the supposedly independent variable (sensory input) is not independent anymore; the output feeds back and, together with the stimulus, both constitute the input to the organism, producing the output again. Thus, behavior is not linearly causal as the sensory-motor transformation idea implies. The motor response influences the subsequent sensory input, the sensory input determines the motor response. Behavior is a loop, not an arc. Or as John Dewey (Dewey, 1896) wrote more than 120 years ago, “What we have is a circuit, not an arc or broken segment of a circle”. The so-called “read out”, conceived as the result of the operations of the brain matter upon something we experimenters “write in”, reflects a covert anthropomorphism: what the animal does is what we see, and what it sees is what we do. Behavior is something more than this lineal sensory-motor transformation inscribed in a stimulus-response phenomenon. It is circularly causal, consistent with the cybernetics idea put forth by Wiener (Wiener, 1949) and later advocated by others (e.g., (Ahissar and Assa, 2016; Churchland et al., 1994; Powers, 1973)). Behavior is, to a great extent, the control of perception (Powers, 1973). Namely, living beings have life-sustaining intentions (fleeing, fighting, feeding and reproducing) and they behave in order to satisfy them. Perceiving the consequences of their actions is the only way they can know, and so it is actually the only thing animals care about. In other words, for an animal, its output means little if it does not control, in some way, its input.

The essence of the problem thus stems from a simple but subtle confusion, a conflation of space with time. What comes in (which certainly must be called input) is not what comes first (the so-called stimulus), nor does what comes out (output) constitute what is last (response). The notion of “stimulus” implicitly postulates the beginning of the whole situation, which is only so from the experimenter’s point of view. Here are examples of behaviors cast in the light of behavior loops instead of arcs.

Robbing and dodging rats.

Social interactions are often considered as complex behaviors requiring complex mechanisms, and as social group size increases it is typically believed that greater amounts of neural resources must be dedicated to such behaviors (Dunbar, 1998) (though the validity of these ideas has been increasing called in to question; see (Barrett et al., 2007; DeCasien et al., 2017; González-Forero and Gardner, 2018)). Cybernetic approaches to social interactions reveal that seemingly complex behaviors can arise through simple rules and thus don’t require increasing amounts of computational power (Barrett et al., 2007; Pellis and Bell, 2011). For example, rats are social animals and one consequence of that is that they must protect their food from other rats that want to steal it. “Robbing and dodging” in rats involves one animal (the dodger) possessing a small piece of food, and another animal (the robber) attempting to acquire the food (Bell and Pellis, 2011; Whishaw, 1988). The robber approaches the head of the dodger, and the dodger evades by swerving laterally away. Given the apparent correlation between the angle swept through by the dodger to evade the robber and both the type of food being consumed and the identity of the robber, this food protection behavior seems to be an excellent system in which to study a complex, ethologically-relevant aspect of rat social cognition. In this view, the dodging rat must calculate the angular displacement of their swerve away from the robber, calculate the time it takes to eat a piece of food and take into account the robber’s identity, distance and speed. This seems like exceedingly complex cognition given that rats make dodging decisions and movements in fractions of a second and most often do so successfully. Because we are fascinated (as one should) by the complexity of the brain, we have no difficulties in ascribing really difficult “computations” to it.

An alternative hypothesis—a closed-loop hypothesis—is that the dodger’s goal in such a context is simply to maintain a constant distance from the robber (Bell and Pellis, 2011). Any behavioral change with regard to food type/eating time could be accomplished by simply decreasing or increasing the inter-animal distance. Such a rule would eliminate the need to perform complex and time-consuming computations by only considering the maintenance of a constant distance between two animals, as opposed to the calculation of a dodge angle based on more elaborate information. If this closed-loop hypothesis is correct, then dodger angle should be a compensatory action in order to maintain the controlled variable (inter-animal distance). In light of this hypothesis, a new analysis of food protection behavior revealed that the dodger moved to maintain a set distance from the robber (regardless of the robber’s movements) and that the “distance” was far less variable than “dodger angle” (Bell and Pellis, 2011). Moreover, context cues such as food type and the identity of the robber had the simple effect of increasing or decreasing the inter-animal distance that needed to be achieved by the dodging rat. [Note: for highly quantitative study illuminating how motor variability serves perceptual constancy in the domain of touch, see (Saraf-Sinik et al., 2015)).

Vocal turn-taking in marmoset monkeys.

Here is another example where seemingly complex behaviors are accounted for by simple closed-loop heuristics. One way to enhance signal quality during communication is to prevent interference through taking turns. By pausing after transmission, a sender allows signals from other individuals to transpire and be heard before another signal is emitted. The elimination of overlap via turn-taking increases the likelihood of the signal being heard accurately. As a consequence, an exchange of signals between two or more individuals has a structure. A successful instance of human vocal turn-taking, for example, would involve person 1 speaking while person 2 attends, followed by a response from person 2, be it a statement or an indication for person 1 to continue speaking. These rules are universal for human conversations (Stivers et al., 2009). It has been argued that this human cooperative vocal communication is unique and requires complex cognitive traits like mind-reading (shared intentionality) not observed in other primate species (Tomasello, 2008).

