Skip to main content
Springer logoLink to Springer
. 2016 Nov 14;82(4):543–565. doi: 10.1007/s11238-016-9581-9

Prospect theory and tax evasion: a reconsideration of the Yitzhaki puzzle

Amedeo Piolatto 1, Matthew D Rablen 2,
PMCID: PMC7010380  PMID: 32103844

Abstract

The standard expected utility (EUT) model of tax evasion predicts that evasion is decreasing in the marginal tax rate (the Yitzhaki puzzle). Recent literature shows cases in which incorporating prospect theory (PT) does and does not overturn the Puzzle. In a general environment that nests both PT and EUT preferences, we provide a detailed study of how the elements of PT affect the Puzzle. PT does not always reverse the Puzzle, hence we give and interpret conditions for when it does and does not. When allowing for stigma and/or variable audit probability, PT reverses the Puzzle in the same way and with the same limitations as does EUT, if equally augmented.

Keywords: Prospect theory, Tax evasion, Yitzhaki puzzle, Stigma, Diminishing sensitivity, Reference dependence, Variable audit probability, Endogenous reference level

Introduction

The expected utility theory (EUT) model of tax evasion predicts a negative relationship between tax rates and evasion whenever fines are imposed on the evaded tax and taxpayers exhibit decreasing absolute risk aversion (Yitzhaki 1974). Although empirical evidence on this question is mixed, and depends to an extent on the econometric methodology used (Bernasconi et al. 2014), a substantial body of empirical and experimental evidence finds a positive relationship between evasion and the tax rate (see, e.g., Ali et al. 2001; Alm et al. 1995; Clotfelter 1983; Crane and Nourzad 1986; Friedland et al. 1978; Pommerehne and Weck-Hannemann 1996; Poterba 1987).1 Owing to the weight of contradicting empirical evidence, and its counter-intuitive nature, the negative relationship between tax rates and evasion predicted by the EUT model has sometimes been termed the “Yitzhaki paradox” or “Yitzhaki puzzle” .

Prospect Theory (PT) has become a centrepiece of behavioural economics, for it is able to resolve many puzzles associated with EUT and it provides a better fit to much empirical data (Bruhin et al. 2010).2 It remains disputed, however, whether the application of PT to tax evasion resolves the Yitzhaki puzzle: Bernasconi and Zanardi (2004), Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) and Yaniv (1999), among others, each illustrate a specification of PT that resolves the Yitzhaki puzzle, but Hashimzade et al. (2013, p. 16) show alternative specifications that do not. Unpicking these divergent results is far from straightforward, however, as the elements of PT are specified differently across studies and as some studies invoke auxiliary assumptions (in addition to those of PT). Hashimzade et al. (2013) do consider some general specifications of PT, but do not directly compare to other preference models, while Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) undertake a comparison of PT and EUT, but not in a unified framework that nests EUT and PT, and for only one specification of PT. In this paper, therefore, we seek to evaluate, in a general sense, the marginal contribution of the elements of PT—individually and collectively—towards resolving the Yitzhaki puzzle. By disentangling the separate driving forces, we are able to reconcile seemingly contradictory results in the literature and to clarify which of the elements of PT, if any, contribute to solving the Puzzle. As these elements are now widely applied in the broader literature on behavioural decision making, by isolating the different components, our results can be readily extended to many further behavioural models besides PT.

We perform our evaluation in a general environment—which we shall term the Taxpayer behavioural model (TBM)—in which it is possible to vary (i) the specification of reference income; (ii) the elements of PT that are assumed to hold—to separate out the distinct effects of reference dependence, diminishing sensitivity, loss aversion, and probability weighting; (iii) the auxiliary assumptions assumed to hold vis-à-vis those of the standard portfolio model of tax compliance. The TBM is sufficiently general to encompass much of the existing literature, but sufficiently specific to yield conditions with clear economic and psychological interpretation.3

Our first contribution is to show that several seemingly disparate approaches to the specification of reference income in the existing literature are variants of a simple, yet general, formulation. Within this general formulation, our two main results are as follows: first, matching Yitzhaki’s original demonstration of the Puzzle under EUT, we give apparently plausible conditions under which the Puzzle still holds under PT (and stripped-down variants). Second, we find that, although some specifications of PT do reverse the Puzzle, such reversals often rely on the psychologically questionable implication that a tax rise makes taxpayers feel subjectively richer (relative to reference income) in the not-caught state, and in expectation. In particular, for PT to resolve the Puzzle, this condition must hold when preferences are homogeneous, a common assumption in applications of PT. Thus, while our results do not necessarily endorse the descriptive validity of EUT, we find nonetheless that a set of specifications of PT—which includes many specifications proposed in the literature—is either psychologically questionable, or share similar descriptive deficiencies in respect of the Puzzle.

We examine the implications for both EUT and PT (among other variants) of allowing for two auxiliary assumptions: social stigma costs and a variable audit probability. Allowing for sufficient social stigma always resolves the Puzzle under EUT, but not always under PT. In contrast, allowing for a variable audit probability does not clearly improve the ability of either EUT or PT to resolve the Puzzle. In general, the conditions under which these auxiliary assumptions improve the predictions of PT with respect to the Puzzle are the same as those which also improve the predictions of EUT.

By allowing for stripped-down variants of PT, we observe the marginal contribution of each of its elements. Under PT preferences, reference dependence is necessary to overturn the Yitzhaki puzzle, but the remaining PT elements—diminishing sensitivity, loss aversion and probability weighting—are neither necessary nor sufficient. These findings seem consistent with the nascent literature on the relative economic importance of the PT elements—reference dependence being the most widely accepted (see, e.g., Barberis 2013; Santos-Pinto et al. 2015).

The results of this study contribute to the literature on the use of non-expected utility preferences (and PT in particular) to explain tax evasion, and to the wider literature on the descriptive usefulness of non-expected utility preferences (Kim 2005; Harrison and Rutström 2009; Bruhin et al. 2010; Isoni 2011; Rees-Jones 2014; Masatlioglu and Raymond 2016). We do not claim that EUT is descriptively superior or inferior to PT over the full gamut of empirical regularities on tax-related behaviour, and other evidence relating to behaviour in risky settings more generally. Our results do, though, lead us to question the claim that PT is inherently better able to reconcile the Yitzhaki puzzle than is EUT.

The rest of the paper is organised as follows. Section 2 introduces a general model of the tax evasion decision that nests both PT and EUT preferences. In Sect. 3, we analyse the model for a fixed audit probability, and then for a variable audit probability. Section 4 concludes with a discussion of our findings and some wider thoughts on the choice of reference income and of preferences in applications of PT to tax evasion. All proofs are given in the Appendix.

Taxpayer behavioural model

We now present a general model of the taxpayer tax evasion decision—the Taxpayer Behavioural Model—which nests PT, EUT and intermediate variants that may be considered as stripped-down versions of PT. Consider a taxpayer with an exogenous taxable income Y>0 (which is known to the taxpayer but not to the tax authority).4 The government levies a proportional income tax at marginal rate t0,1 on declared income X0,Y. The probability of audit is given by p=pX0,1 with p0, though taxpayers may behave as if they transform this objective probability into a decision weight wp, where w0=0, w1=1 and w>0.5 In the special case p=0 the probability of audit is independent, or “exogenous”, of declared income. Audited taxpayers face a fine at rate f1,t-1 on all undeclared tax, where the upper bound ensures that the amount paid (tax plus fines) never exceeds a taxpayer’s total income (hence limited liability is never violated, regardless of earned and declared income). Following Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007), taxpayers may additionally incur social stigma equivalent to a monetary cost sY-X, where s0. Accordingly, YnY-tX is the taxpayer’s income when not caught, and YcYn-tf+sY-X is the taxpayer’s income when caught (audited).

