Abstract
Many fundamental choices in life are intertemporal: they involve trade-offs between sooner and later outcomes. In recent years there has been a surge of interest into how people make intertemporal decisions, given that such decisions are ubiquitous in everyday life and central in domains from substance use to climate change action. While it is clear that people make decisions according to rules, intuitions, and habits, they also commonly deliberate over their options; thinking through potential outcomes and reflecting on their own preferences. In this Perspective, we bring to bear recent research into the higher-order capacities that underpin deliberation – particularly those that enable people to think about the future (prospection) and their own thinking (metacognition) – to shed light on intertemporal decision-making. We show how a greater appreciation for these mechanisms of deliberation promises to advance our understanding of intertemporal decision-making and unify a wide range of otherwise disparate choice phenomena.
Given that time runs in only one direction, many of the most fundamental choices in life are ones that involve trade-offs between sooner and later outcomes. The causes and consequences of intertemporal choice have received attention for centuries1–3, but now face an increasing surge of interest. This is because intertemporal choices are ubiquitous in everyday life, but also because they characterise a wide range of societally significant behaviours from substance use to climate change action. Accordingly, basic and translational scholarship on the phenomenon has accelerated in economics4, clinical psychology5, cognitive neuroscience6, behavioural ecology7, genetics8, philosophy9, and in other branches of the behavioural sciences.
One popular approach to understanding human decision-making has been to study the rules, intuitions, and habits that influence it10–12. Often, however, people deliberate considerably when they must make trade-offs over time; thinking through conceivable payoffs and pitfalls, as well as reflecting on their own preferences. By a broad definition, deliberation is the process by which a decision-maker considers their options (see Box 1, glossary). This process entails multiple stages, including the representation of the possible options and their subsequent outcomes, as well as the evaluation of these representations13–15. It requires a decision-maker to construct and search through the cognitive space of option-outcome paths, and to thereby settle on one route forward. Whether there are multiple interacting systems or a single system that weighs up choice options5,16–20, deliberation has a central role in intertemporal decision-making that must be elucidated13,21–23.
Box 1 |. Glossary.
Cognitive offloading:
the use of physical action to alter the information processing demands of a task so as to reduce cognitive demand.
Core network:
A network of brain regions that show increased activity both when people remember past experiences and imagine future experiences.
Delay discounting:
The decline in the subjective value of an outcome with delay to its receipt.
Deliberation:
The process by which a decision-maker considers their options, involving both representing the options and outcomes, as well as evaluating them. We argue that the higher-order capacities for prospection and metacognition are integral to deliberation.
Dynamic inconsistency:
A decision-maker holds dynamically inconsistent preferences when their preferences change or reverse as choice options come closer in time.
Episodic future thinking:
The capacity to imagine or simulate experiences that might occur in one’s personal future.
Higher-order desire:
A desire about a desire, such as when one wants a doughnut, but wants to want a salad instead.
Intertemporal choices:
Choices with consequences that play out over time, often involving trade-offs between sooner and later outcomes.
Magnitude effect:
People tend to discount future rewards less steeply when the values of all choice options are greater, all else being equal.
Metacognition:
Cognition about cognition; the capacity to monitor, evaluate, and control one’s own cognitive processes.
Model-based control:
In reinforcement learning, model-based control refers to behaviour driven by an agent’s internal causal model of the environment. It is contrasted with model-free control, a comparatively less accurate but less effortful strategy in which actions are based on previous stimulus-response reinforcement.
Precommitment:
The establishment of restraints over one’s own future choice options, usually to lock in a preference for a larger, later reward.
Preference reversal:
When an originally stated preference switches as the decision-maker moves closer in time to the choice options.
Prospection:
The capacity to mentally represent the future. This is an umbrella term that refers to many forms of future-oriented cognition: episodic future thinking is one form.
Sign effect:
People tend to discount the impact of delayed positive events more steeply than they discount the impact of delayed negative events.
In this Perspective, our primary contention is that the cognitive and neural mechanisms that allow people to think about the future (prospection) and about their own thinking (metacognition) are integral to deliberation, and that together these capacities produce effects that are responsible for a range of decision-making idiosyncrasies. For instance, the fact that people can anticipate the costs of waiting for a delayed reward means that deliberation can result in seemingly paradoxical “farsighted impulsivity”, and that therefore deliberation does not equate to patience as it is commonly defined24–26. We begin by introducing the elements of deliberation, and explain how they interlink, before turning to a range of illustrative choice phenomena. A great deal of research has implicated ingredients of deliberation in the flexibility of human intertemporal choice – such as general cognitive effort27,28, reflection29,30, and working memory capacity31,32, and it is by building on that background we develop an account of what deliberation entails and what role it plays in intertemporal choice.
Prospection and metacognition are central to deliberation
Duckworth and colleagues33,34 theorize that self-control strategies require prospection (the capacity to think about the future) and metacognition (the monitoring and control of one’s cognitive processes), and have shown how the development of these abilities in childhood underpins various self-control strategies for overcoming temptations. This idea has roots in views of self-control as a series of interactions between different versions of the self over time20,35–39. Here, we apply the insight to deliberation in intertemporal choice more broadly. We explain how the abilities of prospection and metacognition are fundamental when people deliberate over intertemporal trade-offs, and how the interaction of these two abilities is not additive. The interaction results in qualitatively distinct effects from what either process produces alone; with consequences for a range of phenomena in intertemporal decision-making.
Prospection involves the representation and evaluation of possible futures.
Research into the psychology40–42, evolution43,44, and cognitive neuroscience45–47 of thinking about the future has grown rapidly over the past decades, and it is has become increasingly clear that the ability comprises a broad range of phenomena with many constituent elements. Much of the work has focussed on episodic future thinking, which can be defined as the capacity to imagine or simulate events that might occur in one’s personal future. Numerous lines of evidence have indicated that episodic memory abilities contribute importantly to the capacity for episodic future thinking43,46,47. For instance, neuroimaging research has revealed a close correspondence in neural activity when people remember specific personal memories and imagine possible future events, which led Schacter et al.48 to describe this shared neural system as a core network involved in simulating both past and future experiences. Box 2 presents more detail and expands on the insights from neuroscience relevant to other sections of this Perspective.
Box 2 |. Insights from neuroscience.
Identifying a core network:
The core network of brain activity that supports remembering the past and imagining the future, which closely overlaps with the default-mode network162, includes regions of the medial temporal lobe, medial prefrontal cortex, posterior cingulate and retrosplenial cortices, as well as regions of the lateral temporal and parietal cortices (see Benoit & Schacter for a recent fMRI meta analysis163).
Mechanisms of precommitment:
Recent work on the neural mechanisms of precommitment has implicated the frontopolar cortex164,165, which has also been associated with the core network introduced above (more so in simulating the future than remembering the past)166, as well as with prospective valuation, counterfactual thinking, and metacognitive control167–170. These findings lend suggestive support to the conjecture that precommitment draws upon an interaction of metacognition and prospection instantiated in higher-order executive brain systems170.
Evaluating imagined futures:
Research has consistently linked regions of the core network, in particular midline prefrontal regions such as the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC), to the integration of value into simulations50,171. The vmPFC also appears to play a role in the value of simulated waiting periods: in one recent study, Iigaya and colleagues172 show that core network regions, especially the vmPFC and hippocampus, are central to the pleasure of anticipation via functional coupling with regions of the dopaminergic midbrain. The authors suggest that signals from the dopaminergic system are projected to the hippocampus, and that this amplifies the vivid imagination (and affective quality) of anticipation172. Other neuroimaging work connects delay discounting to the role of vmPFC in mental simulation. This includes findings that brain activity in vmPFC during future thinking directly predicts delay discounting177, that increased vmPFC activity while participants imagine consuming rewards correlates with shallower discounting178, and that a neural predictor of the valence of episodic future thoughts, focussed on the vmPFC, predicted the subjective value of delayed rewards in separate intertemporal choice tasks179. Among the first episodic cuing effect studies, the core network was directly implicated with fMRI. Benoit et al.173 showed that coupling of the rostromedial prefrontal cortex and hippocampus was associated with the cue-driven reduction of delay discounting (for similar results implicating coupling of frontal regions and medial temporal lobe regions see also174–176).