An alternative hypothesis is that vocal turn-taking (particularly, in nonhuman primates) is a closed-loop behavior with the goal of maintaining social contact (a form of “grooming at a distance” (Kulahci et al., 2015)). A study of the vocal exchanges of a small New World primate, the marmoset monkey (Callithrix jacchus) showed that they will participate in contact call exchanges with any conspecific and that these exchanges have a temporal structure that is similar to the turn-taking rules that humans use (Stivers et al., 2009; Takahashi et al., 2013): rare interruptions and a consistent silent interval between utterances. However, there is no evidence that marmosets have any mind-reading skills like humans. Evidence that humans engaged in turn-taking are in a closed-loop includes that there is (i) periodic coupling in the timing of utterances across two interacting individuals and (ii) entrainment, where if the timing of one individual’s vocal output quickens or slows, the other’s follows suit (Chapple, 1970; Oullier et al., 2008; Schmidt and Morr, 2010). The vocal exchanges of marmoset monkeys share both of these features (Takahashi et al., 2013).

Consistent with the idea that turn-taking is driven by the goal of social contact, humans adjust the amplitude of their voices as a function of distance from a listener; we do so in a manner that would compensate for such distance (Pelegrín-García et al., 2011). Again, this ability is presumed to be the product of high-level sociocognitive skills, like theory of mind. Nonhuman primates like marmoset monkeys were thought to lack such socially-related flexibility in vocal production. However, based on the predictions from a simple model whereby vocal feedback from a conspecific modulates the drive to produce a vocalization (Takahashi et al., 2012), it was hypothesized that they should readily be able to exhibits this type of cooperative vocal control. A playback experiment revealed that marmoset monkeys, like humans, increased the amplitude of their contact calls—and produced such calls with shorter response latencies—towards more distant conspecifics (Choi et al., 2015). Cooperative vocal control appears to be a simple system property with the goal of social contact that does not necessitate any particularly advanced socio-cognitive computations.

It is important to note that just “closed-loops” are not sufficient. For example, Braitenberg vehicles are passive-reactive machines with simple circuits in a closed-loop with signals in the environment that, via our reflexive anthropomorphism, seem like they have goals and desires but obviously do not (Braitenberg, 1986). Exquisite mimesis does not qualify as living (Rosen, 2000). Real biological organisms, from bacteria to giraffes, need to move forward in the world. Moving, in turn, implies decision-making: to move there and not here. Perception can be conceptualized as closed-loop convergence processes (Ahissar and Assa, 2016). One needs to decide what to look at. And, to see, one needs to look. One cannot hear if one does not listen. The study of behavior must then confer proactivity and subjectivity to their objects of study, as well as real purpose. This is possible by erecting a principle extending the physical principle of inertia: agency. The inertial view of nature applied to living beings reads: things do not change by themselves; one must push them so that they push back. This assumes (whether intentionally or not) that behavior operates via a passive mechanism. But animals are agents capable of producing actions, not just responses. They are pro-active, not re-active. They anticipate using memory.

Part III —Historicity: living organisms are individuals

Behavioral variability is always deemed as noise to a first approximation (Figure 1G). This reflects our drive to go from concrete instances to universal claims. The standard is to reproduce and replicate. Yet, the relatively neat assumption that “everything else is being kept equal” becomes particularly problematic for behavior because every moment of behavior is the result of a unique history, a history that has unfolded on many different timescales. In physics, we often seek a-temporal relationships amongst universals (rather than particulars), and perceive that what is of real importance is to be found in general laws and normative explanations of behavior. But, what if behavioral variability is not an inescapable “bug” of biology that scientists must contend with but an adaptive feature? Variability is perhaps the ability to vary rather than the “nausea” (noise, etymologically) of the scientist not being able to make sense of the system. Above, we argued that motor variability serves perceptual constancy (and not the other way around). A strong corollary of the principle of historicity is twofold: the lack of (i) genericity in biological objects —two electrons are interchangeable, two homozygotic twins are not—, and (ii) specificity of biological trajectories (Longo and Montévil, 2012). Like the different spatial scales of the Umwelt, biological historicity plays out on different nested timescales, and the variability that is generated from an individual’s history writ large seems more functional than noisy.

In fact, methodological approaches that specifically try to reduce or eliminate phenotypic variability are disappointing when considered carefully. For example, much of neuroscience uses inbred strains of mice housed in uniform environments. The motivation behind this is based on the notion that there are genetic mechanisms that should yield the persistence of certain phenotypes in the face of environmental factors that cannot be controlled for (revisit Figure 2). However, this turns out to be impossible. When the spontaneous homecage behavior of commonly-used inbred mice, raised under identical conditions, were measured using automated procedures, there was substantial variability (Loos et al., 2015). Moreover, across different strains of inbred mice, there were different levels of variability: Some strains where much higher in their behavior variability than others. This is important because one might have suggested that the within-strain variability was just unaccounted for environmental factors or related to the stochastic effects of physical laws at the molecular level (e.g., inter-molecular interactions subjected to thermodynamic instability) (Honegger and de Bivort, 2018), but this would not explain systematic across-strain differences. In fact, it suggests that behavioral variability is built into the system. In support of this, a study of inbred lines of Drosophila was used to address the variability of locomotor “handedness” (the tendency to turn left or right in a y-maze) (Ayroles et al., 2015). Like the mice strains, there was considerable variability in the trait and the amount of variability was linked to different genotypes. By crossing flies with measured levels of handedness variability, the degree of variability was shown to be heritable. Even behaviors that appear as reflexes show heritable variability, such as the startle response in zebrafish (Pantoja et al., 2016) or in the parthenogenetic pea aphid whose clonal daughters show variation in leaping-from versus clinging-to vegetation (Schuett et al., 2011).

