Skip to main content
Canadian Journal of Public Health = Revue Canadienne de Santé Publique logoLink to Canadian Journal of Public Health = Revue Canadienne de Santé Publique
. 2002 Mar 1;93(2):101–103. doi: 10.1007/BF03404547

Principles for the Justification of Public Health Intervention

R E G Upshur 1,
PMCID: PMC6979585  PMID: 11968179

Abstract

Objectives: The objective of this paper is to discuss principles relevant to ethical deliberation in public health.

Methods: Conceptual analysis and literature review.

Results: Four principles are identified: The Harm Principle, The Principle of Least Restrictive Means, The Reciprocity Principle, and The Transparency Principle. Two examples of how the principles are applied in practice are provided.

Interpretation: The paper illustrates how clinical ethics is not an appropriate model for public health ethics and argues that the type of reasoning involved in public health ethics may be at potential variance from that of empirical science. Further research and debate on the appropriate ethics for public health are required.

Footnotes

Acknowledgements: Dr. Upshur is supported by a Canadian Institutes of Health Research New Investigator Award and a Research Scholarship from the Department of Family and Community Medicine, University of Toronto. The author thanks Shari Gruman for her assistance in preparing the manuscript.

References

  • 1.Coughlin SS, Etheredge GD. On the need for ethics curricula in epidemiology. Epidemiology. 1995;6(5):566–67. doi: 10.1097/00001648-199509000-00021. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Coughlin SS, Katz WH, Mattison DR. Ethics instruction at schools of public health in the United States. Association of Schools of Public Health Education Committee. Am J Public Health. 1999;89(5):768–70. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.89.5.768. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Weed DL. Towards a philosophy of public health. J Epidemiol Community Health. 1999;53(2):99–104. doi: 10.1136/jech.53.2.99. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Beauchamp TL. Principalism and its alleged competitors. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1995;5(3):181–98. doi: 10.1353/ken.0.0111. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Gostin LO. Public health, Ethics, and human rights: A tribute to the late Jonathan Mann. J Law Med Ethics. 2001;29(2):121–30. doi: 10.1111/j.1748-720X.2001.tb00330.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Mill J. On liberty. In: Wishy B, editor. Prefaces to Liberty: Selected Writings. Lanham, MD: University Press America; 1959. [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Coker R. Detention and mandatory treatment for tuberculosis patients in Russia. Lancet. 2001;358(9279):349–50. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(01)05587-8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Harris J, Holm S. Is there a moral obligation not to infect others? BMJ. 1995;311(7014):1215–17. doi: 10.1136/bmj.311.7014.1215. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Habermas J. The Theory of Communicative Action. Vol 1. Reason and the Rationalization of Society. McCarthy, T. (trans). Boston: Beacon Press; 1984.
  • 10.Annas GJ. Control of tuberculosis—the law and the public’s health. N Engl J Med. 1993;328(8):585–88. doi: 10.1056/NEJM199302253280825. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Bayer R, Dupuis L. Tuberculosis, Public health, and civil liberties. Annu Rev Public Health. 1995;16:307–26. doi: 10.1146/annurev.pu.16.050195.001515. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Singleton L, Turner M, Haskal R, et al. Long-term hospitalization for tuberculosis control. Experience with a medical-psychosocial inpatient unit. JAMA. 1997;278(10):838–42. doi: 10.1001/jama.1997.03550100064040. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Elliott SJ, Taylor SM, Walter S, et al. Modelling psychosocial effects of exposure to solid waste facilities. Soc Sci Med. 1993;37(6):791–804. doi: 10.1016/0277-9536(93)90373-C. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Horton R. The grammar of interpretive medicine. CMAJ. 1998;159(3):245–49. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Longino H. Science as Social Knowledge. Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press; 1990. [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Walton D. The New Dialectic: Conversational Contexts of Argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press; 1998. [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Hill A. Proc Roy Assoc Med. 1965. The environment and disease: Association or causation? pp. 295–300. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Weed DL. Underdetermination and incommensurability in contemporary epidemiology. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1997;7(2):107–27. doi: 10.1353/ken.1997.0018. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Oreskes N, Shrader-Frechette K, Belitz N. Verification, Validation and confirmation of numerical models in the earth sciences. Science. 1994;263:641–46. doi: 10.1126/science.263.5147.641. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Jadad AR, Cook DJ, Browman GP. A guide to interpreting discordant systematic reviews. CMAJ. 1997;156(10):1411–16. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Barrow J. The Limits of Science and the Science of Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1998. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Canadian Journal of Public Health = Revue Canadienne de Santé Publique are provided here courtesy of Springer

RESOURCES