Interaction of control and prospection in the magnitude effect:
Ballard et al.159 report greater activity in prefrontal executive control network regions when people made difficult higher magnitude intertemporal choices. A subsequent repetitive TMS study showed that disrupting activity in the dlPFC reduced the magnitude effect, thereby providing causal evidence for the dependency of the effect on prefrontal executive control regions. In a recent neuroimaging meta-analysis163, the dlPFC was also shown to be part of the core network and more active during episodic future simulation than episodic memory. The dlPFC is thus a node both of the brain network involved in simulation, and the fronto-parietal control network – with all of the above findings implicating it in controlled deliberation over choice alternatives.
Modelling evidence accumulation in deliberation:
People take longer to choose between options that are more similar in subjective value, presumably because they deliberate more about such choices15,180. The reason that deliberation takes time could be because it involves a sequential sampling from memory (including via retrieval processes that support prospection) in order to provide evidence about choice options180. Recent approaches to modelling value-based decision-making as sequential sampling have revealed new insights about the neural mechanisms of deliberation15, and may prove a fruitful testing ground for hypotheses about intertemporal choice86,181–183, including those presented in this paper. For instance, do metacognitive processes play a role in controlling sequential sampling from memory (and thus prospection) such as by determining where the termination criterion should be set (i.e. via an assessment of whether it is worth one’s time and effort to imagine any more alternative possible futures)?
It has become clear from both neuroimaging studies, as well as behavioural and cognitive research that the mechanisms of episodic simulation share close links to those of emotion and valuation42,49–51. Episodic future thinking is therefore a plausible candidate contributor to affective forecasting42, motivation in goal pursuit52, and the explicit evaluation of choice outcomes – indeed the prospection network is often incorporated into general systems models of intertemporal decision-making6,53,54. Note, nonetheless, that patients with hippocampal amnesia (who exhibit deficits in episodic memory and in some cases, episodic future thinking) may make intertemporal choices similarly to healthy controls55, and this has led to views emphasising the flexibility episodic future thinking affords rather than its necessity for intertemporal choice per se e.g. 25,56,57. A parallel body of research into reinforcement learning has begun to elucidate the processes of model-based control58. In contrast to model-free control, which involves habitual responses based on the repetition of stimulus-response pairings, model-based control enables flexible goal-directed planning and is a plausible computational substrate of goal-directed cognition broadly, and episodic future thinking in particular59,60.
Metacognition enables the evaluation and control of prospection.
The capacity to represent the relation between a representation and reality is known as metarepresentation61. This ability is foundational for appreciating that other people may hold false beliefs (theory of mind), and for thinking about alternative ways the past could have unfolded (counterfactual reasoning)62,63. Metarepresentation also allows for the monitoring and control of one’s own cognition – metacognition – for example in taking stock of one’s own memory strengths and weaknesses and compensating for them64,65. Recent perspectives from artificial intelligence and computational neuroscience have emphasised the utility of meta-level systems66–69. These systems are effective because they can regulate the execution of lower-level processes, for example by determining the value of dedicating computational resources towards solving particular problems over others37,70.
The critical role of metarepresentation in prospection has long been noted63,71. As Redshaw and Suddendorf72–74 have argued, metarepresentation allows an individual to evaluate their own prospective cognition (metaforesight), and this therefore produces: (i) the insight that one could be wrong about one’s beliefs, predictions, or reasoning about the future72, (ii) the awareness that the future has multiple possible paths that are not just probabilistically different, but mutually exclusive73, and (iii) the ability to reflect on what the strengths and weaknesses of one’s other cognitive abilities may be in the future74. In turn, alternative representations of the future can be evaluated and appraised, for example in terms of their likelihood, plausibility, or concordance with one’s goals52,75,76 (Fig1.C). Jing et al. report that an episodic specificity induction, a procedure that enhances the retrieval of episodic details, boosts the number of alternative possible futures that people imagined during problem-solving77. This increase had consequences for the perceived plausibility of the different outcomes, suggesting that the mechanisms of episodic simulation are tightly linked with those responsible for the metacognitive evaluation of those simulations.
Fig.1. Deliberating over anticipated changes of mind.
a, A popular hyperbolic model describing delay discounting; higher k values represent steeper discounting of value with time, while lower k values represent shallower discounting. b, A preference for a larger, later, reward relative to a smaller, sooner one can change when both move closer in time. The interaction of metacognition and prospection enables people to anticipate these preference reversals. c, This interaction also underlies the insight that the future contains mutually exclusive possibilities, such as adhering to a diet or not. People evaluate these alternative futures on dimensions such as plausibility or likelihood, which helps explain precommitment (throwing away one’s doughnuts). Doughnut image credit: Sam Howzit; Salad image credit: Marco Verch. d, In the hyperbolic discounting model k is a free scaling parameter that accentuates or dampens the effect of delay on value.
Understanding how prospection and metacognition interact in deliberation sheds light on intertemporal choice phenomena
Scholars attempting to make sense of human decision-making have long grappled with the malleability78, inconsistencies3, anomalies79, and apparent paradoxes51 of real human choices, and noted how these quirks lead to frequent deviations from normative economic rationality80, as well as away from decision-makers’ own best interests81. A fuller understanding of the mechanisms underlying deliberation stands to bring many such intertemporal choice phenomena together under a common explanatory framework and leads to a number of explicit predictions and experimental avenues.
Decision-makers deliberate about – and compensate for – anticipated changes of mind.
People often express preferences for the future that are different from their preferences in the present4,82,83. A smoker intends to quit, but only starting next week; a dieter intends to stop eating carbs, but only in the New Year. The concavity of the delay discounting curves that have been used to represent the loss in subjective value of a reward with increasing time to its receipt captures this dynamic inconsistency3,51 (Figs. 1.A. & 1.D.) Hyperbolic discounting functions are one modelling approach to intertemporal preferences. These models describe higher discounting rates at shorter delays to an outcome, and lower discounting rates at greater delays to an outcome; while a single parameter value “k” captures discounting steepness35,84 (note that there are alternatives, such as quasi-hyperbolic models, heuristic models, and attribute-based models10,85–88). In intertemporal choice studies, participants commonly violate normative economic rationality (which typically models delay discounting as a time-consistent exponential decay of value) by declaring for instance that they would prefer $40 today over $50 in a month, but that they would also prefer $50 in 12 months over $40 in 11 months. Here, how far away the decision-maker is from the options influences their preference, holding constant the delay between the outcomes and the magnitude of the rewards. Preference reversals occur when an originally stated preference for a larger, later reward relative to a smaller, sooner one switches as the decision-maker moves closer in time to the two options. In Fig 1.B., this is when the two hyperbolic discounting curves cross. Hence the dieter, come New Year’s Day, shifts back to a preference for eating doughnuts (the diet can always start tomorrow).
Prospection allows decision-makers to anticipate their own preference reversals (Fig.1.C). Perhaps unlike any other animals (c.f. the Bischof-Köhler hypothesis43,89,90), humans readily, though sometimes with difficulty, recognize that they may be angrier, hungrier, or craving more intensely in the future than they are now42,91, and therefore that their intertemporal preferences may change. This recognition entails the interaction of metacognition and prospection because it requires a decision-maker to evaluate the characteristics of a future simulation itself, or of their other cognitive processes in a future simulation74,92 (for instance, “how likely am I to want the doughnuts after a long day at work”). The recursive interplay of metacognition and prospection is thereby also expressed in higher-order desires: people frequently want to want other things93, such as wanting to want salad instead of doughnuts. Collectively these cognitive processes may be directly responsible for the puzzling phenomenon of precommitment3,4,33,38,87,94, the establishment of restraints over future options. For example, the dieter may decide to throw away all the doughnuts in December, in order to pre-empt snacking once a currently undesired preference-reversal occurs.