These data show that evolution has not selected out the mechanisms that generate behavioral variability (and thus, individuality) but rather it has selected for them. Behavioral variability is advantageous because the environment is unpredictable and thus an individual’s Umwelt may not be exactly the same as its parents’ Umwelt. Built-in behavior variability ensures that at least some individuals may be able to thrive under a novel set of conditions—a form of bet-hedging (Honegger and de Bivort, 2018).

Behavior and its neurobiology are not only the product of evolutionary processes but developmental ones as well (Gould, 1977). Evolution acts on developmental processes to produce adult phenotypes. Changing developmental trajectories is the only way to evolve phenotypic changes. More pointedly, adaptive behaviors that are learned initially can drive evolution of developmental processes that include the modification of genes. For example, if the goals of any organism (reproduction, survival) were enhanced by a new behavior acquired through learning, then the differential survival of those individuals might be enhanced by skipping the time it takes for the learning to occur by assimilating the process during development. This is known as the “Baldwin effect” (Baldwin, 1896). For example, human populations with a tradition of raising domesticated animals for milk production have acquired lactose tolerance via the evolution of developmental changes (including genetic changes) that keep the lactase enzyme active during adulthood (Laland et al., 2010). Dairy culture increases the selective advantage for this trait.

In contrast, some features of a meaningful world change rapidly or encompass a broad range. In those cases, it is most adaptive for every individual to retain some form of development plasticity as opposed to evolving a built-in mechanism. Human infants, for example, show perceptual abilities that are broadly tuned but as development proceeds these abilities become narrower in scope as a function of experience (Lewkowicz and Ghazanfar, 2009). In the domain of speech, young infants can discriminate between native and nonnative phonetic contrasts but that older infants can only discriminate between contrasts that are present in their native language. Six- to 8-month-old English-learning infants can discriminate nonnative consonants, such as the Hindi retroflex /Da/ and the dental /da/, but that 10-12 month-old infants cannot (Werker and Tees, 1984). The general decline in the salience of nonnative phonetic contrasts is due to language-specific experience (Kuhl et al., 2003). A similar perceptual narrowing occurs for face, music and multisensory perception (Lewkowicz and Ghazanfar, 2009). There are, of course, neural correlates of experience-dependent behavioral development (e.g., (Gomez et al., 2017)), including the emergence of brain regions that are driven purely by culture (e.g., literacy; (Dehaene et al., 2010)). Thus, bet-hedging for robustness against changing environments can take the form of built-in variability (genetics as in fly handedness described above) and/or phenotypic plasticity (such as experience-dependent behavioral plasticity) (Honegger and de Bivort, 2018). Both phenomena operate on two timescales—species evolution and individual development—and are of a piece. For example, the increased behavioral and neural plasticity that humans exhibit relative to other primates is via evolutionary changes in gene expression that allow us to retain neural plasticity for a much longer period during a lifetime (Bufill et al., 2011; Somel et al., 2009).

Learning, plasticity and other responses to a changing environment are not restricted to developmental period. The history of behavior in real time counts as well. One can distinguish between phylo-genesis, onto-genesis and actual-genesis (Gomez-Marin et al., 2016). Every behavior carries with it not only the dynamics of the immediate performance but a momentum (i.e., hysteresis) (Hock et al., 1993). This real-time history is unaccounted for in most approaches to measuring behavior, where the start of a new measurement period is considered an isolated event. Typically, as the subject (human or animal) performs for a duration of time, no account for even basic phenomena such as body condition, fatigue or levels of satiety are considered. The implicit assumption is that they do not matter. As a result, we develop mistaken ideas about the underlying mechanisms. Although hysteresis effects are seen in perception (e.g., speech categorization (Tuller et al., 1994)), it’s most directly apparent in motor behavior. For example, in the A-not-B task, infants watch an experimenter hide an object in one location, A (Piaget, 1954). They are typically allowed to search for the object after a short delay, and this procedure is repeated some number of times. Infants then watch the experimenter hide the object in a new location, B. After this switch, infants often search perseveratively at A. Many cognitive and neural-based accounts were developed to explain this phenomenon including deficits in object representations, working memory and response inhibition as a result of immature prefrontal cortical development (Diamond and Goldman-Rakic, 1989). However, it turns out that the infant’s perseverative reaching to A on B trials is the result of their history of reaching to A: the likelihood of reaching to A on the B-trials is an increasing function of the number of past reaches to A (Smith et al., 1999). Hysteresis, of course, also accounts for the aftereffects observed following sensorimotor adaptation in reaching (Von Helmholtz, 1867) and speaking (Houde and Jordan, 1998). Even fundamental behavioral measures such as reaction times, typically thought to reflect the speed of computing decisions and preparing actions, are subject to history effects: Prior experience in one visuomotor task can speed up the reaction times in another task requiring a different movement strategy (Wong et al., 2017). Thus, reaction time is influenced by prior experience, and standard neural accounts of reaction time must be reconsidered.

