Abstract
Stroke is the second leading cause of death worldwide and a leading cause of adult disability worldwide. More than a third of individuals presenting with strokes are estimated to have a preexisting disability. Despite unprecedented advances in stroke research and clinical practice over the past decade, approaches to acute stroke care for persons with preexisting disability have received scant attention. Current standards of research and clinical practice are influenced by an underexplored range of biases that may hinder acute stroke care for persons with disability. These trends may exacerbate unequal health outcomes by rendering novel stroke therapies inaccessible to many persons with disabilities. Here, we explore the underpinnings and implications of biases involving persons with disability in stroke research and practice. Recent insights from bioethics, disability rights, and health law are explained and critically evaluated in the context of prevailing research and clinical practices. Allowing disability to drive decisions to withhold acute stroke interventions may perpetuate disparate health outcomes and undermine ethically resilient stroke care. Advocacy for inclusion of persons with disability in future stroke trials can improve equity in stroke care delivery.
Stroke is the second leading cause of death worldwide and the leading cause of serious adult disability in America.1,2 More than 17% of the US population lives with disability. This population is disproportionally represented in ischemic stroke presentations; more than a third of patients with stroke present with a preexisting disability.3,4 Acute stroke intervention is currently driven by mechanical thrombectomy and IV thrombolysis. The aim of these interventions is mitigation of future disability by reperfusion, and therefore salvage, of threatened penumbral tissue. Despite unprecedented advances in stroke care and research over the past decade, approaches to acute stroke intervention for persons with disabilities have received limited attention. Increased awareness of key principles and recent findings from disabilities rights research, bioethics, and health law can highlight new insights into the specificities of stroke in persons with disability, help to improve care, and stimulate timely research in this underexplored domain.
The paucity of data and direction pertaining to this growing population has engendered wide variation in clinical practice between individuals and institutions but generally a lack of therapeutic aggression4,5 and reflects a concerning and critical gap in evidence-based and ethically resilient stroke care.5–7 These exigencies are amplified through the lens of directives from biomedical ethics, disabilities rights, and health law that emphasize inclusion of persons with disabilities in health care services and research.
Ethics, law, and disability
The Rehabilitation Act of 1973 and the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) provide official legal standards prohibiting limitation of health care services for people with disabilities relative to persons without a disability.8,9 These standards are rooted in the principles of bioethics, including justice, respect for autonomy, beneficence, and nonmaleficence.10 Whereas the Rehabilitation Act devolves exclusively on federally funded institutions and programs, the ADA applies to private, state, and local government programs regardless of federal funding status. These policies define a disability as any physical or mental condition that substantially limits a major life activity such as walking, learning, or working.11 In addition to prohibiting overt limitation of medical care for persons with disability, the ADA proscribes discrimination based on disparate impact. Discrimination by disparate impact occurs when seemingly neutral eligibility criteria for a treatment or service exclude persons with a disability when broadly implemented.
Despite clear legal and bioethical guidance, however, these directives frequently go overlooked. Unequal health outcomes between persons with and without disabilities across a wide range of clinical contexts have been reported. These disadvantages are often preventable and are largely independent of differences in baseline physiologic risk profiles.12,13 A cadre of social forces contribute to these inequities, including multiform psychological biases, stigma, economic disadvantages, exclusion from research, and suboptimal access to health services.3 Despite growing awareness of these determinants of health, attention to how these particular forces shape stroke care for persons with disability has been limited.