The carrier of utility, v, is constructed to be sufficiently general to nest both EUT and PT preferences. Specifically, we first define a function u :  RR satisfying

  • A0.

    ux is continuous and twice differentiable for all xR, except possibly at x=0.

  • A1.

    u0=0;

  • A2.

    u>0;

  • A3.

    u<0;

  • A4.

    Aux/x0, where Aux-ux/ux.6

The carrier of utility, v, is then defined as

vx=uxifx0;-1DSλu-1DSxotherwise; 1

where λ1, and the condition DS is true (DS=1) when diminishing sensitivity is assumed to hold, and false otherwise (DS=0). Note, first, that setting DS=0 and λ=1 we have vx=ux as under EUT. In this case, A2 and A3 imply that v is increasing and concave. A4 implies that absolute risk aversion with respect to v is decreasing, although we note that for wpp risk preferences (in the sense of preferences for mean-preserving spreads) are determined jointly with respect to v and to w (Schmidt and Zank 2008).7 Note, second, that under diminishing sensitivity utility becomes vx=-λu-x for x<0. In this case, A2 still implies that v is monotonic, but A3 implies that v is convex for x<0. Following Köbberling and Wakker (2005), loss aversion with respect to v requires limx0v(x)/x>limx0v(x)/x, which holds if and only if λ>1. Assumption A4 implies with respect to v that

AxAvx-vxvx<0ifx<0,DS=1;>0otherwise.

Taxpayers are assumed to judge outcomes relative to a reference level of income R—the reference dependence element of PT. Thus, we write ΔYiYi-R, i=c,n. We employ a specification of reference income that we shall show is sufficiently general to nest a wide range of those proposed in the existing literature. The underlying observation informing our specification is that existing approaches can be understood as weighted averages of wealth in the caught and not-caught states. Specifically, we write

R=α·Yc+1-α·Yn, 2

where the function α· satisfies

  • A5.

    α·=ϕ1+ϕ2Y-X,

and ϕ1· and ϕ2· are real-valued functions satisfying ϕ1X=ϕ2X=0 (where ϕiXϕi·/X). For future reference, we denote the elasticity of ϕi with respect to t as εϕi,t. The specifications of reference income in the existing literature that are special cases of A5 are listed in Table 1. R=0, as under EUT, is the special case of A5 obtained by setting ϕ1=t/ft+s and ϕ2=Y1-t/ft+s. Alternatively, setting ϕ1=t/ft+s and ϕ2=0, we obtain the taxpayer’s post-tax income if s/he does not evade (the legal post-tax income): R=Y1-t. This specification for reference income was first proposed by Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007). It is also considered by Trotin (2012), and is one of the examples in the study of Hashimzade et al. (2013). Kőszegi and Rabin (2006) make a general argument that the reference level should reflect the expected outcome of the lottery. Consistent with such approaches, reference income is equated to the expected value of the gamble by setting ϕ1=wp and ϕ2=0. Hashimzade et al. (2013) also consider the specification R=X1-t as one of their examples, which obtains from A5 with ϕ1=1/ft+s, and ϕ2=0. The specification of Yaniv (1999) exercises fully the generality of A5, for it implies ϕ20. The as yet undefined notation in Table 1 required to characterise Yaniv’s specification we shall detail later.

Table 1.

Characterising specifications of reference income in the literature

R ϕ1 ϕ2
Constant (=c) tft+s Y1-t-cft+s
Y1-t tft+s 0
X1-t 1ft+s 0
Exp. val. wp 0
Yaniv (1999) tft+s tωb-Yft+s

Taxpayers are assumed to choose X to maximise

V=wpvΔYc+1-wpvΔYn, 3

where, under A5,

ΔYn=ft+sϕ1Y-X+ϕ2;ΔYc=ft+sϕ1-1Y-X+ϕ2.

Table 2 introduces four variants of the TBM, each of which may be considered with or without social stigma, and under either p=0 or p<0. These are only four of many possible variants, but are sufficient to make our key observations.

Table 2.

Variants of the TBM

Variant R Diminishing sensitivity Loss aversion Probability weighting
EUT 0 No No No
LAPW 0 No Yes Yes
RD Yc,Yn No Yes Yes
PT Yc,Yn Yes Yes Yes

The simplest variant is EUT. To understand the marginal contribution of loss aversion and probability weighting, these features are introduced in the LAPW variant. We introduce these together as it shall transpire that neither is important for the predictions of the TBM with respect to the Puzzle. Reference dependence is introduced in variant RD, while the last variant, PT , satisfies the assumptions of cumulative prospect theory (Tversky and Kahneman 1992). As is widely noted, under diminishing sensitivity an interior maximum to (3) must satisfy ΔYn>0 for p sufficiently small, for otherwise the taxpayer’s objective function is globally convex. Moreover, if ΔYc>0, then the predictions of the PT variant are identical to those of the RD variant. Hence, under PT we assume ΔYc<0<ΔYn, and we retain this assumption in the RD variant to isolate the marginal effect of allowing for diminishing sensitivity. As the most parsimonious of the variants, EUT is at an inherent disadvantage relative to the remaining variants in respect of predicting empirical phenomena. This observation would make any failure of PT to outperform EUT the more surprising. As we shall now go on to demonstrate, these four variants of the TBM are consistent with special cases of A5.

Differentiating with respect to X, we obtain the first and second derivatives of (3) as

VX=ft+swp1-ϕ1vΔYc-1-wpϕ1vΔYn-pwvΔYn-vΔYc; 4
2VX2D=ft+s2wp1-ϕ12vΔYc+1-wpϕ12vΔYn+2ft+spw1-ϕ1vΔYc+ϕ1vΔYn-pw+p2wvΔYn-vΔYc. 5

Sufficient conditions for a (global) interior maximum with respect to Eqs. (4) and (5) are V/X=0 and the second derivative D<0 for all X. Under diminishing sensitivity, the second-order condition (D<0)—implying that the objective function is concave in X—cannot be guaranteed for any easily interpretable restriction on the parameters. Moreover, under diminishing sensitivity it is possible—because of the possibility of corner solutions—that the first- and second-order conditions do not describe the solution of the maximisation problem.8 As these difficulties of PT are well understood, we choose to set them aside here. Henceforth, when analysing the TBM under diminishing sensitivity, we proceed under the maintained assumption that the second derivative in (5) is negative, such that indeed the first-order condition describes a unique choice for the taxpayer on the interval X0,Y.9

  • A6.

    D<0 for all X.

If ϕ1 is decreasing in stigma (ϕ1s<0), as is the case for all the specifications of reference income in Table 1, then the restriction to interior solutions for evasion places an upper bound s<s¯ on the level of stigma. We prove the following Lemma, which extends Dhami and al-Nowaihi’s Proposition 5:

Lemma 1

If ϕ1s<0 then, at any interior maximum of (3), it must hold that s<s¯, where s¯ is the unique s such that

ϕ1s¯=limXYλwpX1+λ-1wpXifϕ2=0;limXYwpXotherwise.