Individual behaviors carry with them a history and build momentum; these accumulated histories constitute the stuff of learning and development change. Learning and developmental change can lead to differential engagement with the environment, a new Umwelt which in turn affects individual behaviors. “Habit, memory, learning, adaptation, and development form one seamless web built on process over time—activities in the real world” (Thelen and Smith, 1998). The organism (brain, body) changes over time (evolution, development, single-event) which changes its Umwelt (niche, affordances) which then modifies the organism (brain, body). It is perpetual change in a closed-loop, rolling towards a goal (survival, reproduction) while also unfolding —rather than unfurling— creatively (Bergson, 1907).

Every individual mouse, fly, monkey and human has a history that forges its behavior.

Summary

In Figure 1, we summarized three principles alien to inert behavior and that we think characterize the life of behavior: materiality (an embodied brain embedded in the world), agency (circular causality with the capacity to initiate actions in order to attain particular purposes) and historicity (individuality and individuation at multiple timescales). In Figure 2, we emphasized the inapplicability of a basic principle of scientific experimentation: the assumption of restoration of initial conditions, the "all else being equal" idea. Animals are particulars, not particles. These entail special difficulties to the biological object of study. Let us revisit those claims.

Part I. We neuroscientists have no problem acknowledging that brains need bodies, only to indefinitely postpone adding them to our mechanistic framework. The same is true with bodies embedded in the world. This is our main bias: We believe that the "real deal" is taking place inside the skull, and that all the rest is an add-on. As a result, our typical approach is to remove context (body, Umwelt) in order to distill content (information, algorithm) to then be able to predict the behavior in any context. A subtle philosophical distinction lies at the bottom of this: whether non-neural stufffacilitates or constitutes behavior. We hope we have convinced you that its role is constitutive. Materiality does not mean dull matter as a principle of the life of behavior, but rather the recognition of the meaningful lived world of the flesh.

Part II. In stressing that animals operate under circular causality, one could be tempted to conclude that what we need to do is to map animals to machines. Behavior would then be an engineering problem. Such a view would not grant animals with purpose, however. The life of behavior is circular causality towards a goal. William James made the distinction beautifully: "If now we pass from such actions as these to those of living things, we notice a striking difference. Romeo wants Juliet as the filings want the magnet; and if no obstacles intervene he moves towards her by as straight a line as they. But Romeo and Juliet, if a wall be built between them, do not remain idiotically pressing their faces against its opposite sides like the magnet and the filings with the card. Romeo soon finds a circuitous way, by scaling the wall or otherwise, of touching Juliet's lips directly. With the filings the path is fixed; whether it reaches the end depends on accidents. With the lover it is the end which is fixed, the path may be modified indefinitely" ((James, 1890), p.7). For the behavior of animals, the principle of inertia (and stimulus-response) should be rejected in favor of agency, generalizing “descent with modification” of species to individuals (Ana Soto, personal communication) and at all temporal scales. Finally, with respect to causality, there is an irresistible tendency by us to anthropomorphize it in the flavor of lineal causality, namely, counterfactuals (Gomez-Marin 2017). We tend to posit that the essence of behaving entails that what you do shall affect what will happen (and so what you will perceive), while still stubbornly insisting in studying loops by cutting-and-pasting them as a concatenation of arcs. We often accept as much as we ignore the circular nature of behavior.

Part III. When stressing the importance of history for living organisms, a quick reply could be that geology is also concerned with it (geology was, of course, a source of inspiration for Darwin). Yet nobody would claim that stones have personalities. There are indeed physical phenomena for which hysteresis is relevant. Yet, memory is different in kind in living beings. Also, and this is again an important truism, living beings come-into-being, and so ontogeny is crucial. No doubt that is also key at the phylogenetic timescale. It is ironic that evolution is often presented as an example where theory generalizes (like in physics), when what evolution (arguably the most important principle in biology) precisely teaches us is that "living stuff" is inherently historical and radically contextual (which is precisely the opposite of the basic presupposition that works for "inert stuff": an electron is just an electron, regardless of when or where it is observed). There is no "ceteris paribus" in biology. Historicity gives rise to individuality, and so the object of biology is specific, not generic.