It has been questioned whether initiating a precommitment strategy necessarily requires the simulation of a future preference reversal95,96, and this is a key target for future research. To better elucidate the psychological and neural mechanisms, it may be useful to integrate external precommitment into a recently proposed metacognitive model of cognitive offloading, the use of physical action to alter the information processing demands of a task97–100. Such a view would treat compensating for anticipated preference reversals via external precommitment as analogous to, for example, compensating for anticipated memory failures by setting reminders97,101,102. In both cases, a decision-maker has a prospective intention that they wish to pursue (e.g. not to eat the doughnuts; not to forget to water the plants). And in both cases, the interaction of metacognition and prospection is required to assess the relative costs and benefits of external versus internal strategies (see also103). Future research into the correspondence between cognitive offloading and precommitment may therefore elucidate the higher-order processes that facilitate the pursuit of intentions. For instance, perhaps compensating for anticipated changes of mind in both cases initially requires effortful and self-reflective deliberation but can then become automatized.
Metacognition means prospection is recursive, which produces effects of anticipated anticipation on choice.
Economists have long noted that decision-makers derive utility (or dis-utility) not only from outcomes during intertemporal choice, but also from the delay to those outcomes80. The emotional experiences of dread and savouring are representative cases, first expounded in detail by Loewenstein79,104; they reflect the negative and positive value of anticipation during delay, respectively. In cognitive and clinical psychology, there has meanwhile been much research into the interplay of emotion and episodic simulation105–107, and this has underscored that episodic future thinking can readily evoke emotion in a similar manner as-if an emotional event were really occurring108. Anticipatory emotions like dread and savouring are therefore likely to rely upon episodic processes104,105,109,110; though this conjecture has remained largely untested. Box 2 details an initial promising neuroimaging and modelling approach that supports the conjecture.
Not only do people derive utility from simulating emotional future events, they also adjust their decisions according to the value of the experience they expect to have during the delay period. This leads decision-makers to postpone a vacation or save a bottle of wine so they can enjoy the anticipation – in violation of expectations from hyperbolic discounting models104,111. Similarly, when given the choice between suffering different amounts of pain at different times in the future, people will sometimes opt to “get it over with”112, which reflects the mental accounting of anticipated dread, rather than just dread itself113,114. This phenomenon may account for the fact that the value (impact) of negative future outcomes tends to be discounted less steeply than positive outcomes (the sign effect), given that the anticipated negativity of dread may contribute more to the impact of delayed negative outcomes than anticipated savouring does to positive ones111,115.
Anticipating dread and changing decisions accordingly requires a decision-maker to anticipate what they will anticipate if they make a certain choice (Fig 2.A). Anticipated dread is thus also a recursive operation, in that the underlying process of anticipation calls upon itself116. This raises the largely unexplored question about the role of episodic simulation in deeper levels of recursive thinking during intertemporal choice, such as in anticipated regret117,118. Anticipated regret has three levels of recursive embedding because regret itself is a two-level counterfactual (i.e. it requires appreciating that “a different past choice would have led to a different future”73,119), and it is associated with activity in core network regions (perhaps implying episodic simulation120). The perspective outlined here predicts that the sign effect would be absent in people incapable of episodic simulation of the delay period, such as certain individuals with hippocampal amnesia (even if they discount delayed rewards normally55,121,122).
Fig. 2. Deliberation in intertemporal choice phenomena.
a, Schematic of postulated role for metacognition and prospection in delay discounting of negative outcomes. With increasing time, the subjective impact of a negative outcome decreases: people tend to prefer postponing negative events. However, with the capacity to anticipate the dread leading to a negative outcome, people sometimes opt to get negative experiences “over with”. This would correspond to a reduced discounting of the impact of a negative outcome. b, Cuing participants to imagine either positive or negative future events reduces delay discounting relative to neutral control mental imagery (n=297), data from Bulley et al125. c, Asking participants to justify their choices increases cognitive control, and this reduces the magnitude effect by selectively increasing patience for smaller rewards; large rewards are presumed to already elicit greater control (n=1,382). Reproduced with permission from ref.159, Sage Publications.
Cuing people to simulate future events can reduce delay discounting.
A number of studies have directly cued participants to simulate future events while they make intertemporal decisions, an episodic cuing procedure that produces robust reductions in delay discounting (e.g. Fig.2.C). This effect has been directly and conceptually replicated a number of times (see Bulley et al.25, and Schacter et al.122 for reviews, and Rung & Madden123 for a recent meta-analysis). Studies on episodic cuing of discounting emerged after Boyer124 suggested that a major evolutionary function of imagining the future is the curtailing of delay discounting. In this view, episodic simulation is proposed to act as a motivational brake on short-term preferences. A computational model of the role of search processes in intertemporal choice accounts for the episodic cuing effect by suggesting that it makes future choice outcomes easier to locate and evaluate during deliberation21 – though the precise mechanisms of the effect remain opaque (see Box 2 for a discussion of the neural mechanisms). There is also some variability in the size of the cuing effect between studies123, and ongoing debates about what simulated content is responsible for the effect (including regarding whether memory retrieval can also reduce discounting125–127). For instance, various studies have shown the episodic cuing effect by having participants imagine relatively banal, everyday events, while others have taken pains to have participants simulate goal-relevant events where the effects may be stronger because of the close relationship between episodic future thinking and goal pursuit52,128.
There are also conflicting results about the role of valence in the episodic cuing effect. Two studies initially showed elevated delay discounting when participants were cued to imagine negative future events relative to control imagination129,130, but in two subsequent studies both negative and positive episodic future cuing resulted in reduced delay discounting relative to control imagination125,131. Metacognitive evaluations may prove informative in determining when different event simulations lead to different patterns of intertemporal decision-making. One candidate pertains to the controllability of the imagined events. For instance, it is possible that imagining a negative event as within one’s control might spur preparatory motivation, while imagining a negative event that is out of one’s control might encourage steeper delay discounting7,132. Given the preceding discussion of the role of savouring and dread during discounting, one explanation for the positive episodic cuing effect is that episodic simulation causes people to reflect on and anticipate the pleasure derived from waiting for rewards (regardless of whether imagined events are negative or positive). One interesting prediction is therefore that episodic cuing during discounting of negative outcomes would, at least for a substantial portion of participants, accentuate “get it over with” choices by bolstering the weight of anticipated dread.
Deliberation does not equate to patience.
Contrary to its frequently assumed role, greater deliberation does not necessarily lead to the pursuit of larger, later rewards25,133,134. For instance, people sometimes regret missing out on pleasurable experiences in pursuit of a later goal135. Foreseeing this regret, a consumer may intentionally splurge on indulgences like an expensive dinner26,136 and this would be incorrectly called shortsighted by those failing to understand the causal metacognitive and prospective deliberation involved24. In a similar vein, people may intentionally choose a smaller, sooner reward if they do not trust that they will obtain a larger, later one137; a fact that helps explain the steeper discounting observed amongst people living in poverty7,132,138, and perhaps also the robust individual and cross-national associations between lower life expectancy and steeper delay discounting139–141. Even young children will modify their intertemporal choices based on their expectations of environmental reliability. In one study, when an experimenter broke a promise before conducting a version of the marshmallow test142, the average waiting time among 3- to 5-year-olds fell from 12 to 3 minutes143.