Analysis

Exogenous audit probability

In this section, we examine the four variants of the TBM given in Table 2 under one further assumption regarding the probability of audit:

  • A7.

    p=0,

which is equivalent to the assumption of random auditing. As we restrict our attention to interior maxima, and several variants in Table 2 additionally require ΔYc<0<ΔYn, we establish the conditions under which each of these restrictions is satisfied:

Lemma 2

Under A0–A7,

  • (i)

    at any interior maximum of (3), it must hold that ϕ10,1;

  • (ii)

    ΔYc<0<ΔYn always holds at an interior maximum of (3) if and only if ϕ2=0.

Part (ii) of Lemma 2 weakens the conditions for an interior maximum to exist given in Proposition 3 of Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007).

Proposition 1

If assumptions A0–A7 hold then, at an interior maximum,

  • (i)

    under both EUT and LAPW, Xt0 for s sufficiently close to (or equal to) zero and Xt<0 for s sufficiently close to s¯;

  • (ii)

    under RD there exists a Φii>0 such that Xt0ϕ1tΦii;

  • (iii)

    under PT there exists a critical value of ϕ1t, Φiii, which may be positive or negative, around which Xt switches sign. For s sufficiently close to s¯ (or for ϕ1 sufficiently close to zero), Xt0ϕ1tΦiii>Φii;

  • (iv)

    under both PT and RD, Xt0 for ϕ1t sufficiently close to (or equal to) zero;

  • (v)

    under Yaniv’s (1999) specification of reference income there exists a Φv>-tftf+s such that Xt0εϕ2,tΦv.

Part (i) of Proposition 1 begins by extending Yitzhaki’s (1974) statement of the Puzzle—which implicitly assumes λ=1, s=0 and wp=p—to allow for loss aversion, probability weighting and for sufficiently low levels of stigma. The finding in part (i) is a pure income effect: there is no substitution effect as both the tax rate and the penalty rate increase proportionally with t. The income effect generated by an increase in t can itself be considered in two parts. The first part, IEϕ, is the part of the income effect arising from movements in R through ϕ1,ϕ2; and the second part, IE-ϕ, is the remainder of the effect—arising directly from movements in t and from the equilibrium adjustments of X. IE-ϕ always increases the optimal declaration following a tax rate rise at an interior maximum, whereas IEϕ under both EUT and LAPW is zero; hence, the Yitzhaki puzzle.

There are two elements of PT that can reverse the above intuition. Reference dependence can reverse the Puzzle if it makes taxpayers feel richer in expectation, rather than poorer, following an increase in the tax rate. To make these concepts precise, we define the expected absolute wealth of a taxpayer as EYwpYc+1-wpYn and the expected relative wealth (when wealth is measured relative to the reference level R) as EΔYwpΔYc+1-wpΔYn. We write that taxpayers “feel richer in expectation” when EΔY increases.

Taxpayers can be expected to be left poorer in absolute terms from a tax rate rise, even after accounting for equilibrium adjustments in X. The only possible exception is the (seemingly unlikely) case in which the government operates at a tax rate on the “wrong” side of a Laffer curve relationship for expected revenue (whereby X/t is sufficiently negative that also tX/t<0, such that taxpayers pay less tax following a tax rate rise).10 Under EUT we have R=0 so when taxpayers are made poorer in absolute terms from a tax rate rise, they are also poorer in relative terms. Yet, under reference dependence, it is possible for an increase in the tax rate to make taxpayers feel richer in relative terms, even when they are made poorer in absolute terms, if reference income falls faster with the tax rate than does post-tax income. When taxpayers feel richer following a tax rate rise, the income effect drives declared income down, rather than up, creating an opening to resolve the Puzzle (the RD-effect). Under what conditions will an increase in the tax rate result in expected relative income, EΔY, (and relative income in the not-caught state, ΔYn) increasing too? We now show that the answer to this question is regulated by the sign of ϕ1t. In the following Lemma, we write “d” rather than the partial derivative symbol “ ” to emphasise that here we consider the “full” effect of a change in t, including that arising from any equilibrium adjustment in X.

Lemma 3

Under the assumptions of Proposition 1, it holds that

  • (i)

    Under RD dEΔYdt0dΔYndt0ϕ1t0;

  • (ii)

    Under PT the sign of dEΔYdt and dΔYndt switch around ϕ1t=0. For s sufficiently close to s¯, dEΔYdt0dΔYndt0ϕ1t0.

With Lemma 3 in hand, it is straightforward to interpret part (ii) of Proposition 1, which states that a necessary condition for the RD variant to reverse the Puzzle is that ϕ1t>0. By part (i) of Lemma 3, this condition is equivalent to the statement that a tax rate rise makes taxpayers feel richer in expectation. As a sufficient condition to reverse the Puzzle, ϕ1t must not just be positive, but sufficiently so to overcome an offsetting substitution effect. How plausible is the necessary assumption that taxpayers feel richer in the not-caught state, and in expectation, following a tax rate rise? Barring the Laffer curve consideration given above, the taxpayer—judged in absolute terms—is poorer in expectation following a tax rate increase, in which case the RD-effect relies on a strong disjunction between the response to a tax rate rise of absolute and relative income to resolve the Yitzhaki puzzle. Although we know of no direct empirical evidence on this point, we find the idea that taxpayers made poorer in absolute terms would also feel poorer (i.e., dEY/dt<0dEΔY/dt<0) compelling from a psychological perspective.

The second element of PT that can reverse the Yitzhaki puzzle is diminishing sensitivity: this can overturn the Puzzle by reversing the sign of the income effect in the caught state, so that when a taxpayer feels poorer in the caught state, they are induced to take more (not less) risk, and thus declare less income (the DS-effect). Note, however, that whereas the RD-effect requires that a tax rate rise makes taxpayers feel richer, the DS-effect requires that a tax rate rise makes taxpayers feel poorer. Equivalently, reference dependence requires reference income to be sensitive to the tax rate to resolve the Puzzle, but diminishing sensitivity requires reference income to be insensitive to the tax rate. Therefore, the effects of reference dependence and diminishing sensitivity with respect to the Puzzle oppose each other. Accordingly, part (ii) of Lemma 3 implies that an increase in ϕ1t (which makes reference income more sensitive to the tax rate) can either increase or decrease the effect of a tax rate rise on expected income depending on the balance of the DS- and RD-effects. It is this ambiguity that lies at the heart of part (iii) of Proposition 1, which gives the condition needed for the DS-effect to reverse the Puzzle.

Part (iv) of the Proposition exploits the observation that the RD- and DS-effects are in opposition to establish a simple and relevant condition under which the Yitzhaki puzzle unambiguously holds. It states that when the expected value of the gamble moves sufficiently little with the tax rate (ϕ1t close to zero), the Yitzhaki puzzle holds under both the PT and RD variants. In this case, taxpayers neither feel sufficiently richer after a tax rate rise for the RD-effect to overturn the Puzzle, nor feel sufficiently poorer for the DS-effect to overturn the Puzzle.