Conclusion

The current approach to behavior and its mechanisms could be characterized as "the Frankenstein error" (Figure 3), or the failure of the principle that what can be taken apart can be put together. There is no putting things that were pulled apart back together again. In our current automatized and sterilized approaches to behavior, we ignore the body, remove it from its natural context, and stop time. Integrative biology of behavior is needed more than ever. Our previous efforts to correct a reductionist bias may have left the impression that what animals and their brains do is of less importance than what they are made of (a move towards “functionalism") (Krakauer et al., 2017). What if, instead of chess--a classic example in functionalism—one plays another game instead: pool (billiards)? In this game, functioning is not irrespective of substrate, but actually because of it. The "hardware" (the shape of the player, how long he or she has been playing, the length of the cue stick, the size of the table and the quality of its felt) and actually changes the nature of the question (and so its split with "software" becomes ill-posed). Substrate-irrelevant activities can be identically played any number of times, but there will never be two equal games of pool. Understanding behavior is not possible when it is taken out of context (Figure 3).

Figure 3. Beyond a Frankenstein biology.

Figure 3.

(A) The main approach to understand behavior “cuts” but fails to “stitch”. Wholes are taken to be the sum of their parts, which in turn are replaceable. Context is believed to be dispensable. Biology literally become puzzle-solving; like in a Sudoku, our job is “to fill in the gaps”, or “to crack the circuit”. In mainstream biology, God does not play dice; scientists play Lego. (B) In opposition to (A), after cutting one cannot really sew life back the life of behavior because context is constitutive and thus inseparable from content. This tension is illustrated in (C-D) with respect to space and in (E-F) with respect to time. (C) Don’t cut the body, as it is not a neural “plug-in” for behavior. For instnace, in chess, only algorithm matters, and implementation is irrelevant. The hardware-software split (a form of crypto-dualism) easily endorses a pseudo-materialism (indifference to matter). However, in pool, the body is an inextricable part of the game. One can never play the same pool game twice. (D) Don’t cut the world. Even when the body is taken into account, the same posture can reflect very different behaviors. Leaving the physics of the world out literally leaves the body floating in an empty space, disregarding the Umwelt of the animal. The meaning of the behavior is then lost. (E) Don’t cut the loop. When our study of the organism in the lab is framed under the “manipulate and measure” arc, anthropomorphism has crept into the interpretation of behavior before any data is even collected yet. The organism, being an agent like the scientist, is also trying to measure and manipulate. Thus, lineal causality (so dear to us) is a broken loop that cannot account for the circularity that constitutes the behavior of organisms. (F) Don’t cut the history. The restoration of initial conditions is an abstraction inapplicable in biology. Living organisms are individuals; they have their own history. Treating them as indistinguishable particles smears out their intrinsic differences, and trumps not only predictability but biological understanding.

The behavior of animals is not the behavior of their brains. Behavior is not a broken loop. The behavior of the individual is not the behavior of the average. Living organisms are not just complicated systems (biologist zeitgeist) nor just complex systems (physicist zeitgeist). We hope we have persuasively articulated the obvious so as to expose the non-trivial.

Acknowledgments

Funding. The authors declare no competing financial interests. The work was supported by the Spanish Ministry of Science (grant BFU-2015-74241-JIN to AGM) and by the National Institutes of Health-NINDS (R01NS054898 to AAG).