In addition to uncertainty about the likelihood of a delayed payoff, uncertainty about the length of delay to receipt may similarly drive choices for sooner, smaller rewards given certain prior beliefs144–146. For instance, in some cases the longer one has waited for an outcome, the longer one might expect to wait (such as when waiting in a queue). Recent work shows that people prioritize immediate relative to delayed rewards in line with such predictions about the delay to a payoff146. Aside from representing such uncertainty as intrinsic to various future events, representing future scenarios as uncertain may be performed metacognitively, for instance when it involves assessing whether one’s simulation of the future is plausible, accurate, or will actually occur – or when explicitly comparing and appraising mutually exclusive possible future alternatives75 such as imagining both waiting only a short time and waiting a long time for an outcome.
In the clinical domain (see also Box 3), people diagnosed with anorexia nervosa in an acutely ill underweight state exhibit reduced (shallower) delay discounting relative to controls, contrary to the vast majority of other patient groups who exhibit steeper discounting5,147. Weight recovery in remitted anorexia leads to an increased prioritization of sooner, smaller rewards148,149. This increase may be precisely because treatment re-establishes cognitive resources that enable greater deliberation and executive control, and thus the overcoming of pathological patience149,150. This case, as with the other examples presented in this section, make it clear that deliberation and patience cannot be equated. Patterns of “farsighted impulsivity” may explain recent null or opposite-to-predicted results when researchers have explored links between delay discounting and model-based planning151 (though see27), visualisation abilities152, or individual differences in episodic future thinking153. If greater deliberation can lead to either greater patience or greater impulsivity, the two constructs will not always correlate. Instead, a nuanced approach focussing on the constituent processes of both deliberation and intertemporal choice may be revealing. In one recent study, even though delay discounting and model-based control did not correlate, the amount of time spent deliberating over intertemporal choices correlated with measures of model-based multi-step planning154.
Box 3 |. Promising avenues for clinical intervention.
Steeper delay discounting has been observed in a variety of behavioural health issues and psychopathologies, leading to calls for it to be considered a trans-disease process5. Delay discounting is also therefore a primary target for clinical intervention6. The potential clinically significant role of individual differences in prospection and metacognition in deliberation during intertemporal choice has received less attention though see184–186, but there are a number of promising avenues for future research.
If deliberation is reduced, one possibility is to find alternative, compensatory strategies that do not put demands on it. For example, establishing self or other-imposed commitments, rules, habits, or principles that may require only an initial deliberative commitment and then a less deliberative execution could be effective, but may also impose other cognitive demands. For a comprehensive recent taxonomy of such strategies, and their relative merits see Duckworth et al.187. This approach may be particularly useful in clinical settings where deliberation or executive control has deteriorated. For instance, rigidity and reduced cognitive flexibility (including impairments in episodic future thinking) manifest in a range of dementia subtypes alongside maladaptive shifts in delay discounting (e.g. behavioural variant frontotemporal dementia188,189), and so compensatory strategies here could be particularly useful186. A parallel can be again evoked with cognitive offloading, which is commonly adopted in the context of dementia or brain injury when memory begins to fail (reminders, lists, Google calendars, etc.)190–192. Studying patient populations who have selective impairments to certain kinds of prospection may also prove informative for basic science, in delineating the respective role of episodic versus semantic processing in the various effects of prospection discussed in this paper47,56.
It may be possible to selectively boost deliberation, instead of compensating for its loss. Promising results discussed in this paper include the attenuation of the magnitude effect, the episodic cuing effect (particularly in clinical contexts like obesity or substance use disorder treatment193–195), and a range of other behavioural interventions such as implementation intentions196). Recent results also suggest that metacognition can be directly improved with training197. Together these studies suggest that intervening at the level of specific deliberative processes may prove fruitful.
Framing and magnitude effects may result from meta-control of deliberation.
Intertemporal decisions depend on many contextual, situational, and framing variables78. We highlight two here to illustrate how understanding the mechanisms at play during deliberation can be informative: explicit zero framing, and the magnitude effect. Laboratory intertemporal choice questions typically contain no reference to the foregone alternatives implicit to each choice option. For example, the question: “would you prefer $40 today, OR $55 in 62 days?” contains implicit zero values that can be made explicit as follows: “would you prefer $40 today and $0 in 62 days, OR $55 in 62 days and $0 today”. This explicit zero framing has been shown to reliably reduce delay discounting155,156. One reason is that participants appear to be drawn selectively to consider the opportunity cost of choosing the smaller, sooner reward (the foregone opportunity to gain more money later)157.
Mentally accounting for delayed opportunity costs rests on the insight that there are branching, mutually exclusive possible versions of the future, and that particular choices close off particular branches73 (Fig 1.C). A recent study directly tested the possibility that explicit zero framing would enhance the simulation of choice alternatives. Jenkins & Hsu158 report that explicit zero framing: (i) increased self-reported and other-rated imagination of intertemporal choice outcomes, (ii) boosted imagination of larger, later rewards more than smaller, sooner ones, and (iii) enhanced activation in regions of the core network involved in episodic future thinking (relative to regions involved in executing willpower). The increased imagination of choice alternatives, and in particular imagining larger, later reward outcomes, predicted the framing-induced shift in willingness to wait.
People reliably discount future rewards less steeply when the options are of larger magnitude. Ballard et al.159 propose that this magnitude effect occurs because people invest greater cognitive control (and hence probably more deliberation) into choices deemed more important. In support of this idea, having participants justify their choices, which requires considering the reasons behind decisions, attenuated the magnitude effect. The justification-manipulation selectively reduced delay discounting for smaller magnitude options, while larger magnitude options – which are presumed to already elicit high control – were not affected (Fig. 2.C; see Box 2 for additional supportive neuroscience findings).
If larger magnitude choices engender greater control processes, then the magnitude effect may be a manifestation of the interaction between metacognition and prospection. Meta-control systems are responsible for allocating levels of effort70, and the same may be true of deliberation about the future68. In a recent model, Gershman & Bhui160 show that the magnitude effect could emerge from meta-control of prospective simulation. Simulating the future is a noisy process161, but this noisiness can be attenuated by allocating greater (costly) cognitive control. When the stakes of a choice are higher, the meta-control system should be more willing to accept this cost and boost the precision of episodic simulations – thereby reducing delay discounting for higher magnitude relative to lower magnitude outcomes160. Note, however, that at least one individual with hippocampal amnesia (with deficits in episodic future thinking) showed the magnitude effect, raising questions about the relative contributions of episodic and semantic prospection in the aforementioned deliberative process55. The potential role of metacognitive control over deliberation in the magnitude effect suggests a striking possibility: by primarily studying relatively small, mostly monetary choices, we may have greatly underestimated the role of deliberation (and overestimated the role of habits, biases, and intuitions) when people make intertemporal choices, which frequently in the real world concern matters of much graver importance: what work to pursue, whom to partner with, how to provide for one’s descendants.
Conclusion
While it has been well documented that decision-making commonly results from the operation of rules, intuitions, and habits, in this Perspective article we have emphasized the other side of the coin: people also deliberate considerably about their intertemporal decisions. Recent research into the psychological and neural mechanisms of deliberation stands to provide a deeper understanding of how humans make intertemporal choices, with implications for a range of recognised decision-making phenomena. We have focused on the role of metacognition and prospection during deliberation, to show how together these processes allow humans a sophisticated degree of mental accounting for the later consequences of their decisions. We have only attempted to illustrate the promise of this direction, by pointing to a range of work from cognitive neuroscience, behavioural economics, clinical neuropsychology, and other areas of the behavioural sciences that have contributed important insights. We have proposed a number of specific predictions about intertemporal choice generated by the perspective that the interaction of metacognition and prospection underpins deliberation. However, the burgeoning research in this area stands to make a great deal of further progress by integrating new inter-disciplinary findings in pursuit of a cohesive understanding of how humans think through trade-offs with the future.
Acknowledgements
We thank R. Bhui, N. Brashier, T. Cochard, C. Conwell, D. Bulley, B. Leahy, J. Mahr,H. Pailian, D. Palombo, J. Redshaw, T. Suddendorf and M. Wilks for helpful discussions and comments on a previous draft of this article. AB is supported by an Australian National Health and Medical Research Council CJ Martin Biomedical Fellowship APP1162811. DLS is supported by National Institute of Mental Health grant R01 MH060941 and National Institute on Aging grant R01 AG008441.