How does introducing stigma mediate the above findings? Part (i) of Proposition 1 states that the Yitzhaki puzzle is always resolved under EUT for s sufficiently high. This finding is consistent with various analyses incorporating stigma—differing in the way in which stigma enters the taxpayer’s objective function—that establish bounds for s above which X/t<0 (al-Nowaihi and Pyle 2000; Dell’Anno 2009; Gordon 1989; Kim 2003). In contrast, even in the neighbourhood of the maximum level of stigma, the Puzzle is not unambiguously reversed in either the PT or RD variants. Rather, close to the maximum level of stigma, part (iii) of Proposition 1 states that the same questionable necessary condition for reversing the Yitzhaki puzzle under the RD variant holds also under PT: taxpayers must feel richer in the not-caught state, and in expectation, after an increase in the tax rate (and, as a sufficient condition, this effect must be sufficiently strong).

Implications for the literature

We now consider the implications of our findings for the existing literature. We first consider those specifications of reference income given in Table 1 that satisfy RYc,Yn. To begin, we consider these specifications in the absence of stigma (s=0). In this case, the specification of reference income as the taxpayer’s legal post-tax income, R=Y1-t, implies ϕ1=f-1, and the specification as the expected value of the tax gamble implies ϕ1=wp. It is readily observed that, for both specifications, ϕ1t=0, thus (by part (iv) of Proposition 1) the Yitzhaki puzzle holds both under the PT and RD variants.11 Only for the specification of reference income R=X1-t examined by Hashimzade et al. (2013) does part (iv) of Proposition 1 not apply, for it implies ϕ1=ft-1, hence ϕ1t=-ft2-1<0. In this case, the Yitzhaki puzzle holds under RD, but the sign of X/t is not determined a priori under PT. Thus, for two of the three specifications of reference income in the literature satisfying RYc,Yn—including the most utilised specification of reference income as the taxpayer’s legal post-tax income—neither PT nor its stripped-down variants resolve the Yitzhaki puzzle. Note that, for these two specifications that do not resolve the Puzzle, the ability of the PT and RD variants to reverse the Yitzhaki puzzle is strictly weaker than that of EUT. The latter can always reverse the Puzzle, albeit by invoking the empirically unsatisfactory assumption of increasing absolute risk aversion (and this must be sufficiently strong), whereas PT and its variants cannot reverse the Puzzle for any choice of preferences consistent with an interior maximum.

Allowing for stigma yields mixed findings. For the specification of reference income as legal post-tax income, the predictions of the PT and RD variants are improved, for we obtain ϕ1t=s/ft+s2>0, such that the sign of X/t becomes ambiguous in general, but unambiguously negative for s close to s¯. This reversal as ss¯ relies, however, on a tax rate rise making taxpayers feel richer (ϕ1t>0). The predictions for X/t are unchanged for the specification of reference income as the expected value of the gamble, however, and for the specification R=X1-t they worsen: in the absence of stigma this specification implies an ambiguous sign for X/t under PT, but unambiguously implies Yitzhaki’s puzzle for s close to s¯. In summary, augmenting EUT with stigma unambiguously improves its descriptive abilities, for it always overturns the Yitzhaki puzzle if enough stigma is allowed for. Augmenting PT with stigma sharpens its predictions with respect to the Yitzhaki puzzle, but does not unambiguously improve their descriptive validity. In particular, for either the PT or RD variants to overturn the Puzzle, even close to the maximum level of stigma, an increase in the tax rate must make taxpayers feel richer in expectation.

Proposition 1 connects to two further studies in the existing literature: Yaniv (1999) and Bernasconi and Zanardi (2004), each of which employs a specification of reference income that does not always satisfy RYc,Yn. Specifically, Yaniv examines a model with reference income specified as R=Y-H, where H is the amount of an advance tax payment. The advance payment H is specified (up to a constant) as H=ωtb where b is the tax authority’s estimate of the taxpayer’s income (which could under- or over-estimate the true Y), and ω0,1. This specification of reference income is a special case of A5 with ϕ1=t/tf+s and ϕ2=tωb-Y/ft+s. Yaniv’s model is not, however, encompassed by the TBM for, in forming the taxpayer’s objective function, the author adopts the segregation assumption of the original 1979 version of PT, according to which certain gains and losses are extracted from the gamble. The coding phase (in which the original version of PT held segregation to occur) is, however, de-emphasised in the later cumulative version of PT—the version we employ. Accordingly, the remaining literature on PT and tax evasion, all of which post-dates Yaniv’s contribution, does not adopt this assumption. Does Yaniv’s model still reverse the Yitzhaki puzzle if segregation is not assumed? In part (v) of Proposition 1, we give a result that addresses this question, and answers it in the negative: for Yaniv’s specification of R we obtain εϕ2,t=-1 yet, by part (v), a necessary (and still not sufficient) condition for the Yitzhaki puzzle to be overturned is εϕ2,t>-tf/tf+s-1.

The last contribution to the literature we discuss here is that of Bernasconi and Zanardi (2004). Unlike the rest of the literature, this study does not explicitly specify reference income, but rather it examines taxpayer behaviour for all possible values of R. Implicitly, however, the non-specification of R is equivalent to the specification of R as a constant, R=c. Viewed this way, the Bernasconi and Zanardi specification of R is the special case of A5 with ϕ1=t/ft+s and ϕ2=Y1-t-c/ft+s. As this specification of reference income implies Rt=0 the RD-effect does not arise, leaving only a pure DS-effect. Hence, under the PT variant, X/t<0. The contribution of Proposition 1 in respect of this analysis is to highlight that, once an endogenous specification for R is adopted, PT and its variants may no longer reverse the Yitzhaki puzzle. As the authors note in their conclusion, pinning-down reference income is unavoidable if PT is to yield clear and testable predictions.

We complete our discussion of Proposition 1 by assessing its implications for the separate elements of the TBM. The proposition makes clear that the Yitzhaki puzzle can be resolved without recourse to either probability weighting or loss aversion, and part (i) makes clear that when EUT is augmented with probability weighting and/or loss aversion the Puzzle is unaffected. These two features of PT are, therefore, unimportant with respect to the predicted sign of X/t.12 Diminishing sensitivity, too, is neither necessary nor sufficient to resolve the Puzzle. Indeed, in the presence of social stigma, diminishing sensitivity appears to hinder the resolution of the Puzzle. To see this, note from part (iv) of Proposition 1 that, close to the maximum level of social stigma, the necessary condition for the Puzzle to be resolved is weaker under RD than under PT. Thus, reference dependence stands out as the only feature of PT that is essential to resolving the Puzzle.

Endogenous audit probability

In practice only a fairly small proportion of tax authority audits are selected randomly. Accordingly, here we repeat the analysis conducted in the previous section under an alternative assumption to that of A7:

  • A8.

    p<0.

Under A8, Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) prove (their Proposition 1c) that if the only assumptions made with regard to preferences are A0, A2 and A3, then the sign of X/t under EUT is ambiguous. To obtain comparative static results under A8, we require a stronger restriction on preferences. Homogeneous utility appears of particular relevance in this context as Tversky and Kahneman’s (1992) original value function—subsequently axiomatised under PT by al-Nowaihi et al. (2008)—is piecewise homogeneous. Accordingly, we assume

  • A9.

    xux=βuxifx0;γuxotherwise;

which is equivalent to the statement that ux is homogeneous of degree β in the gain domain, and of degree γ in the loss domain.13 For A9 to be compatible with A2, we require β0,1 and γ>1.

Whereas, when p=0, ϕ10,1 was guaranteed by Lemma 2, under A8, interior maxima satisfying ϕ1>1 can exist. This is readily observed from the first-order condition in equation (4), where the final term is positive when p<0. We now show, however, that under the stronger preference restriction in A9 ϕ10,1 must hold at an interior maximum when ϕ2=0.