References

  1. Ahissar E, and Assa E (2016). Perception as a closed-loop convergence process. Elife 5, e12830. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  2. Ayroles JF, Buchanan SM, O’Leary C, Skutt-Kakaria K, Grenier JK, Clark AG, Hartl DL, and de Bivort BL (2015). Behavioral idiosyncrasy reveals genetic control of phenotypic variability. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 112, 6706–6711. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Baldwin JM (1896). A new factor in evolution. The american naturalist 30, 441–451. [Google Scholar]
  4. Barrett L, Henzi P, and Rendall D (2007). Social brains, simple minds: does social complexity really require cognitive complexity? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362, 561–575. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Batteau DW (1967). The role of the pinna in human localization. Proc R Soc Lond B 168, 158–180. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  6. Bell HC (2014). Behavioral variability in the service of constancy. International Journal of Comparative Psychology 27. [Google Scholar]
  7. Bell HC, and Pellis SM (2011). A cybernetic perspective on food protection in rats: simple rules can generate complex and adaptable behaviour. Animal Behaviour 82, 659–666. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bergson H (1907). L’évolution créatrice [Creative evolution]. Felix Alcan, Paris. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bortoff GA, and Strick PL (1993). Corticospinal terminations in two new-world primates: further evidence that corticomotoneuronal connections provide part of the neural substrate for manual dexterity. Journal of Neuroscience 13, 5105–5118. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Braitenberg V (1986). Vehicles: Experiments in synthetic psychology (MIT press; ). [Google Scholar]
  11. Brooks RA (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial intelligence 47, 139–159. [Google Scholar]
  12. Bufill E, Agustí J, and Blesa R (2011). Human neoteny revisited: the case of synaptic plasticity. American Journal of Human Biology 23, 729–739. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Burley N, Krantzberg G, and Radman P (1982). Influence of colour-banding on the conspecific preferences of zebra finches. Animal Behaviour 30, 444–455. [Google Scholar]
  14. Calhoun AJ, and Murthy M (2017). Quantifying behavior to solve sensorimotor transformations: advances from worms and flies. Current opinion in neurobiology 46, 90–98. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Calvo P (2017). What is it like to be a plant? Journal of Consciousness Studies 24, 205–227. [Google Scholar]
  16. Canguilhem G (2008). Knowledge of life (Fordham Univ Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  17. Chapple ED (1970). Culture and biological man: Explorations in behavioral anthropology. (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston; ). [Google Scholar]
  18. Chiel HJ, and Beer RD (1997). The brain has a body: adaptive behavior emerges from interactions of nervous system, body and environment. Trends in Neurosciences 20, 553–557. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Choi JY, Takahashi DY, and Ghazanfar AA (2015). Cooperative vocal control in marmoset monkeys via vocal feedback. J Neurophysiol 114, 274–283. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Churchland PS, Ramachandran VS, and Sejnowski TJ (1994). A critique of pure vision. Large-scale neuronal theories of the brain, 23–60. [Google Scholar]
  21. Darwin C (2004). On the origin of species, 1859 (Routledge; ). [Google Scholar]
  22. Dawkins R (1976). The selfish gene Oxford university press; New York, New York, USA. [Google Scholar]
  23. DeCasien AR, Williams SA, and Higham JP (2017). Primate brain size is predicted by diet but not sociality. Nature ecology & evolution 1, 0112. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Dehaene S, Pegado F, Braga LW, Ventura P, Nunes Filho G, Jobert A, Dehaene-Lambertz G, Kolinsky R, Morais J, and Cohen L (2010). How learning to read changes the cortical networks for vision and language. science 330, 1359–1364. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Dewey J (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological review 3, 357. [Google Scholar]
  26. Diamond A, and Goldman-Rakic PS (1989). Comparison of human infants and rhesus monkeys on Piaget's AB task: Evidence for dependence on dorsolateral prefrontal cortex. Experimental brain research 74, 24–40. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Dunbar RI (1998). The social brain hypothesis. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews: Issues, News, and Reviews 6, 178–190. [Google Scholar]
  28. Fleagle JG (2013). Primate adaptation and evolution (Academic Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  29. Gallistel CR, Fairhurst S, and Balsam P (2004). The learning curve: implications of a quantitative analysis. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 101, 13124–13131. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Ghazanfar AA, Neuhoff JG, and Logothetis NK (2002). Auditory looming perception in rhesus monkeys. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 99, 15755–15757. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  31. Goldenfeld N, Biancalani T, and Jafarpour F (2017). Universal biology and the statistical mechanics of early life. Phil Trans R Soc A 375, 20160341. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Goldstein MH, and Schwade JA (2008). Social feedback to infants' babbling facilitates rapid phonological learning. Psychol Sci 19, 515–523. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  33. Gomez J, Barnett MA, Natu V, Mezer A, Palomero-Gallagher N, Weiner KS, Amunts K, Zilles K, and Grill-Spector K (2017). Microstructural proliferation in human cortex is coupled with the development of face processing. Science 355, 68–71. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Gomez-Marin A (2017). Causal circuit explanations of behavior: Are necessity and sufficiency necessary and sufficient? In Decoding Neural Circuit Structure and Function (Springer; ), pp. 283–306. [Google Scholar]
  35. Gomez-Marin A, Oron E, Gakamsky A, Valente D, Benjamini Y, and Golani I (2016). Generative rules of Drosophila locomotor behavior as a candidate homology across phyla. Scientific reports 6, 27555. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. González-Forero M, and Gardner A (2018). Inference of ecological and social drivers of human brain-size evolution. Nature 557, 554. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Gould SJ (1977). Ontogeny and phylogeny (Harvard University Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  38. Gros-Louis J, West MJ, Goldstein MH, and King AP (2006). Mothers provide differential feedback to infants' prelinguistic sounds. Int J Behav Dev 30, 509–516. [Google Scholar]