Footnotes
Competing Interests
The authors declare no competing interests.
References
- 1.Plato. Protagoras. in B. Jowett and M. Ostwald Translation (ed. Vlastos G) (Bobbs-Merrill, 1956). [Google Scholar]
- 2.Smith A Adam Smith: The theory of moral sentiments. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 1759). doi:DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511800153 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Strotz RH Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization. Rev. Econ. Stud 23, 165–180 (1955). [Google Scholar]
- 4.Ericson KM & Laibson D Intertemporal choice in Handbook of Behavioral Economics - Foundations and Applications 2, Volume 2 (eds. Bernheim BD, DellaVigna S & Laibson D) 1–67 (North-Holland, 2019). doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-36172-2_7034 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Bickel WK et al. Excessive discounting of delayed reinforcers as a trans-disease process: Update on the state of the science. Curr. Opin. Psychol 30, 59–64 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Lempert KM, Steinglass JE, Pinto A, Kable JW & Simpson HB Can delay discounting deliver on the promise of RDoC? Psychol. Med 49, 190–199 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Pepper GV & Nettle D The behavioural constellation of deprivation: causes and consequences. Behav. Brain Sci 1–72 (2017). doi: 10.1017/S0140525X1600234X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Sanchez-Roige S et al. Genome-wide association study of delay discounting in 23,217 adult research participants of European ancestry. Nat. Neurosci 21, 16–20 (2018). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Viganò E Adam Smith’s theory of prudence updated with neuroscientific and behavioral evidence. Neuroethics 10, 215–233 (2017). [Google Scholar]
- 10.Marzilli Ericson KM, White JM, Laibson D & Cohen JD Money earlier or later? Simple heuristics explain intertemporal choices better than delay discounting does. Psychol. Sci 26, 826–833 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Gigerenzer G & Todd PM Simple heuristics that make us smart. (Oxford University Press, USA, 1999). [Google Scholar]
- 12.Gilovich T, Griffin D. & Kahneman D Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. (Cambridge University Press, 2002). doi:citeulike-article-id:4057156 [Google Scholar]
- 13.Redish AD Vicarious trial and error. Nat. Rev. Neurosci 17, 147–159 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Abram SV, Hanke M, Redish AD & MacDonald AW Neural signatures underlying deliberation in human foraging decisions. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci (2019). doi: 10.3758/s13415-019-00733-z [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Bakkour A et al. The hippocampus supports deliberation during value-based decisions. Elife 8, 1–28 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Kable JW & Glimcher PW The neural correlates of subjective value during intertemporal choice. Nat. Neurosci 10, 1625–1633 (2007). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Peters J & Büchel C Overlapping and distinct neural systems code for subjective value during intertemporal and risky decision making. J. Neurosci 29, 15727–15734 (2009). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Kable JW & Glimcher PW An ‘as soon as possible’ effect in human intertemporal decision making: Behavioral evidence and neural mechanisms. J. Neurophysiol 103, 2513–2531 (2010). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.McClure SM, Laibson DI, Loewenstein GF & Cohen JD Separate neural systems value immediate and delayed monetary rewards. Science (80-. ). 306, 503–507 (2004). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Thaler RH & Shefrin H An economic theory of self-contol. Journal of Political Economy 89, 392–406 (1981). [Google Scholar]
- 21.Kurth-Nelson Z, Bickel W & Redish AD A theoretical account of cognitive effects in delay discounting. Eur. J. Neurosci 35, 1052–1064 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Regier PS & Redish AD Contingency management and deliberative decision-making processes. Front. Psychiatry 6, 1–13 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Loewenstein G, O’Donoghue T & Bhatia S Modeling the Interplay Between Affect and Deliberation. Decision 2, 55–81 (2015). [Google Scholar]
- 24.Loewenstein G Self-control and its discontents: a commentary on Duckworth, Milkman, and Laibson. Psychol. Sci. Public Interes 19, 95–101 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Bulley A, Henry J & Suddendorf T Prospection and the present moment: The role of episodic foresight in intertemporal choices between immediate and delayed rewards. Rev. Gen. Psychol 20, 29–47 (2016). [Google Scholar]
- 26.Keinan A & Kivetz R Remedying hyperopia: the effects of self-control regret on consumer behavior. J. Mark. Res 45, 676–689 (2008). [Google Scholar]
- 27.Shenhav A, Rand DG & Greene JD The relationship between intertemporal choice and following the path of least resistance across choices, preferences, and beliefs. Judgement Decis. Mak 12, 1–18 (2017). [Google Scholar]
- 28.Kool W, McGuire JT, Wang GJ & Botvinick MM Neural and behavioral evidence for an intrinsic cost of self-control. PLoS One 8, 1–6 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Frederick S Cognitive reflection and decision making. J. Econ. Perspect 19, 25–42 (2005). [Google Scholar]
- 30.Imas A, Kuhn MA & Mironova V Waiting to choose. SSRN Electron. J 1–42 (2018). [Google Scholar]
- 31.Aranovich GJ, McClure SM, Fryer S & Mathalon DH The effect of cognitive challenge on delay discounting. Neuroimage 124, 733–739 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Bickel WK, Yi R, Landes RD, Hill PF & Baxter C Remember the future: working memory training decreases delay discounting among stimulant addicts. Biol. Psychiatry 69, 260–265 (2011). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Duckworth AL, Gendler TS & Gross JJ Self-control in school-age children. Educ. Psychol 49, 199–217 (2014). [Google Scholar]
- 34.Robinson CD, Pons GA, Duckworth AL & Rogers T Some middle school students want behavior commitment devices (but take-up does not affect their behavior). Front. Psychol 9, 1–10 (2018). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Rachlin H The science of self-control. (Harvard University Press, 2000). [Google Scholar]
- 36.Stanovich KE On the coexistence of cognitivism and intertemporal bargaining. Behav. Brain Sci 28, 661–662 (2005). [Google Scholar]
- 37.Foxall GR Metacognitive control of categorial neurobehavioral decision systems. Front. Psychol 7, 1–18 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Schelling TC Choice and consequence. (Harvard University Press, 1984). [Google Scholar]
- 39.Ainslie G Picoeconomics: The strategic interaction of successive motivational states within the person. (Cambridge University Press, 1992). [Google Scholar]
- 40.Atance CM & O’Neill DK Episodic future thinking. Trends Cogn. Sci 5, 533–539 (2001). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Seligman MEP, Railton P, Baumeister RF & Sripada C Navigating Into the future or driven by the past. Perspect. Psychol. Sci 8, 119–141 (2013). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Gilbert DT & Wilson TD Prospection : experiencing the future. Science (80-. ). 317, 1351–1354 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Suddendorf T & Corballis MC The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behav. Brain Sci 30, 299–351 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Suddendorf T, Bulley A & Miloyan B Prospection and natural selection. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 24, 26–31 (2018). [Google Scholar]
- 45.Szpunar KK Episodic future thought: An emerging concept. Perspect. Psychol. Sci 5, 142–162 (2010). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Schacter DL & Addis DR The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: remembering the past and imagining the future. Philos. Trans. B 362, 773–786 (2007). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Irish M, Addis DR, Hodges JR & Piguet O Considering the role of semantic memory in episodic future thinking: evidence from semantic dementia. Brain 135, 2178–2191 (2012). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Schacter DL, Addis DR & Buckner RL Remembering the past to imagine the future: the prospective brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci 8, 657–661 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Miloyan B & Suddendorf T Feelings of the future. Trends Cogn. Sci (2015). doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2015.01.008 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Benoit RG, Paulus PC & Schacter DL Forming attitudes via neural activity supporting affective episodic simulations. Nat. Commun 10, 2215 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Ainslie G Précis of Breakdown of Will. Behav. Brain Sci 28, 660–661 (2005). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Ernst A, Philippe FL & D’argembeau A Wanting or having to: The role of goal self-concordance in episodic future thinking. Conscious. Cogn 66, 26–39 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Peters J & Büchel C The neural mechanisms of inter-temporal decision-making: Understanding variability. Trends Cogn. Sci 15, 227–239 (2011). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Sellitto M, Ciaramelli E & Di Pellegrino G The neurobiology of intertemporal choice: Insight from imaging and lesion studies. Rev. Neurosci 22, 565–574 (2011). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Kwan D et al. Future decision-making without episodic mental time travel. Hippocampus 22, 1215–1219 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Palombo DJ, Keane MM & Verfaellie M Using future thinking to reduce temporal discounting: Under what circumstances are the medial temporal lobes critical? Neuropsychologia 89, 437–444 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Palombo DJ, Keane MM & Verfaellie M The medial temporal lobes are critical for reward-based decision making under conditions that promote episodic future thinking. Hippocampus (2014). doi: 10.1002/hipo.22376 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Dolan RJ & Dayan P Goals and habits in the brain. Neuron 80, 312–325 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Gershman SJ Predicting the past, remembering the future. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 17, 7–13 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Pezzulo G & Rigoli F The value of foresight: How prospection affects decision making. Front. Neurosci 5, (2011). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Pylyshyn ZW When is attribution of beliefs justified? Behav. Brain Sci 1, 592–593 (1978). [Google Scholar]
- 62.Perner J Understanding the representational mind. (The MIT Press, 1991). [Google Scholar]
- 63.Suddendorf T The rise of the metamind in The Descent of Mind (ed. Corballis MC, L. C) 218–260 (Oxford University Press, 1999). [Google Scholar]
- 64.Dunlosky J & Metcalfe J Metacognition. (Sage Publications, 2008). [Google Scholar]
- 65.Flavell JH & Wellman HM Metamemory. (1975).
- 66.Wang JX et al. Prefrontal cortex as a meta-reinforcement learning system. Nat. Neurosci 21, 860–868 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67.Gershman SJ, Horvitz EJ & Tenenbaum JB Computational rationality: A converging paradigm for intelligence in brains, minds, and machines. Science (80-. ). 349, 273–278 (2015). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.Boureau YL, Sokol-Hessner P & Daw ND Deciding how to decide: self-control and meta-decision making. Trends Cogn. Sci 19, 700–710 (2015). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 69.Botvinick M et al. Reinforcement learning, fast and slow. Trends Cogn. Sci 23, 408–422 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 70.Kool W & Botvinick M Mental labour. Nat. Hum. Behav (2018). doi: 10.1038/s41562-018-0401-9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71.Suddendorf T & Corballis MC Mental time travel and the evolution of the human mind. Genet. Soc. Gen. Psychol. Monogr 123, 133–167 (1997). [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72.Redshaw J Does metarepresentation make human mental time travel unique? Wiley Interdiscip. Rev. Cogn. Sci 5, 519–531 (2014). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 73.Redshaw J & Suddendorf T Temporal junctures in the mind. Trends in Cognitive Sciences (2020). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 74.Bulley A, Redshaw J & Suddendorf T The future-directed functions of the imagination: From prediction to metaforesight in The Cambridge Handbook of the Imagination (ed. Abraham A) 1–50 (Cambridge University Press, 2019). [Google Scholar]
- 75.Ernst A & D’Argembeau A Make it real: Belief in occurrence within episodic future thought. Mem. Cognit 45, 1045–1061 (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 76.Ernst A, Scoboria A & D’Argembeau A On the role of autobiographical knowledge in shaping belief in the future occurrence of imagined events. Q. J. Exp. Psychol 174702181985562 (2019). doi: 10.1177/1747021819855621 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 77.Jing HG, Madore KP & Schacter DL Preparing for what might happen: An episodic specificity induction impacts the generation of alternative future events. Cognition 169, 118–128 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 78.Lempert KM & Phelps E. a. The malleability of intertemporal choice. Trends Cogn. Sci 20, 64–74 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 79.Loewenstein G & Thaler RH Anomalies: intertemporal choice. J. Econ. Perspect 3, 181–193 (1989). [Google Scholar]
- 80.Loewenstein G & Elster J Choice over time. (Russell Sage Foundation, 1992). [Google Scholar]
- 81.Mele AR Irrationality: An essay on akrasia, self-deception, and self-control. (Oxford University Press, 1987). [Google Scholar]
- 82.Read D, Loewenstein G & Kalyanaraman S Mixing virtue and vice: Combining the immediacy effect and the diversification heuristic. J. Behav. Decis. Mak 12, 257–273 (1999). [Google Scholar]
- 83.Berns GS, Laibson D & Loewenstein G Intertemporal choice - toward an integrative framework. Trends Cogn. Sci 11, 482–488 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 84.Mazur JE An adjusting procedure for studying delayed reinforcement. Commons ML; Maz JE; Nevin JA 55–73 (1987).
- 85.Stevens JR Intertemporal Similarity: Discounting as a Last Resort. J. Behav. Decis. Mak 29, 12–24 (2016). [Google Scholar]
- 86.Amasino DR, Sullivan NJ, Kranton RE & Huettel SA Amount and time exert independent influences on intertemporal choice. Nat. Hum. Behav 3, 383–392 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 87.Laibson D Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Q. J. Econ 112, 443–447 (1997). [Google Scholar]
- 88.Rubinstein A ‘Economics and Psychology’? The Case of Hyperbolic Discounting. Int. Econ. Rev. (Philadelphia). 44, 1207–1216 (2003). [Google Scholar]
- 89.Bischof-Köhler D Zur phylogenese menschlicher motivation. (1985).