Lemma 4

Under A0–A6 and A8–A9, and assuming ϕ2=0, at any interior maximum of (3), it must hold that ϕ10,1.

Given Lemma 4, it is straightforward to verify that ϕ2=0 remains necessary and sufficient for ΔYc<0<ΔYn to hold at any interior maximum.

Proposition 2

If assumptions A0–A6 and A8–A9 hold then, at an interior maximum,

  • (i)

    under both EUT and LAPW Xt0 for s sufficiently close to (or equal to) zero, and Xt<0 for s sufficiently close to s¯;

  • (ii)

    under PT Xt0ϕ1t0;

  • (iii)

    under RD Xt0ϕ1tfγ-βϕ1ϕ1-1tf+sγϕ1-βϕ1-1<0.

Part (i) of Proposition 2 extends the original statement of the Yitzhaki puzzle to the case of variable audit probability and homogeneous utility (as well as allowing for loss aversion, probability weighting, and sufficiently low levels of stigma). Introducing variable audit probabilities does not, therefore, appear to enhance importantly the descriptive abilities of EUT with respect to the Puzzle. Under PT, the income and substitution effects cancel, leaving a residual that takes the sign of -ϕ1t. A simple necessary and sufficient condition for the Yitzhaki puzzle to be resolved, therefore, holds: ϕ1t>0. In the absence of stigma, all three of the specifications of reference income satisfying RYc,Yn in the existing literature fail to satisfy this necessary condition. Moreover, it is straightforward to show (with the same procedure we use to prove Lemma 3) that when ϕ1t>0 it holds that both dEΔY/dt and dΔYn/dt are positive, so whenever the Puzzle is resolved under PT it also predicts that expected relative wealth increases following a tax rate rise. Thus, allowing for variable audit probabilities does not appear to enhance the descriptive abilities of PT and its variants with respect to the Puzzle either. Once again, the condition for the RD variant to overturn the Yitzhaki puzzle is strictly weaker than that for PT.

The effects of stigma are similar to those in the analysis with fixed probabilities. In particular, in the presence of stigma, the specification of reference income as the legal post-tax income satisfies the necessary condition for Yitzhaki’s puzzle to be resolved, but the predictions regarding X/t of the PT and RD variants for the remaining two specifications of reference income satisfying RYc,Yn are either unchanged with stigma, or worsen with stigma.

What are the implications of Proposition 2 for the existing literature? The model of Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) satisfies the assumptions of Proposition 2, where it corresponds to a special case of the PT variant with R=Y1-t. Our insights with respect to this contribution are twofold. First, while these authors demonstrate, in this special case, that PT outperforms EUT, we can assess whether PT has a general advantage over EUT in relation to predicting the sign of X/t. Concerning this question, Proposition 2 does not suggest that PT has such an advantage.14 Second, the specification of the model implies that taxpayers who are made poorer in absolute terms by a tax rate rise will feel relatively richer.

Conclusion

Prospect theory (PT) is widely viewed as the best available description of how (many) people behave in risky settings, and we do not dissent from this view. Barberis (2013) notes, however, that PT is not always straightforward to apply: in particular, the most appropriate specification of the reference level is often unclear.15 Yet, we show that theoretical predictions related to tax evasion and the Yitzhaki puzzle depend crucially on the specification of that reference level.

We focus on tax evasion and in particular on the Yitzhaki puzzle: the EUT model of tax evasion predicts a decrease in tax evasion when the tax rate increases (X/t<0). The PT literature provides several specific examples in which the Puzzle is solved: our research is a first step towards understanding, in a general setting, the conditions under which PT reverses the Puzzle. Furthermore, by stripping down the elements of PT, we are able to (i) identify the forces that drive predictions concerning the impact of the tax rate on tax evasion; (ii) compare our findings with those under Expected Utility Theory (EUT). Although our findings do not clearly endorse the descriptive validity of EUT, we find that, in respect of the Puzzle, many specifications of PT share similar descriptive deficiencies. Interestingly, the set of specifications of PT that cannot reverse the Puzzle overlaps with many of those advocated in the literature. The auxiliary assumptions we consider—social stigma and variable audit probability—allow PT in some cases to reverse the Yitzhaki puzzle, but when they do so, they also allow the model under EUT to do likewise when similarly augmented. Although there are indeed many specifications of PT that do reverse the Puzzle, we find that in many instances these specifications imply that taxpayers will feel richer after a tax rise, for they imply that reference income falls (and by a sufficient amount) following a tax rate increase. That taxpayers made objectively poorer by a tax rate rise would feel subjectively richer seems psychologically questionable, albeit empirical work addressing this point is needed. Thus, Barberis’s point concerning the difficulty of properly identifying the reference level is evident in the tax evasion context.

Our findings contribute to the literature on the individual elements of PT. Of the four elements of PT that we isolate, only reference dependence is necessary to resolve the Puzzle, which is in agreement with its supposed status as the most accepted of all the elements of PT. Loss aversion and probability weighting are largely irrelevant for the sign of X/t. Invoking Occam’s razor, we believe that some of the findings relating to the Yitzhaki puzzle that have been attributed to PT may more properly be interpreted as being attributable to simpler reference-dependent models that contain only a subset of the elements of PT. Perhaps more surprisingly, diminishing sensitivity is neither necessary nor sufficient to resolve the Yitzhaki puzzle, and indeed pushes X/t the “wrong” way in the presence of social stigma.

Given the importance of PT in explaining behaviour in so many economic domains, it seems altogether likely that it is also of importance in explaining behaviour towards tax evasion too. As such, our cautionary findings need not imply that tax evasion researchers should cease to explore the insights of PT, but they do suggest that renewed focus must be placed on the specification of reference income and preferences. In particular, if researchers wish to retain the common assumption of homogeneous preferences then specifications of reference income beyond those encompassed by our model must be sought, for otherwise taxpayers must feel subjectively richer after a tax rate rise for PT to reverse the Puzzle.

Acknowledgements

Rablen acknowledges financial support from the ESRC (ES/K001744/1), and Piolatto from the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation (ECO-2015-68311-R) and the Generalitat de Catalunya (2014SGR420). We thank the editor; two anonymous referees; participants of PET13 (Lisbon) and PEUK2014 (Bristol); seminar audiences at Durham, Exeter, Haverford, Kent, Lucca, Milan Bicocca, and Sheffield; Ali al-Nowaihi and Sanjit Dhami for many useful comments on a preliminary version of the manuscript.

Appendix

Proof of Lemma 1

Under A6 the first derivative in (4) is decreasing, and when an interior maximum exists it must also switch sign on 0,Y. Hence, limX0V/X0 and limXYV/X0. Taking the limit of (4) as XY, and noting that limXYvΔYn-vΔYc=0 by A1, the latter inequality in the preceding sentence implies

ϕ1limXYwpYvΔYc1-wpYvΔYn+wpYvΔYc.

Using (1), this may be re-written as

ϕ1limXYλwpX1-wpX+λwpXifϕ2=0;limXYwpXotherwise.

Proof of Lemma 2

(i) Suppose, by way of contradiction, ϕ11 then the first derivative in (4) with p=0 is always negative, thus ruling out the possibility of an interior maximum. Hence, ϕ1<1 at an interior maximum. Next, the proof of Lemma 1 establishes that either ϕ1limXYwpX>0 or

ϕ1limXYλwpX1-wpX+λwpXwpX>0.

Hence, ϕ1>0.

(ii) We first show that ϕ2=0 implies that Yc<R<Yn. Equation (2) becomes R=ϕ1Yc+1-ϕ1Yn. By Lemma 2, ϕ10,1, hence R is a convex combination of Yn and Yc.

We now show that Yc<R<Yn for all X0,Y implies ϕ2=0. ΔYn>0>ΔYc holds for all X0,Y. At X=Y, however, it holds that Yn=Yc=Y1-t, so ΔYn=ΔYc=0. Therefore, as RYn,Yc arbitrarily close to X=Y, by continuity, we must have R=Yn=Yc=Y1-t at X=Y. However, when X=Y, Eq. (2) gives R=Y1-t-ft+sϕ2, which is consistent with R=Y1-t also holding only if ft+sϕ2=0, hence ϕ2=0.

Proof of Proposition 1

We start by proving statement (i). Under the parameter restrictions defining LAPW the derivative X/t, found implicitly from (4), is

Xt=-1D1-wptXvYn-wptf-1+sX+fY-XvYc+wpf-1vYc-1-wpvYn.

Substituting from the first-order condition, we obtain

Xt=-1D1-wptvYnYAYc-AYn+Y-XAYn+f-1AYc-wpstvYc.

If s=0 this rewrites as

Xt=1tY-X+YAYc-AYnf-1AYc+AYn. A.1

Under A4, AYc-AYn0, hence X/t>0. As equation (A.1) holds for wp=p, and is independent of λ, X/t0 also holds under EUT. If ss¯ then XY and AYcAYn so

Xt=limss¯wpstDvYc<0.

(ii–iv). Under the relevant parameter restrictions the derivative X/t, found implicitly from the first-order condition, is

Xt=ft+sD×ϕ1twpvΔYc+1-wpvΔYn+Y-Xwpϕ1-1fϕ1-1+ϕ1tft+svΔYc+ϕ11-wpfϕ1+ϕ1tft+svΔYn.

After some algebra and using the first-order condition to simplify the equation, we obtain:

Xt=fY-Xft+s+ft+sϕ1tD1ϕ1wpvΔYc+ϕ1ft+sY-X1-wpvΔYnAΔYc-AΔYn. A.2

Equation (A.2) allows us to prove parts (ii–iv). Notice that the first term in (A.2) is always positive. The second term is all multiplied by ϕ1t. This is sufficient to prove statement (iv). Indeed, when ϕ1t=0, then the second term disappears and X/t0. By continuity, this result must also hold in a neighbourhood of 0.

Under RD, AΔYc-AΔYn0, so the sign of the second term in (A.2) is that of -ϕ1t. Define Φii as the value of ϕ1t such that X/t=0. Then,

Φii=-fY-XDft+s2×wpvΔYcϕ1+ϕ1ft+sY-X1-wpvΔYnAΔYc-AΔYn-1.

Notice that Φii>0. Statement (ii) follows immediately.

To prove part (iii) notice that AΔYc-AΔYn<0 under PT. Then, although Φiii is written identically to Φii, its sign is no longer determined. If the term in square brackets is positive, it follows that X/t0 if ϕ1tΦiii and X/t<0 if ϕ1t>Φiii. However, if the term in brackets is negative, then X/t0 if ϕ1t>Φiii and X/t<0 if ϕ1t<Φiii. Finally, notice that the term in square brackets is positive if its first (positive) term outweighs the second. This occurs when ϕ1=0 (and by continuity, in its neighbourhood) and when s tends to s¯ (for then X tends to Y and AΔYc-AΔYn tends to zero).

(v) Under the relevant parameter restrictions, the derivative X/t is

Xt=ft+sDfϕ1-1Y-X+ϕ2+ft+sϕ2tϕ1-1wpvΔYc+fϕ1Y-X+ϕ2+ft+sϕ2tϕ11-wpvΔYn.

Using the first-order condition in (4) and replacing εϕ2,ttϕ2t/ϕ2, we obtain

Xt=fY-Xft+s+ϕ2ttf+tf+sεϕ2,t×AΔYc-AΔYnft+sϕ1-1AΔYc-ϕ1AΔYn.

The second-order condition in (5) writes as

2VX2=ft+s2wp1-ϕ12vΔYc+1-wpϕ12vΔYn<0, A.3

hence

ϕ1-1AΔYc-ϕ1AΔYn<0.

As also AΔYc-AΔYn<0 (under diminishing sensitivity), a sufficient condition for X/t>0 is, therefore, εϕ2,t<-ft/ft+s.

Proof of Lemma 3

We first prove the statements relative to dEΔY/dt and then move on to those relative to dΔYn/dt. From EΔY=ft+sY-Xϕ1-wp we compute

dEΔYdt=fY-Xϕ1-wp-ft+sXtϕ1-wp+ft+sY-Xϕ1t=ϕ1-wpft+s×fY-Xft+s-Xt+ft+sY-Xϕ1t.

Replacing Xt by its expression, we obtain dEΔY/dt=Ωϕ1t with

Ω-1ϕ1-1AΔYc-ϕ1AΔYn×Y-Xft+s1-wpAΔYc+wpAΔYn+ϕ1-wppvΔYc1-pϕ12vΔYn.

Studying the sign of Ω, by the second-order condition in (A.3), the initial fraction is positive. Within the main square bracket, the first term is positive under RD while the second term is always positive, for ϕ1>wp by Lemma . This proves that under RD dEΔY/dt0ϕ1t0. Under PT, the first term in brackets may take negative values. However, for s=s¯ (and, by continuity, in its neighbourhood), then Y=X and the first term in square bracket is zero. This proves that for s sufficiently close to s¯, dEΔY/dt0ϕ1t0.

Moving to ΔYn, from ΔYn=ϕ1ft+sY-X we compute

dΔYnt=fϕ1+tf+sϕ1tY-X-ϕ1ft+sXt=ft+sY-X1-ft+s2ϕ121-wpvΔYnAΔYc-AΔYnD-ft+sDwpvΔYcϕ1t.

Under RD, AΔYc-AΔYn>0; hence, all the terms in the bracket are positive. This directly implies that dΔYn/dt0ϕ1t0. Instead, under PT we have AΔYc-AΔYn<0. However, for s=s¯ (and, by continuity, in its neighbourhood), then Y=X and the first term in square bracket is zero: dΔYn/t=-ft+s¯2DpvΔYcϕ1t. This proves that for s sufficiently close to s¯, dΔYn/dt0ϕ1t0.

Proof of Lemma 4

Setting ϕ2=0 the taxpayer’s objective function can be written as

V=wptf+sY-Xβ1-DSγDSvϕ1-1+1-wptf+sβY-Xβvϕ1. A.4

Thus, V/X is found as

-tf+sβ1-DSγDSY-Xβ1-DSγDS-1×β1-DSγDSwp-Y-Xwpvϕ1-1+β1-DSγDS1-wp+Y-Xwpvϕ1.

If ϕ11 then V/X<0 and if ϕ10 then V/X>0. In either case, there cannot be an interior maximum. Hence, at an interior maximum ϕ10,1.

Proof of Proposition 2

(i) Under LAPW the first-order condition is written, using A9, as

VX=wptf-1+svYc-1-wptvYn+wpvYc-vYn=0. A.5

Thus, X/t is found as

Xt=-1βDβwpf-1-wpX+fY-XvYc-β1-wp-wpXvYn-βwptf-1+s+wpYcX+fY-XvYc+βt1-wp+wpYnXvYn.

If s=0, and noting that AYi=1-β/Yi, i=c,n, X/t reduces to

Xt=-YβtDwpvYn-vYc+1-βYn-YcYnvYc+βtwpf-11-βYn-YcYnYcvYc. A.6

Now note that from the first-order condition and A9 we have

βtwpf-1+wpYcβt1-wp+wpYn=vYnvYc=YcYn1-β.

Then, defining ϕz=z1-β, the first-order Taylor series expansion of ϕz at z=1 is gz=1-1-β1-z. Clearly, g(z)ϕz for all z and g(z)>z1-β for all z1, so

vYnvYc<gYcYn=1-1-βYn-YcYn.

Rearranging, we obtain

vYn-vYc+1-βYn-YcYnvYc<0, A.7

which signs (A.6) positive. As Eq. (A.6) holds for wp=p, and it is independent of λ, X/t0 also holds under EUT. If ss¯ then X/t instead writes as

Xt=limss¯wpstDvYc<0.

(ii)–(iii) Setting ϕ2=0 the taxpayer’s objective function is given by (A.4). Using the first order condition, we obtain

Xt=tf+sβ1-DSγDSY-Xβ1-DSγDS-1D×β1-DSγDSwp-Y-Xwpvϕ1-1×fβ1-DSγDS-β+ϕ1tft+sβ1-DSγDSϕ1-βϕ1-1ϕ1ϕ1-1.

Under PT (DS=1) we, therefore, obtain

Xt=tf+sβY-Xβ-1ϕ1Dϕ1tβwp-Y-Xwpvϕ1-1, A.8

which takes the sign of -ϕ1t. Under RD (DS=0) we obtain

Xt0ϕ1tfγ-βϕ1ϕ1-1tf+sγϕ1-βϕ1-1<0.

Footnotes

1

See Feinstein (1991), however, for evidence consistent with a negative relationship.

2

PT was initially proposed by Kahneman and Tversky (1979), and subsequently extended to “cumulative” PT by Tversky and Kahneman (1992). In this study, we use cumulative PT, but our main qualitative conclusions apply also to the original version of PT. See, e.g., Barberis (2013) and Camerer (2000) for reviews of applications of PT other than to tax evasion.

3

Among others, the TBM allows us to treat as special cases the models developed by Bernasconi and Zanardi (2004), Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) and two cases described in Hashimzade et al. (2013). Our model can be used to reconcile the apparently contradictory results therein. Although we have strived for widespread applicability, the TBM does not exhaustively encompass the literature. In particular, Rablen (2010) introduces PT into a version of the tax evasion model that allows for taxes to fund the provision of a public good (which we do not consider here). In addition, Bernasconi et al. (2014) allow for reference income to adapt over time to changes in the tax rate. These authors show that their model predicts an upward drift in tax evasion (after an initial fall), following an increase in the tax rate.

4

Following the study of Kleven et al. (2011)—who show that the descriptive validity of the EUT model is improved when allowing for plausible levels of third-party reporting—it is now common to interpret Y not as a taxpayer’s full income, but as that part of income not subject to third-party reporting. As this interpretation is not adopted, however, in the literature we address, we do not formally adopt this interpretation.

5

Hence, the objective probability distribution is p,1-p and the transformed probability distribution is wp,1-wp. PT allows for different weighting functions to apply to outcomes that fall above or below the reference level. As pointed out by Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) and Prelec (1998), however, empirically the same weighting function is found to apply above and below the reference level, so we assume there to be a single weighting function w . The assumption p0 is consistent with the literature on optimal auditing (e.g., Reinganum and Wilde 1986; Piolatto and Trotin 2016).

6

An example of a function satisfying A0-A4 is ux=x-e-bx with b>0. See the study by Bell and Fishburn (2000) for an axiomatisation of functions of this type.

7

These properties continue to hold if λ>1, the only difference between cases being that, if λ>1 then, even if ux is differentiable at x=0, vx is not differentiable at x=0.

8

Local maxima may also arise, so the first-order condition may not possess a unique solution. See the study by Hashimzade et al. (2013) for a detailed discussion of these difficulties.

9

We do not investigate the properties of the corner solutions X0,Y, for the descriptive validity of tax evasion as an all-or-nothing activity appears weak.

10

Fisman and Wei (2004) empirically document an instance in which tax evasion indeed leads to a Laffer curve relationship holding. Clearly, however, were the government operating on the wrong side of a Laffer curve, it is unclear why it would ever wish to further increase the tax rate.

11

Trotin (2012) uses the taxpayer’s legal post-tax income to specify reference income in a model without stigma and claims (her Proposition 8) to resolve the Yitzhaki puzzle. The difference between our findings and hers is attributable to a non-sequitur in her proof of Proposition 8. In particular, we are unable to replicate the expression for ΦR¯x,t/t in the first line of her proof.

12

Consistent with our finding regarding probability weighting, Eide (2001) shows that introducing (rank-dependent) probability weighting into the standard tax evasion model does not qualitatively change the comparative statics results.

13

An example ux that satisfies A0–A4 is given by the piecewise function ux=axβ for x0 and ux=ax1/β for x<0, where a>0 and β0,1.

14

We have shown (Table 1) that the specification of reference income in the study by Dhami and al-Nowaihi (2007) corresponds to a convex combination of Yc and Yn with a weight on Yc of α=ϕ1=t/ft+s . A possible confusion in evaluating Dhami and al-Nowaihi’s result, which our analysis enables us to clarify, is that these authors assert this specification to be the only one with the property R(Yc,Yn). We show, however, that this specification is just one special case of a wider set of specifications with this property. In particular, any specification of reference income as a (strictly) convex combination of Yc and Yn must also satisfy this property (Lemma 2).

15

The specification of the value and weighting functions of PT may also be problematic (see, e.g., Neilson and Stowe 2002; Sadiraj 2014).

Contributor Information

Amedeo Piolatto, Email: piolatto@ub.edu, https://sites.google.com/site/piolatto.

Matthew D. Rablen, Email: m.rablen@sheffield.ac.uk

References

  1. Ali MM, Cecil HW, Knoblett JA. The effects of tax rates and enforcement policies on taxpayer compliance: A study of self-employed taxpayers. Atlantic Economic Journal. 2001;29(2):186–202. doi: 10.1007/BF02299137. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  2. Alm J, Sanchez I, De Juan A. Economic and noneconomic factors in tax compliance. Kyklos. 1995;48(1):3–18. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-6435.1995.tb02312.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  3. al-Nowaihi A, Pyle D. Income tax evasion: A theoretical analysis. In: MacDonald Z, Pyle D, editors. Illicit activity: The economics of crime, drugs, and tax fraud. Aldershot: Ashgate; 2000. pp. 249–266. [Google Scholar]
  4. al-Nowaihi A, Bradley I, Dhami S. A note on the utility function under prospect theory. Economics Letters. 2008;99(2):337–339. doi: 10.1016/j.econlet.2007.08.004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  5. Apesteguia J, Ballester MA. A theory of reference-dependent behavior. Economic Theory. 2009;40(3):427–455. doi: 10.1007/s00199-008-0387-z. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  6. Barberis NC. Thirty years of prospect theory in economics: A review and assessment. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2013;27(1):173–196. doi: 10.1257/jep.27.1.173. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  7. Bell DE, Fishburn PC. Utility functions for wealth. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2000;20(1):5–44. doi: 10.1023/A:1007822718954. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  8. Bernasconi M, Corazzini L, Seri R. Reference dependent preferences, hedonic adaptation and tax evasion: Does the tax burden matter? Journal of Economic Psychology. 2014;40:103–118. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2013.01.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  9. Bernasconi M, Zanardi A. Tax evasion, tax rates and reference dependence. FinanzArchiv. 2004;60(3):422–445. doi: 10.1628/0015221042396122. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  10. Bruhin A, Fehr-Duda H, Epper T. Risk and rationality: Uncovering heterogeneity in probability distortion. Econometrica. 2010;78(4):1375–1412. doi: 10.3982/ECTA7139. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  11. Camerer C. Prospect theory in the wild: Evidence from the field. In: Kahneman D, Tversky A, editors. Choices, values, and frames. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2000. pp. 288–300. [Google Scholar]
  12. Clotfelter CT. Tax evasion and tax rates: An analysis of individual returns. Review of Economics and Statistics. 1983;65(3):363–373. doi: 10.2307/1924181. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  13. Crane SE, Nourzad F. Inflation and tax evasion. Review of Economics and Statistics. 1986;68(2):217–223. doi: 10.2307/1925500. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  14. Dell’Anno R. Tax evasion, tax morale and policy maker’s effectiveness. Journal of Socio-Economics. 2009;38(6):988–997. doi: 10.1016/j.socec.2009.06.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  15. Dhami S, al-Nowaihi A. Why do people pay taxes? Prospect theory versus expected utility theory. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 2007;64(1):171–192. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2006.08.006. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  16. Eide, E. (2001). Rank dependent expected utility models of tax evasion. Working Paper 27/2001, International Centre for Economic Research.
  17. Feinstein JS. An econometric analysis of income tax evasion and its detection. RAND Journal of Economics. 1991;22(1):14–35. doi: 10.2307/2601005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  18. Fisman R, Wei S-J. Tax rates and tax evasion: Evidence from “missing imports” in China. Journal of Political Economy. 2004;112(2):471–496. doi: 10.1086/381476. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  19. Friedland N, Maital S, Rutenberg A. A simulation study of income tax evasion. Journal of Public Economics. 1978;10(1):107–116. doi: 10.1016/0047-2727(78)90008-7. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  20. Gordon JPF. Individual morality and reputation costs as deterrents to tax evasion. European Economic Review. 1989;33(4):797–805. doi: 10.1016/0014-2921(89)90026-3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  21. Harrison GW, Rutström EE. Expected utility theory and prospect theory: One wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics. 2009;12(2):133–158. doi: 10.1007/s10683-008-9203-7. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  22. Hashimzade N, Myles GD, Tran-Nam B. Applications of behavioural economics to tax evasion. Journal of Economic Surveys. 2013;27(5):941–977. [Google Scholar]
  23. Isoni A. The willingness-to-accept/willingness-to-pay disparity in repeated markets: Loss aversion or ‘bad-deal’ aversion? Theory and Decision. 2011;71(3):409–430. doi: 10.1007/s11238-010-9207-6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  24. Kahneman D, Tversky A. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica. 1979;47(2):263–292. doi: 10.2307/1914185. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  25. Kamdar N. Information reporting and tax compliance: An investigation using individual TCMP data. Atlantic Economic Journal. 1995;23(4):278–292. doi: 10.1007/BF02298764. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  26. Kim Y. Income distribution and equilibrium multiplicity in a stigma-based model of tax evasion. Journal of Public Economics. 2003;87(7–8):1591–1616. doi: 10.1016/S0047-2727(01)00219-5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  27. Kim Y. Audit misperception, tax compliance, and optimal uncertainty. Journal of Public Economic Theory. 2005;7(3):521–541. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9779.2005.00215.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  28. Kleven HJ, Knudsen MB, Kreiner CT, Pedersen S, Saez E. Unwilling or unable to cheat? Evidence from a tax audit experiment in Denmark. Econometrica. 2011;79(3):651–692. doi: 10.3982/ECTA9113. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  29. Köbberling V, Wakker PP. An index of loss aversion. Journal of Economic Theory. 2005;122(1):119–131. doi: 10.1016/j.jet.2004.03.009. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  30. Kőszegi B, Rabin M. A model of reference-dependent preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2006;121(4):1133–1165. [Google Scholar]
  31. Masatlioglu R, Raymond C. A behavioral analysis of stochastic reference dependence. American Economic Review. 2016;106(9):2760–2782. doi: 10.1257/aer.20140973. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  32. Neilson W, Stowe J. A further examination of cumulative prospect theory parameterizations. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2002;24(1):31–46. doi: 10.1023/A:1013225326328. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  33. Piolatto A, Trotin G. Optimal income tax enforcement under prospect theory. Journal of Public Economic Theory. 2016;18(1):29–41. doi: 10.1111/jpet.12143. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  34. Pommerehne WW, Weck-Hannemann H. Tax rates, tax administration and income tax evasion in Switzerland. Public Choice. 1996;88(1–2):161–170. doi: 10.1007/BF00130416. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  35. Poterba J. Tax evasion and capital gains taxation. American Economic Review. 1987;77(2):234–239. [Google Scholar]
  36. Prelec D. The probability weighting function. Econometrica. 1998;66(3):497–527. doi: 10.2307/2998573. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  37. Rablen MD. Tax evasion and exchange equity: A reference-dependent approach. Public Finance Review. 2010;38(3):282–305. doi: 10.1177/1091142110367858. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  38. Rees-Jones, A. (2014). Loss aversion motivates tax sheltering: Evidence from U.S. tax returns. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2330980
  39. Reinganum J, Wilde L. Equilibrium verification and reporting policies in a model of tax compliance. International Economic Review. 1986;27(3):739–760. doi: 10.2307/2526692. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  40. Sadiraj V. Probabilistic risk attitudes and local risk aversion: A paradox. Theory and Decision. 2014;77(4):443–454. doi: 10.1007/s11238-013-9410-3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  41. Santos-Pinto L, Bruhin A, Mata J, Åstebro T. Detecting heterogeneous risk attitudes with mixed gambles. Theory and Decision. 2015;79(4):573–600. doi: 10.1007/s11238-015-9484-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  42. Schmidt U, Zank H. Risk aversion in cumulative prospect theory. Management Science. 2008;54(1):208–216. doi: 10.1287/mnsc.1070.0762. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  43. Trotin, G. (2012). Solving the Yitzhaki paradox: Income tax evasion and reference dependence under prospect theory. AMSE Working Paper No. 2012-38.
  44. Tversky A, Kahneman D. Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1992;5(4):297–323. doi: 10.1007/BF00122574. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  45. Yaniv G. Tax compliance and advance tax payments: A prospect theory analysis. National Tax Journal. 1999;52(4):753–764. [Google Scholar]
  46. Yitzhaki S. A note on income tax evasion: A theoretical analysis. Journal of Public Economics. 1974;3(2):201–202. doi: 10.1016/0047-2727(74)90037-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Theory and Decision are provided here courtesy of Springer

RESOURCES