  39. Hauber ME, Tong L, Bán M, Croston R, Grim T, Waterhouse GI, Shawkey MD, Barron AB, and Moskát C (2015). The value of artificial stimuli in behavioral research: making the case for egg rejection studies in avian brood parasitism. Ethology 121, 521–528. [Google Scholar]
  40. Hill RA, and Barton RA (2005). Psychology: red enhances human performance in contests. Nature 435, 293. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Hock HS, Kelso JS, and Schöner G (1993). Bistability and hysteresis in the organization of apparent motion patterns. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 19, 63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  42. Honegger K, and de Bivort B (2018). Stochasticity, individuality and behavior. Current Biology 28, R8–R12. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  43. Houde JF, and Jordan MI (1998). Sensorimotor adaptation in speech production. Science 279, 1213–1216. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Humle T (2011). Ant-dipping: how ants have shed light on culture In The Chimpanzees of Bossou and Nimba (Springer; ), pp. 97–105. [Google Scholar]
  45. Iverson JM (2010). Developing language in a developing body: The relationship between motor development and language development. Journal of child language 37, 229–261. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  46. James W (1890). The principles of psychology, Vol 1 (Macmillan; London: ). [Google Scholar]
  47. Katz PS (2016). ‘Model organisms’ in the light of evolution. Current Biology 26, R649–R650. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  48. King AJ, and Moore DR (1991). Plasticity of auditory maps in the brain. Trends in neurosciences 14, 31–37. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Krakauer JW, Ghazanfar AA, Gomez-Marin A, MacIver MA, and Poeppel D (2017). Neuroscience needs behavior: correcting a reductionist bias. Neuron 93, 480–490. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  50. Kuhl PK, Tsao F-M, and Liu H-M (2003). Foreign-language experience in infancy: Effects of short-term exposure and social interaction on phonetic learning. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 100, 9096–9101. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  51. Kulahci IG, Rubenstein DI, and Ghazanfar AA (2015). Lemurs groom-at-a-distance through vocal networks. Animal Behaviour 110, 179–186. [Google Scholar]
  52. Lahti DC (2015). The limits of artificial stimuli in behavioral research: the umwelt gamble. Ethology 121, 529–537. [Google Scholar]
  53. Laland KN, Odling-Smee J, and Myles S (2010). How culture shaped the human genome: bringing genetics and the human sciences together. Nature Reviews Genetics 11, 137. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  54. Lemon RN, and Griffiths J (2005). Comparing the function of the corticospinal system in different species: organizational differences for motor specialization? Muscle & nerve 32, 261–279. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Levitis DA, Lidicker WZ Jr, and Freund G (2009). Behavioural biologists do not agree on what constitutes behaviour. Animal behaviour 78, 103–110. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Lewkowicz DJ, and Ghazanfar AA (2009). The emergence of multisensory systems through perceptual narrowing. Trends in cognitive sciences 13, 470–478. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Longo G, and Montévil M (2012). The inert vs. the living state of matter: extended criticality, time geometry, anti-entropy–an overview. Frontiers in physiology 3, 39. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Loos M, Koopmans B, Aarts E, Maroteaux G, van der Sluis S, Verhage M, Smit AB, and Consortium, N.-B.M.P. (2015). Within-strain variation in behavior differs consistently between common inbred strains of mice. Mammalian genome 26, 348–354. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  59. Maier JX, Neuhoff JG, Logothetis NK, and Ghazanfar AA (2004). Multisensory integration of looming signals by rhesus monkeys. Neuron 43, 177–181. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Maturana HR, and Varela FJ (1987). The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding (New Science Library/Shambhala Publications; ). [Google Scholar]
  61. Mayr E (1997). This is biology: the science of the living world (Universities Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  62. McGraw MB (1945). The neuromuscular maturation of the human infant. (New York: Columbia University Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  63. Möbius Y, Boesch C, Koops K, Matsuzawa T, and Humle T (2008). Cultural differences in army ant predation by West African chimpanzees? A comparative study of microecological variables. Animal Behaviour 76, 37–45. [Google Scholar]
  64. Mrsic-Flogel TD, Schnupp JW, and King AJ (2003). Acoustic factors govern developmental sharpening of spatial tuning in the auditory cortex. Nature neuroscience 6, 981. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  65. Nagel T (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The philosophical review 83, 435–450. [Google Scholar]
  66. Napier JR, and Napier PH (1985). The natural history of the primates (MIT Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  67. Neuhoff JG, Long KL, and Worthington RC (2012). Strength and physical fitness predict the perception of looming sounds. Evolution and Human Behavior 33, 318–322. [Google Scholar]
  68. Noë A (2004). Action in perception (MIT press; ). [Google Scholar]
  69. Oullier O, de Guzman GC, Jantzen KJ, Lagarde J, and Kelso JAS (2008). Social coordination dynamics: measuring human bonding. Social neuroscience 3, 178–192. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  70. Padberg J, Disbrow E, and Krubitzer L (2005). The organization and connections of anterior and posterior parietal cortex in titi monkeys: do New World monkeys have an area 2? Cerebral cortex (New York, NY : 1991) 15, 1938–1963. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Pantoja C, Hoagland A, Carroll EC, Karalis V, Conner A, and Isacoff EY (2016). Neuromodulatory regulation of behavioral individuality in zebrafish. Neuron 91, 587–601. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Pelegrín-García D, Smits B, Brunskog J, and Jeong C-H (2011). Vocal effort with changing talker-to-listener distance in different acoustic environments. The Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 129, 1981–1990. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  73. Pellis SM, and Bell HC (2011). Closing the circle between perceptions and behavior: a cybernetic view of behavior and its consequences for studying motivation and development. Developmental cognitive neuroscience 1, 404–413. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  74. Pfeifer R, Lungarella M, and Iida F (2007). Self-organization, embodiment, and biologically inspired robotics. science 318, 1088–1093. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Piaget J (1954). The construction of reality in the child (Cook M, Trans.). New York, NY, US: (Basic Books; 10.1037/11168-000). [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  76. Pontzer H (2015). Energy expenditure in humans and other primates: a new synthesis. Annual Review of Anthropology 44, 169–187. [Google Scholar]