- 90.Bischof N Das Rätsel Ödipus. (Piper, 1985). [Google Scholar]
- 91.Suddendorf T & Busby J Making decisions with the future in mind: Developmental and comparative identification of mental time travel. Learn. Motiv 36, 110–125 (2005). [Google Scholar]
- 92.Redshaw J, Bulley A & Suddendorf T Thinking about thinking about time. Behav. Brain Sci (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 93.Frankfurt HG Freedom of the will and the concept of a person in What Is a Person? 127–144 (Springer, 1988). [Google Scholar]
- 94.Elster J Ulysses unbound: Studies in rationality, precommitment, and constraints. (Cambridge University Press, 2000). [Google Scholar]
- 95.Kurth-Nelson Z & Redish AD Dont let me do that! - models of precommitment. Front. Neurosci 6, 1–9 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 96.Kurth-Nelson Z & Redish AD A reinforcement learning model of precommitment in decision making. Front. Behav. Neurosci 4, 1–13 (2010). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 97.Risko EF & Gilbert SJ Cognitive offloading. Trends Cogn. Sci 20, 676–688 (2016). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 98.Risko EF & Dunn TL Storing information in-the-world: Metacognition and cognitive offloading in a short-term memory task. Conscious. Cogn 36, 61–74 (2015). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 99.Gilbert S, Carpenter J, Fleming S, Tsai P-C & Bird A Optimal use of reminders: Metacognition, effort, and cognitive offloading. Psyarxiv 44, 1–39 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 100.Redshaw J, Vandersee J, Bulley A & Gilbert SJ Development of children’s use of external reminders for hard-to-remember intentions. Child Dev 89, 2099–2108 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 101.Paglieri F Ulysses’ will: self-control, external constraints, and games in Consciousness in interaction: the role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness (ed. Paglieri F) (John Benjamins Publishing, 2012). [Google Scholar]
- 102.Hu X, Luo L & Fleming SM A role for metamemory in cognitive offloading Cognition 193, 104012 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 103.Laibson BD Why don’t present-biased agents make commitments. Am. Econ. Rev. Pap. Proc 105, 267–272 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 104.Loewenstein GF Anticipation and the valuation of delayed consumption. Econ. J 97, 666–684 (1987). [Google Scholar]
- 105.Bulley A, Henry JD & Suddendorf T Thinking about threats: Memory and prospection in human threat management. Conscious. Cogn 49, 53–69 (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 106.Jing HG, Madore KP & Schacter DL Worrying about the future: an episodic specificity induction impacts problem solving, reappraisal, and well-being. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen 145, 402–418 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 107.Miloyan B, Pachana N a & Suddendorf T The future is here: a review of foresight systems in anxiety and depression. Cogn. Emot 28, 795–810 (2014). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 108.Damasio AR Looking for Spinoza: Joy, sorrow, and the feeling brain. (Random House, 2004). [Google Scholar]
- 109.Miloyan B, Bulley A & Suddendorf T Anxiety: here and beyond. Emot. Rev (2018). doi: 10.1177/1754073917738570 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 110.Jimura K, Chushak MS & Braver TS Impulsivity and self-control during intertemporal decision making linked to the neural dynamics of reward value representation. J. Neurosci 33, 344–357 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 111.Hardisty DJ Kisses vs. shocks: Contemplation asymmetries (partly) explain why negative events are discounted less than positive events. SSRN Electron. J 1–47 (2012). [Google Scholar]
- 112.Thaler R Some empirical evidence on dynamic inconsistency. Econ. Lett 8, 201–207 (1981). [Google Scholar]
- 113.Story G et al. Dread and the disvalue of future pain. PLoS Comput Biol 9, e1003335 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 114.Berns GS et al. Neurobiological substrates of dread. Science (80-. ). 312, 754–758 (2006). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 115.Molouki S, Hardisty DJ & Caruso EM The sign effect in past and future discounting. Psychol. Sci 30, 1674–1695 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 116.Corballis MC The recursive mind: The origins of human language, thought, and civilization. (Princeton University Press, 2011). [Google Scholar]
- 117.Schacter DL, Benoit RG, De Brigard F & Szpunar KK Episodic future thinking and episodic counterfactual thinking: Intersections between memory and decisions. Neurobiol. Learn. Mem 117, 14–21 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 118.De Brigard F & Parikh N Episodic counterfactual thinking. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci 28, 59–66 (2019). [Google Scholar]
- 119.Hoerl C & McCormack T Making decisions about the future: regret and the cognitive function of episodic memory in Seeing the Future: Theoretical Perspectives on Future-Oriented Mental Time Travel (eds. Michaelian K, Klein SB & Szpunar KK) 241–266 (Oxford University Press, 2016). [Google Scholar]
- 120.Coricelli G et al. Regret and its avoidance: A neuroimaging study of choice behavior. Nat. Neurosci 8, 1255–1262 (2005). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 121.Palombo DJ, Keane MM & Verfaellie M How do lesion studies elucidate the role of the hippocampus in intertemporal choice? Hippocampus 25, 407–408 (2015). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 122.Schacter DL, Benoit RG & Szpunar KK Episodic future thinking: mechanisms and functions. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 17, 41–50 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 123.Rung JM & Madden GJ Experimental reductions of delay discounting and impulsive choice: A systematic review and meta-analysis. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen 147, 1349–13831 (2018). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 124.Boyer P Evolutionary economics of mental time travel? Trends Cogn. Sci 12, 219–224 (2008). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 125.Bulley A et al. Cuing both positive and negative episodic foresight reduces delay discounting but does not affect risk-taking. Q. J. Exp. Psychol 72, 1998–2017 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 126.Lempert KM, Speer ME, Delgado MR & Phelps EA Positive autobiographical memory retrieval reduces temporal discounting. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci 12, 1584–1593 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 127.Ciaramelli E, Sellitto M, Tosarelli G & Pellegrino G Imagining Events Alternative to the Present Can Attenuate Delay Discounting. Front. Behav. Neurosci 13, 1–9 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 128.O’Donnell S, Oluyomi Daniel T & Epstein LH Does goal relevant episodic future thinking amplify the effect on delay discounting? Conscious. Cogn 51, 10–16 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 129.Liu L, Feng T, Chen J & Li H The value of emotion: How does episodic prospection modulate delay discounting? PLoS One 8, (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 130.Zhang S, Peng J, Qin L, Suo T & Feng T Prospective emotion enables episodic prospection to shift time preference. Br. J. Psychol 1–13 (2018). doi: 10.1111/bjop.12284 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 131.Calluso C, Tosoni A, Cannito L & Committeri G Concreteness and emotional valence of episodic future thinking ( EFT ) independently affect the dynamics of intertemporal decisions. PLoS One 1–22 (2019). doi: 10.6084/m9.figshare.7072568 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 132.Frankenhuis WE, Panchanathan K & Nettle D Cognition in harsh and unpredictable environments. Curr. Opin. Psychol 7, 76–80 (2016). [Google Scholar]
- 133.Bulley A, Pepper G & Suddendorf T Using foresight to prioritise the present. Behav. Brain Sci 40, (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 134.Paglieri F Social choice for one: On the rationality of intertemporal decisions. Behav. Processes 127, 97–108 (2016). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 135.Kivetz R & Keinan A Repenting hyperopia: An analysis of self-control regrets. J. Consum. Res 33, 273–282 (2006). [Google Scholar]
- 136.Kivetz R & Simonson I Self-control for the righteous: Toward a theory of precommitment to indulgence. J. Consum. Res 29, 199–217 (2002). [Google Scholar]
- 137.Michaelson L, de la Vega A, Chatham C & Munakata Y Delaying gratification depends on social trust. Front. Psychol 4, (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 138.Jachimowicz JM, Chafik S, Munrat S, Prabhu JC & Weber EU Community trust reduces myopic decisions of low-income individuals. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A 114, 5401–5406 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 139.Bulley A & Pepper GV Cross-country relationships between life expectancy, intertemporal choice and age at first birth. Evol. Hum. Behav 38, 652–658 (2017). [Google Scholar]
- 140.Lee AJ, DeBruine L & Jones BC Individual-specific mortality is associated with how individuals evaluate future discounting decisions. (2018). doi: 10.17605/OSF.IO/FGVQM [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 141.Falk A et al. The nature and predictive power of preferences: Global evidence. IZA Discuss. Pap. Ser 9504, 1–76 (2015). [Google Scholar]
- 142.Mischel W, Shoda Y & Rodriguez MI Delay of gratification in children. Science (80-. ). 244, 933–938 (1989). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 143.Kidd C, Palmeri H & Aslin RN Rational snacking: Young children’s decision-making on the marshmallow task is moderated by beliefs about environmental reliability. Cognition 126, 109–114 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 144.Dai J, Pachur T, Pleskac TJ & Hertwig R What the future holds and when: A description–experience gap in intertemporal choice. Psychol. Sci 30, 1218–1233 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 145.Dai J, Pachur T, Pleskac TJ & Hertwig R Tomorrow never knows - why and how uncertainty matters in intertemporal choice in Taming Uncertainty (eds. Hertwig R, Pleskac TJ & Pachur T) 175–189 (The MIT Press, 2019). [Google Scholar]
- 146.McGuire JT & Kable JW Rational temporal predictions can underlie apparent failures to delay gratification. Psychol. Rev 120, 395–410 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 147.Amlung M et al. Delay discounting as a transdiagnostic process in psychiatric disorders. JAMA Psychiatry 1–11 (2019). doi: 10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2019.2102 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 148.King JA et al. Intact value-based decision-making during intertemporal choice in women with remitted anorexia nervosa? An fMRI study. J. Psychiatry Neurosci 44, 180252 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 149.Decker JH, Figner B & Steinglass JE On weight and waiting: Delay discounting in anorexia nervosa pretreatment and posttreatment. Biol. Psychiatry 78, 606–614 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 150.Foerde AK, Daw ND, Rufin T & Walsh BT Deficient goal-directed control in a population characterized by extreme goal pursuit. 1–32 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 151.Solway A, Lohrenz T & Montague PR Simulating future value in intertemporal choice. Sci. Rep 7, 43119 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 152.Parthasarathi T, McConnell MH, Luery J & Kable JW The vivid present: Visualization abilities are associated with steep discounting of future rewards. Front. Psychol 8, 289 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 153.Wiehler A, Bromberg U & Peters J The role of prospection in steep temporal reward discounting in gambling addiction. Front. Psychiatry 6, (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 154.Hunter LE, Bornstein AM & Hartley CA A common deliberative process underlies model-based planning and patient intertemporal choice. bioRxiv 499707 (2018). doi: 10.1101/499707 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 155.Radu PT, Yi R, Bickel WK, Gross JJ & McClure SM A mechanism for reducing delay discounting by altering temporal attention. J. Exp. Anal. Behav 96, 363–385 (2011). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 156.Rung JM, Peck S, Hinnenkamp JE, Preston E & Madden GJ Changing delay discounting and impulsive choice: implications for addictions, prevention, and human health. Perspect. Behav. Sci 42, 1–21 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 157.Read D, Olivola CY & Hardisty DJ The value of nothing: Asymmetric attention to opportunity costs drives intertemporal decision making. Manage. Sci 63, 4277–4297 (2016). [Google Scholar]
- 158.Jenkins AC & Hsu M Dissociable contributions of imagination and willpower to the malleability of human patience. Psychol. Sci 28, 894–906 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 159.Ballard IC et al. More Is meaningful: The magnitude effect in intertemporal choice depends on self-control. Psychol. Sci 28, 1443–1454 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 160.Gershman SJ & Bhui R Rationally inattentive intertemporal choice. bioRxiv 680652 (2019). doi: 10.1101/680652 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 161.Gabaix X & Laibson D Myopia and discounting. NBER Work. Pap. Ser (2017). [Google Scholar]
- 162.Buckner RL & DiNicola LM The brain’s default network: updated anatomy, physiology and evolving insights. Nat. Rev. Neurosci 20, 593–608 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 163.Benoit RG & Schacter DL Specifying the core network supporting episodic simulation and episodic memory by activation likelihood estimation. Neuropsychologia 75, 450–457 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 164.Soutschek A et al. Binding oneself to the mast: stimulating frontopolar cortex enhances precommitment. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci 12, 635–642 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 165.Crockett MJ et al. Restricting temptations: Neural mechanisms of precommitment. Neuron 79, 391–401 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 166.Addis DR, Wong AT & Schacter DL Remembering the past and imagining the future: Common and distinct neural substrates during event construction and elaboration. Neuropsychologia 45, 1363–1377 (2007). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 167.De Martino B, Fleming SM, Garrett N & Dolan RJ Confidence in value-based choice. Nat. Neurosci 16, 105–110 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 168.Burgess PW, Dumontheil I & Gilbert SJ The gateway hypothesis of rostral prefrontal cortex (area 10) function. Trends Cogn. Sci 11, 290–298 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 169.Boorman ED, Behrens TEJ, Woolrich MW & Rushworth MFS How green is the grass on the other side? Frontopolar cortex and the evidence in favor of alternative courses of action. Neuron 62, 733–743 (2009). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 170.Koechlin E & Hyafil A Anterior prefrontal function and the limits of human decision-making. Science (80-. ). 318, 594–598 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 171.D’Argembeau A On the Role of the Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex in Self-Processing: The Valuation Hypothesis. Front. Hum. Neurosci 7, 372 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 172.Iigaya K et al. Hippocampal-midbrain circuit enhances the pleasure of anticipation in the prefrontal cortex. bioRxiv 588699 (2019). doi: 10.1101/588699 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 173.Benoit RG, Gilbert SJ & Burgess PW A neural mechanism mediating the impact of episodic prospection on farsighted decisions. J. Neurosci 31, 6771–6779 (2011). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 174.Peters J & Büchel C Episodic future thinking reduces reward delay discounting through an enhancement of prefrontal-mediotemporal interactions. Neuron 66, 138–148 (2010). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 175.Sasse LK, Peters J & Brassen S Cognitive control modulates effects of episodic simulation on delay discounting in aging. Front. Aging Neurosci 9, 1–11 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 176.Hu X, Kleinschmidt H, Martin JA, Han Y & Thelen M A reduction in delay discounting by using episodic future imagination and the association with episodic memory capacity. 10, 1–20 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 177.Cooper N, Kable JW, Kim BK & Zauberman G Brain activity in valuation regions while thinking about the future predicts individual discount rates. J. Neurosci 33, 13150–6 (2013). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 178.Hakimi S & Hare T a. Enhanced neural responses to imagined primary rewards predict reduced monetary temporal discounting. J. Neurosci 35, 13103–13109 (2015). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 179.Lee S, Parthasarathi T & Kable JW Neural predictor of concreteness also predicts temporal proximity in intertemporal choice. Unpubl. Prepr (2019). [Google Scholar]
- 180.Shadlen MNN & Shohamy D Decision Making and Sequential Sampling from Memory. Neuron 90, 927–939 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 181.Rodriguez CA, Turner BM & McClure SM Intertemporal choice as discounted value accumulation. PLoS One 9, (2014). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 182.Peters J & D’Esposito M The drift diffusion model as the choice rule in inter-temporal and risky choice: a case study in medial orbitofrontal cortex lesion patients and controls. bioRxiv 642587 (2019). doi: 10.1101/642587 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 183.Zhao WJ, Diederich A, Trueblood JS & Bhatia S Automatic biases in intertemporal choice. Psychon. Bull. Rev 26, 661–668 (2019). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 184.Noël X, Jaafari N & Bechara A Addictive behaviors: Why and how impaired mental time matters? 235, 219–237 (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 185.Redish AD, Jensen S & Johnson A A unified framework for addiction: Vulnerabilities in the decision process. Behav. Brain Sci 31, 415–437 (2008). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 186.Bulley A & Irish M The functions of prospection: Variations in health and disease. Front. Psychol 9, 1–8 (2018). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 187.Duckworth AL, Milkman KL & Laibson D Beyond willpower: strategies for reducing failures of self-control. Psychol. Sci. Public Interest 19, 102–129 (2018). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 188.Bertoux M, de Souza LC, Zamith P, Dubois B & Bourgeois-Gironde S Discounting of future rewards in behavioural variant Frontotemporal Dementia & Alzheimer’s Disease. Neuropsychology 29, 933–939 (2015). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 189.Irish M, Hodges JR & Piguet O Episodic future thinking is impaired in the behavioural variant of frontotemporal dementia. Cortex 49, 2377–2388 (2013). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 190.Svoboda E & Richards B Compensating for anterograde amnesia: A new training method that capitalizes on emerging smartphone technologies. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc 15, 629–638 (2009). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 191.McDonald A et al. Google calendar: A memory aid to manage prospective memory deficits following acquired brain injury. Neuropsychol. Rehabil 21, 784–807 (2011). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 192.Clark A & Chalmers D The extended mind. Analysis 58, 7–19 (1998). [Google Scholar]
- 193.O’Neill J, Daniel TO & Epstein LH Episodic future thinking reduces eating in a food court. Eat. Behav (2015). doi: 10.1016/j.eatbeh.2015.10.002 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 194.Stein JS et al. Unstuck in time: episodic future thinking reduces delay discounting and cigarette smoking. Psychopharmacology (Berl). 233, 3771–3778 (2016). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 195.Bulley A & Gullo MJ The influence of episodic foresight on delay discounting and demand for alcohol. Addict. Behav 66, 1–6 (2017). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 196.Gollwitzer PM Weakness of the will: Is a quick fix possible? Motiv. Emot 38, 305–322 (2014). [Google Scholar]
- 197.Carpenter J et al. Domain-general enhancements of metacognitive ability through adaptive training. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen 148, 51–64 (2019). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]