The heavy weight of bias
Biases in clinical decision-making affecting persons with disability include ineffectual bias, fragility bias, and catastrophe bias.14 Ineffectual bias refers to the tendency to underestimate the competence and quality of life of persons with disability. Misattributions of incompetence can result in discounting the preferences of patients with a disability in favor of substituted judgments by clinicians (i.e., paternalism).15 External observers estimating the quality of life of persons with disabilities tend to vastly underestimate relative to estimations reported by those with disability themselves, who tend to endorse good or excellent quality of life.16–19 These tendencies might stem from misguided preconceptions of lower life or hedonic value. In acute settings, parallel preconceptions might result in premature withdrawal of care or withholding of life-saving treatments for patients with disabilities, often stemming from covert or overt beliefs that disabled lives are not worth living and therefore not worth saving.19 This bias comes into play not only when considering preexisting disability but also in considering future disabilities.19 For example, while decompressive hemicraniectomy has been shown to reduce death and may improve functional outcome after malignant stroke, because of high rates of disability in survivors, controversy still exists about whether and when to offer it.20,21 Despite a high incidence of disability, however, the majority of patients who have undergone this procedure report being satisfied with life without regretting undergoing the procedure.19,22,23
Fragility bias is the misperception that persons with disability are, by being disabled, more prone to perceived risks and possible harm of treatments compared to their nondisabled counterparts. Erroneous overestimation of risk due to fragility bias may skew clinician decision-making in favor of not offering otherwise beneficial treatments to patients. This may be especially true in the context of an invasive or aggressive treatment such as thrombectomy for large vessel occlusion stroke. The cognitive tendency to be unduly pessimistic when prognostication involves someone with a preexisting disability is well described.24–27
Catastrophe bias is the assumption that the subjective experience of a person with disability faced with a new medical problem is worse than it is. This presumption of magnified suffering and underestimation of resilience has been studied as a common caregiver reaction to those with a range of disabling conditions, including spinal cord injury, trauma, terminal cancer, and amputation.28,29 When catastrophe bias enters into clinical decision-making, it can animate self-fulfilling prophecies whereby choices, assessments, and outcomes are artificially swayed to match pessimistic expectations.14
Stroke trials and disability outcomes
Despite a robust evidence base supporting the utility of thrombectomy and thrombolysis in select patients, prestroke disability is commonly invoked as a reason to withhold these treatments from otherwise eligible patients who have preexisting disabilities.30–34 Although there is no clear pathophysiologic rationale for this practice, such decisions are often predicated on the absence of data pertaining to patients with disability from key trials, which tend to systematically exclude patients with disability. This is routinely operationalized in trials through the implementation of an exclusion criterion for individuals with baseline modified Rankin Scale (mRS) score greater than 1 or 2.
The mRS is the most widely used scale for quantifying disability and dependency in stroke research and practice, typically assessed as a baseline variable for trial inclusion or treatment selection and then again at 90 days after the stroke has occurred. The original scale was devised by Dr. John Rankin in 1957 and revised in 1988 as a means to assess functional outcomes in patients who have had strokes. It is an ordinal scale ranked from 0 to 5, with a separate category of 6 reserved for patients who die. In this scale, a patient with no symptoms at all is assigned a score of 0, with a spectrum of disability to 5, a patient with severe disability who is bedridden and incontinent and requires continuous care. mRS scores of 0, 1, or 2 represent grades of disability (either at baseline or 90 days after a stroke) in which a patient can live without the assistance of another person (i.e., functional independence).
Consider the case of a young patient with spinal cord injury who is unable to walk unassisted. When mRS-based guidelines that have emerged from clinical trials are implemented, such a patient would not be routinely considered for thrombectomy or thrombolysis in the event of a major stroke because of his preexisting mRS score of 3, despite a priori likelihood of benefit and sound rationale for treatment.
The importance of homogeneity in trial populations as a means of better isolating the effect of an intervention is well recognized. The competing challenge is to study a population that closely resembles the heterogeneity of clinical practice. One explanation for the practice of excluding patients with baseline disability from stroke intervention trials is the convolutions required in dichotomized mRS analyses that arise from enrollment of patients with disability; this is pragmatic and distinct from any mechanistic hypotheses about reduced benefit for this population.35–37 Given the simple dichotomized mRS endpoints that are routinely used to quantify favorable outcomes in stroke trials (which tend to define favorable outcome as an mRS score of <2 for thrombolysis or 3 for thrombectomy), enrolling patients with preexisting disabilities introduces practical difficulties in adjusting for different levels of premorbid disability when quantifying the utility of an intervention, especially when the good outcome is defined as functional independence (mRS score ≤2).36,38
The road ahead
Rather than excluding patients with disabilities from stroke trials due to anticipated complexities in data analysis, it is ethically and clinically imperative that the current orthodoxy in trial design occasioning this systematic exclusion be challenged and revised. That patients with preexisting disability face higher rates of mortality and institutionalization, care costs, and accumulated disability after stroke merely augments the propriety of ensuring that this population of patients are not categorically excluded from potentially beneficial interventions.4 Apart from satisfying the normative demands of nondiscrimination, enrolling patients with disabilities in trials can further help to ensure more representative and generalizable samples, especially as increasing longevity drives a higher proportion of patients with stroke with increased premorbid baseline mRS score over time.38 Outcome measures that capture accumulated functional dependence (such as change in mRS score from before stroke to after stroke, the modified Rankin shift,34 or the weighted mRS33) rather than the mere binary state transfer from nondependent to dependent could become standard outcomes for future studies. These outcome measures may allow more widespread inclusion of persons with disability without compromising data construct validity.38
With respect to thrombolysis, data from stroke registries suggest that those with significant disability account for <10% of treated cases, despite accounting for a much larger percentage of patients who present with acute stroke.39,40 This disparity demands careful evaluation. The argument sometimes cited that those with preexisting disability have higher chances of sustaining unfavorable outcomes erroneously ascribes anticipated adverse outcomes to the intervention rather than to the natural history of stroke itself. Neither the Food and Drug Administration nor the American Heart Association/American Stroke Association 2018 acute stroke guideline specifies preexisting disability as prohibitive.5 Multiple studies have demonstrated that preexisting disability does not portend increased risk of symptomatic intracranial hemorrhage,37 the most dreaded complication of thrombolysis. Moreover, limited data suggest that treatment with thrombolysis increases the chances of returning to prestroke functional status without increased attributable risk of mortality.41–44
Available data to guide thrombectomy decisions for patients with preexisting disabilities are similarly limited, likewise largely due to trial selection paradigms that have excluded patients with significant disabilities despite the absence of principled hypotheses to explain why this population would fail to benefit. Clinical Mismatch in the Triage of Wake Up and Late Presenting Strokes Undergoing Neurointervention With Trevo (DAWN) and Endovascular Therapy Following Imaging Evaluation for Ischemic Stroke (DEFUSE 3), the 2 recent landmark trials that established endovascular thrombectomy for patients with emergent large vessel occlusions presenting up to 24 hours after stroke, excluded patients with baseline mRS scores >1 (in DAWN) or >2 (in DEFUSE 3).33,34 Only 13 DEFUSE 3 patients had a prestroke mRS score of 2, an inadequate sample to extrapolate favorable response.45 Nonetheless, the 2018 American Heart Association/American Stroke Association guidelines delineate that for patients with a prestroke mRS score >1, “the use of mechanical thrombectomy with stent retrievers may be reasonable.”5
An analysis of the Multicenter Randomized Clinical Trial of Endovascular Treatment of Acute Ischemic Stroke (MR CLEAN) registry estimates that 11% of patients who underwent thrombectomy had prestroke functional dependence, defined as baseline mRS score ≥3. After adjustment, functional dependence was not associated with less favorable outcomes, complication rates of symptomatic intracranial hemorrhage and stroke progression were similar, and a substantial portion returned to their prestroke functional status.46 These findings are bolstered by other analyses that have found no higher procedural complication rates in those with preexisting disability, with many returning to their prestroke level of disability after thrombectomy.47,48 Preexisting disability is an independent risk factor for poorer clinical outcomes, and passive nonintervention may only amplify the likelihood of actualizing these risks.49 Taken together, these considerations argue for the inclusion of patients with preexisting disability in clinical treatment paradigms.
Resource use
In weighing the utility of acute stroke interventions for persons with disabilities, some may cite perceived resource constraints and costs as prohibitive. If resources are limited, their application must be, too; therefore, treatment of individuals with a disability is practically infeasible or unjustified from a distributive justice standpoint. A lack of normative equipoise in systematically excluding patients with a disability from receiving therapies due to perceived costs notwithstanding, such considerations merely bolster the justification for offering these interventions to this population. Those with disabilities stand to incur only costlier outcomes from stroke, including length of stay, discharge destination, mortality, and complications, if therapies are routinely withheld and preventable neurologic injury is sustained.4 Economic analyses further suggest that treatment with endovascular thrombectomy not only is cost-effective but also may significantly reduce health care use and attenuate longitudinal health care costs after stroke.6,7
The autonomy paradox
Respect for patient autonomy, a cornerstone of modern bioethics, requires understanding patient preferences and values and allowing these ideals to inform care. When approaching stroke treatment decisions or undertaking advanced care planning, clinicians should diligently explore and understand patient or surrogate preferences, especially when it comes to potentially life-sustaining interventions. If an informed patient or surrogate chooses to forego a treatment, this should be acknowledged and respected. However, to limit this choice for patients with disabilities or to make the decision on their behalf assuming that such therapies would be undesirable simply by virtue of a disability, as some have suggested,50 not only discriminates against those with disability but paradoxically further usurps patient autonomy by limiting their voice in guiding trajectories of care. Clinicians and scientists should be mindful of the potential for ineffectual bias, fragility bias, and catastrophe bias in clinical decision-making, advanced care planning, and trial design before prematurely narrowing the range of choices made available for those with disabilities.
Conclusions
Awareness of the cognitive vulnerabilities, social stigmas, and psychological biases surrounding disability that may covertly creep into treatment decisions and trial design is crucial. The action that follows from this awareness will ensure that these social and psychological forces do not magnify the impact of disability on this already vulnerable and growing population. The principles of beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice find particularly acute expression in this arena, where current practices do not clearly align with biological insights or ethical ideals.51 If mitigation of lasting new deficits from acute stroke is taken as a guiding principle, then this should apply regardless of whether there is a preexisting disability. Routinely excluding patients with disability from consideration of treatments that could prevent further morbidity and mortality may exacerbate disparate health outcomes, increase long-term costs, and undermine ethically resilient stroke care. Advocacy for inclusion of persons with disability in future stroke trials can improve equity in stroke care delivery and stimulate timely research in this critically underexplored domain.
Author contributions
M.J. Young: drafting/revising the manuscript, data acquisition, study concept or design, analysis or interpretation of data, accepts responsibility for conduct of research and will give final approval. R.W Regenhardt: drafting/revising the manuscript, study concept or design, analysis or interpretation of data, accepts responsibility for conduct of research and will give final approval, study supervision. T.M. Leslie-Mazwi: drafting/revising the manuscript, study concept or design, analysis or interpretation of data, accepts responsibility for conduct of research and will give final approval. M.A. Stein: drafting/revising the manuscript, study concept or design, accepts responsibility for conduct of research and will give final approval.
Study funding
No targeted funding reported.
Disclosure
The authors report no disclosures relevant to the manuscript. Go to https://n.neurology.org/lookup/doi/10.1212/WNL.0000000000008964 for full disclosures.
Glossary
- ADA
Americans with Disabilities Act
- DAWN
Clinical Mismatch in the Triage of Wake Up and Late Presenting Strokes Undergoing Neurointervention With Trevo
- DEFUSE 3
Endovascular Therapy Following Imaging Evaluation for Ischemic Stroke
- MR CLEAN
Multicenter Randomized Clinical Trial of Endovascular Treatment of Acute Ischemic Stroke
- mRS
modified Rankin Scale
Footnotes
Editorial, page 293
References
- 1.Gorelick PB. The global burden of stroke: persistent and disabling. Lancet Neurol 2019;18:417–418. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.GBD 2016 Lifetime Risk of Stroke Collaborators. Global, regional, and country-specific lifetime risks of stroke, 1990 and 2016. N Engl J Med 2018;379:2429–2437. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Krahn GL, Walker DK, Correa-De-Araujo R. Persons with disabilities as an unrecognized health disparity population. Am J Public Health 2015;105:S198–S206. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Ganesh A, Luengo-Fernandez R, Pendlebury ST, Rothwell PM. Long-term consequences of worsened poststroke status in patients with premorbid disability. Stroke 2018;49:2430–2436. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Furie KL, Jayaraman MV. 2018 Guidelines for the early management of patients with acute ischemic stroke. Stroke 2018;49:509–510. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Kamal N, Rogers E, Stang J, et al. One-year healthcare utilization for patients that received endovascular treatment compared with control. Stroke 2019;50:1883–1886. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Malhotra A, Wu X, Payabvash S, et al. Comparative effectiveness of endovascular thrombectomy in elderly stroke patients. Stroke 2019;50:963–969. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Gostin LO. The Americans with Disabilities Act at 25: the highest expression of American values. JAMA 2015;313:2231–2235. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Harris S. The Rehabilitation Act of 1973: discrimination against the handicapped prohibited. J Am Health Care Assoc 1984;10:51–52. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Bernat JL. Theory and practice of clinical ethics. In: Ethical Issues in Neurology, 3rd ed. Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins; 2008:8–13. [Google Scholar]
- 11.Orentlicher D. Destructuring disability: rationing of health care and unfair discrimination against the sick. Harv CR-CLL Rev 1996;31:49. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Peacock G, Iezzoni LI, Harkin TR. Health care for Americans with disabilities: 25 years after the ADA. N Engl J Med 2015;373:892–893. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Iezzoni LI. Eliminating health and health care disparities among the growing population of people with disabilities. Health Aff 2011;30:1947–1954. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Haque OSS, Stein MA. Humanizing clinical care for patients with disabilities. In: Cohen I, Shachar C, Silvers A, Stein MA, editors. Humanizing Clinical Care for Patients with Disabilities. In: Disability, Health, Law and Bioethics.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, In Press. [Google Scholar]
- 15.Kirschner KL. Physician paternalism and severe disability: strengthening autonomy through therapeutic engagement. AMA J Ethics 2015;17:500–505. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Jespersen LN, Michelsen SI, Tjornhoj-Thomsen T, Svensson MK, Holstein BE, Due P. Living with a disability: a qualitative study of associations between social relations, social participation and quality of life. Disabil Rehabil 2019;41:1275–1286. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Friedman C, VanPuymbrouck L. The impact of people with disabilities choosing their services on quality of life outcomes. Disabil Health J 2019;12:187–194. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Mestrovic J, Kardum G, Sustic A, et al. Neurodevelopmental disabilities and quality of life after intensive care treatment. J Paediatr Child Health 2007;43:673–676. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Honeybul S, Gillett GR, Ho KM, Janzen C, Kruger K. Is life worth living? Decompressive craniectomy and the disability paradox. J Neurosurg 2016;125:775–778. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Jüttler E, Bösel J, Amiri H, et al. Destiny II: DEcompressive Surgery for the Treatment of malignant INfarction of the middle cerebral arterY II. Int J Stroke 2011;6:79–86. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Hofmeijer J, Kappelle LJ, Algra A, Amelink GJ, van Gijn J, van der Worp HB. Surgical decompression for space-occupying cerebral infarction (the Hemicraniectomy after Middle Cerebral Artery infarction with Life-threatening Edema Trial [HAMLET]): a multicentre, open, randomised trial. Lancet Neurol 2009;8:326–333. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Rahme R, Zuccarello M, Kleindorfer D, Adeoye OM, Ringer AJ. Decompressive hemicraniectomy for malignant middle cerebral artery territory infarction: is life worth living? J Neurosurg 2012;117:749–754. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Ropper AH. Hemicraniectomy: to halve or halve not. N Engl J Med 2014;370:1159–1160. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Ferraro KF, Su YP. Physician-evaluated and self-reported morbidity for predicting disability. Am J Public Health 2000;90:103. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Rohaut B, Claassen J. Decision making in perceived devastating brain injury: a call to explore the impact of cognitive biases. Br J Anaesth 2018;120:5–9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Fuchs D, Fuchs LS, Power MH, Dailey AM. Bias in the assessment of handicapped children. Am Ed Res J 1985;22:185–198. [Google Scholar]
- 27.Tervo RC, Palmer G. Health professional student attitudes towards people with disability. Clin Rehabil 2004;18:908–915. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Dunn D. Challenges. In: The Social Psychology of Disability. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2014:45–47. [Google Scholar]
- 29.Adcock RJ, Goldberg ML, Patterson DR, Brown PB. Staff perceptions of emotional distress in patients with burn trauma. Rehab Psych 2000;45:179. [Google Scholar]
- 30.Cappellari M, Bosco M, Forlivesi S, et al. Reasons for exclusion from intravenous thrombolysis in stroke patients admitted to the stroke unit. J Thromb Thrombolysis 2016;42:593–599. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Ovbiagele B, Reeves MJ, Nasiri M, et al. A simple risk index and thrombolytic treatment response in acute ischemic stroke. JAMA Neurol 2014;71:848–854. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Goyal M, Menon BK, Van Zwam WH, et al. Endovascular thrombectomy after large-vessel ischaemic stroke: a meta-analysis of individual patient data from five randomised trials. Lancet 2016;387:1723–1731. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Nogueira RG, Jadhav AP, Haussen DC, et al. Thrombectomy 6 to 24 hours after stroke with a mismatch between deficit and infarct. N Engl J Med 2018;378:11–21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Albers GW, Lansberg MG, Kemp S, et al. A multicenter randomized controlled trial of endovascular therapy following imaging evaluation for ischemic stroke (DEFUSE 3). Int J Stroke 2017;12:896–905. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Kwok CS, Potter JF, Dalton G, et al. The SOAR stroke score predicts inpatient and 7-day mortality in acute stroke. Stroke 2013;44:2010–2012. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Chaisinanunkul N, Adeoye O, Lewis RJ, et al. Adopting a patient-centered approach to primary outcome analysis of acute stroke trials using a utility-weighted modified Rankin Scale. Stroke 2015;46:2238–2243. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Demaerschalk BM, Kleindorfer DO, Adeoye OM, et al. Scientific rationale for the inclusion and exclusion criteria for intravenous alteplase in acute ischemic stroke: a statement for healthcare professionals from the American Heart Association/American Stroke Association. Stroke 2016;47:581–641. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Ganesh A, Luengo-Fernandez R, Wharton RM, Rothwell PM, Oxford Vascular S. Ordinal vs dichotomous analyses of modified Rankin Scale, 5-year outcome, and cost of stroke. Neurology 2018;91:e1951–e1960. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Karlinski M, Kobayashi A, Mikulik R, Sanak D, Wahlgren N, Czlonkowska A; SITS-EAST Collaborative Group. Intravenous alteplase in ischemic stroke patients not fully adhering to the current drug license in Central and Eastern Europe. Int J Stroke 2012;7:615–622. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Merlino G, Corazza E, Lorenzut S, Gigli GL, Cargnelutti D, Valente M. Efficacy and safety of intravenous thrombolysis in patients with acute ischemic stroke and pre-existing disability. J Clin Med 2019;8:400. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Zhang W, Coote S, Frost T, Dewey HM, Choi PM. Acute stroke patients with mild-to-moderate pre-existing disability should be considered for thrombolysis treatment. J Stroke Cerebrovasc Dis 2018;27:2707–2711. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Hong KS, Saver JL. Years of disability-adjusted life gained as a result of thrombolytic therapy for acute ischemic stroke. Stroke 2010;41:471–477. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Nolte CH, Ebinger M, Scheitz JF, et al. Effects of prehospital thrombolysis in stroke patients with prestroke dependency. Stroke 2018;49:646–651. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Karlinski M, Kobayashi A, Czlonkowska A, et al. Role of preexisting disability in patients treated with intravenous thrombolysis for ischemic stroke. Stroke 2014;45:770–775. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Leslie-Mazwi TM, Hamilton S, Mlynash M, et al. DEFUSE 3 non-DAWN patients: a closer look at late window thrombectomy selection. Stroke 2019;50:618–625. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Goldhoorn RJB, Verhagen M, Dippel DW, et al. Safety and outcome of endovascular treatment in prestroke-dependent patients: results from MR CLEAN registry. Stroke 2018;49:2406–2414. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Seker F, Pfaff J, Schönenberger S, et al. Clinical outcome after thrombectomy in patients with stroke with premorbid modified Rankin Scale scores of 3 and 4: a cohort study with 136 patients. AJNR Am J Neuroradiol 2019;40:283–286. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Andrews CE, Mouchtouris N, Fitchett EM, et al. Revascularization and functional outcomes after mechanical thrombectomy for acute ischemic stroke in elderly patients. J Neurosurg 2019;1:1–8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Meyer L, Alexandrou M, Leischner H, et al. Mechanical thrombectomy in nonagenarians with acute ischemic stroke. J Neurointerventional Surg 2019;11:1091–1094. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Yan B. Selection of patients with stroke for thrombectomy must be judicious and should not be offered to any patient with large-vessel occlusion with a femoral pulse. AJNR Am J Neuroradiol 2019;40:287. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Regenhardt RW. Acute stroke treatments for patients with pre-stroke disability: are we discriminating against the disabled [online]? Dallas: American Stroke Association; 2019. Available at: journals.heart.org/bloggingstroke/2018/11/13/acute-stroke-treatments-for-patients-with-pre-stroke-disability-are-we-discriminating-against-the-disabled/. Accessed October 10, 2019. [Google Scholar]