  77. Powers WT (1973). Feedback: Beyond Behaviorism: Stimulus-response laws are wholly predictable within a control-system model of behavioral organization. Science 179, 351–356. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  78. Rosen R (2000). Essays on life itself (Columbia University Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  79. Rosenblum LD, Carello C, and Pastore RE (1987). Relative effectiveness of three stimulus variables for locating a moving sound source. Perception 16, 175–186. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  80. Rust NC, and Movshon JA (2005). In praise of artifice. Nature neuroscience 8, 1647. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  81. Saraf-Sinik I, Assa E, and Ahissar E (2015). Motion makes sense: an adaptive motor-sensory strategy underlies the perception of object location in rats. Journal of Neuroscience 35, 8777–8789. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  82. Schmidt R, and Morr S (2010). Coordination dynamics of natural social interactions. International Journal of Sport Psychology 41, 105. [Google Scholar]
  83. Schöning C, Humle T, Möbius Y, and McGrew WC (2008). The nature of culture: technological variation in chimpanzee predation on army ants revisited. Journal of Human Evolution 55, 48–59. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  84. Schuett W, Dall SR, Baeumer J, Kloesener MH, Nakagawa S, Beinlich F, and Eggers T (2011). Personality variation in a clonal insect: the pea aphid, Acyrthosiphon pisum. Developmental psychobiology 53, 631–640. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  85. Seifritz E, Neuhoff JG, Bilecen D, Scheffler K, Mustovic H, Schächinger H, Elefante R, and Di Salle F (2002). Neural processing of auditory looming in the human brain. Current Biology 12, 2147–2151. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  86. Smith LB, Thelen E, Titzer R, and McLin D (1999). Knowing in the context of acting: the task dynamics of the A-not-B error. Psychological review 106, 235. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. Somel M, Franz H, Yan Z, Lorenc A, Guo S, Giger T, Kelso J, Nickel B, Dannemann M, and Bahn S (2009). Transcriptional neoteny in the human brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 106, 5743–5748. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  88. Stivers T, Enfield NJ, Brown P, Englert C, Hayashi M, Heinemann T, Hoymann G, Rossano F, de Ruiter JP, Yoon K-E, and Levinson SC (2009). Universals and cultural variation in turn-taking in conversation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 106, 10587–10592. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  89. Takahashi DY, Narayanan D, and Ghazanfar AA (2012). A computational model for vocal exchange dynamics and their development in marmoset monkeys. In 2012 IEEE Development and Learning and Epigenetic Robotics Conference (San Diego, CA), pp. 1–2. [Google Scholar]
  90. Takahashi DY, Narayanan DZ, and Ghazanfar AA (2013). Coupled Oscillator Dynamics of Vocal Turn-Taking in Monkeys. Current biology : CB 23, 2162–2168. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  91. Thelen E, Fisher DM, and Ridley-Johnson R (1984). The relationship between physical growth and a newborn reflex. Infant Behavior and Development 7, 479–493. [Google Scholar]
  92. Thelen E, and Smith LB (1998). Dynamic systems theories. Handbook of child psychology. [Google Scholar]
  93. Thompson E, and Cosmelli D (2011). Brain in a vat or body in a world? Brainbound versus enactive views of experience. Philosophical topics, 163–180. [Google Scholar]
  94. Tinbergen N (1951). The study of instinct. [Google Scholar]
  95. Tomasello M (2008). Origins of human communication. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  96. Tomasello M, Davis-Dasilva M, CamaK L, and Bard K (1987). Observational learning of tool-use by young chimpanzees. Human evolution 2, 175–183. [Google Scholar]
  97. Tuller B, Case P, Ding M, and Kelso J (1994). The nonlinear dynamics of speech categorization. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human perception and performance 20, 3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  98. Tytell ED, Holmes P, and Cohen AH (2011). Spikes alone do not behavior make: why neuroscience needs biomechanics. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 21, 816–822. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  99. Von Helmholtz H (1867). Treatise on physiological optics vol. iii. [Google Scholar]
  100. Von Uexküll J (2013). A foray into the worlds of animals and humans: With a theory of meaning, Vol 12 (U of Minnesota Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  101. Werker JF, and Tees RC (1984). Cross-language speech perception: Evidence for perceptual reorganization during the first year of life. Infant behavior and development 7, 49–63. [Google Scholar]
  102. Whishaw IQ (1988). Food wrenching and dodging: Use of action patterns for the analysis of sensorimotor and social behavior in the rat. Journal of Neuroscience Methods 24, 169–178. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  103. Whiten A, Goodall J, McGrew WC, Nishida T, Reynolds V, Sugiyama Y, Tutin CE, Wrangham RW, and Boesch C (1999). Cultures in chimpanzees. Nature 399, 682. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  104. Wiener N (1949). Cybernetics (New York: John Wiley & Sons; ). [Google Scholar]
  105. Wilson EO (2000). Sociobiology (Harvard University Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  106. Wong AL, Goldsmith J, Forrence AD, Haith AM, and Krakauer JW (2017). Reaction times can reflect habits rather than computations. Elife 6, e28075. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  107. Yingling JM (1982). TEMPORAL FEATURES OF INFANT SPEECH: A DESCRIPTION OF BABBLING PATTERNS CIRCUMSCRIBED BY POSTURAL ACHIEVEMENT. [Google Scholar]
  108. Zhang YS, and Ghazanfar AA (2018). Vocal development through morphological computation. PLoS biology 16, e2003933. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES