Skip to main content
PLOS ONE logoLink to PLOS ONE
. 2020 May 18;15(5):e0231081. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0231081

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

Douglas Lee 1,2,3, Jean Daunizeau 1,2,3,*
Editor: Alireza Soltani4
PMCID: PMC7233538  PMID: 32421699

Abstract

For more than 60 years, it has been known that people report higher (lower) subjective values for items after having selected (rejected) them during a choice task. This phenomenon is coined “choice-induced preference change” or CIPC, and its established interpretation is that of “cognitive dissonance” theory. In brief, if people feel uneasy about their choice, they later convince themselves, albeit not always consciously, that the chosen (rejected) item was actually better (worse) than they had originally estimated. While this might make sense from an intuitive psychological standpoint, it is challenging from a theoretical evolutionary perspective. This is because such a cognitive mechanism might yield irrational biases, whose adaptive fitness would be unclear. In this work, we consider an alternative possibility, namely that CIPC is -at least partially- due to the refinement of option value representations that occurs while people are pondering about choice options. For example, contemplating competing possibilities during a choice may highlight aspects of the alternative options that were not considered before. In the context of difficult decisions, this would enable people to reassess option values until they reach a satisfactory level of confidence. This makes CIPC the epiphenomenal outcome of a cognitive process that is instrumental to the decision. Critically, our hypothesis implies novel predictions about how observed CIPC should relate to two specific meta-cognitive processes, namely: choice confidence and subjective certainty regarding pre-choice value judgments. We test these predictions in a behavioral experiment where participants rate the subjective value of food items both before and after choosing between equally valued items; we augment this traditional design with both reports of choice confidence and subjective certainty about value judgments. The results confirm our predictions and provide evidence that many quantitative features of CIPC (in particular: its relationship with metacognitive judgments) may be explained without ever invoking post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction explanation. We then discuss the relevance of our work in the context of the existing debate regarding the putative cognitive mechanisms underlying CIPC.

Introduction

The causal relationship between choices and subjective values goes both ways. By definition, choices are overt expressions of subjective values, which is the basis of decision theory [1]. However, one’s choices also influence one’s values, such that actions or items seem to acquire value simply because one has chosen them. Such “choice-induced preference change” (CIPC) has been repeatedly demonstrated via the so-called “free-choice paradigm” [2]. Here, people rate the pleasantness of (e.g., food) items both before and after choosing between pairs of equally pleasant items. Results show that the post-choice pleasantness ratings of chosen (rejected) options are typically higher (lower) than their pre-choice pleasantness ratings, which has traditionally been taken as empirical evidence for the existence of a "cognitive dissonance" reduction mechanism, triggered by difficult choices [3,4]. For example, people may rationalize their choice ex post facto as they think along the lines of, “I chose (rejected) this item, so I must have liked it better (worse) than the other one,” and hence adjust their internal values accordingly [5]. Over the past decade, neuroimaging studies have demonstrated that the act of choosing between similarly-valued options causes changes in the brain’s encoding of subjective values [6,7]. This has lent neurobiological support to the theory, and cognitive dissonance reduction is now the popular explanation behind a broad variety of important irrational sociopsychological phenomena, ranging from, for example, post-vote political opinion changes [8] to post-violence hostile attitude worsening [9].

This is not to say, however, that the theory of cognitive dissonance reduction has remained unchallenged. The first issue is theoretical in essence. In brief, it is unclear why evolutionary pressure would have favored post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction mechanisms, given that they could eventually induce irrational cognitive biases that have no apparent adaptive fitness [1012]. For example, in the context of evidence-based decision making, standard cognitive dissonance theory predicts the appearance of confirmation and overconfidence biases. This is simply because weak beliefs should be reinforced by subsequent choices, despite the lack of any additional piece of evidence [13,14]. At least in principle, cognitive dissonance reduction may of course have other behavioral consequences that would overcompensate for the adverse selective pressure on cognitive biases [1517]. Now, if it possessed such adaptive fitness, then it would undoubtedly be expressed in many other animal species. This is, however, an unresolved issue in the existing ethological literature [18,19]. Second, the main experimental demonstration of cognitive dissonance has also been challenged on statistical grounds. In 2010, Chen and Risen reported a methodological issue in the way CIPC had typically been measured and explained. The basic idea was that simple random variability in repeated value ratings could confound classical measures of CIPC in the context of the free-choice paradigm. The authors provided a detailed mathematical explanation for how such a statistical confound might eventually cause an apparent CIPC [20], and introduced a clever control condition. Here, both first and second value ratings are provided before any choice is ever made, thus precluding choice from causally influencing reported subjective values. Results show that significant CIPC occurs regardless of whether the choice is made before or after the second rating. Although this supports the validity of the authors’ statistical criticism, subsequent studies also demonstrated that the magnitude of CIPC is significantly greater when the choice is made before the second value rating [2123]. Taken together, the current theoretical and empirical bases of CIPC do not yet provide a straightforward portrait of why and how choice may influence subjective values.

Interestingly, recent neuroimaging evidence suggests that, in the context of typical free-choice paradigms, preference changes occur during the decision, not after it [24,25]. This is at odds with the classical post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory. Recall that people are reluctant to make a choice that they are not confident about [26]. But contemplating competing possibilities during a choice provides a new context that highlights the unique aspects of the alternative options [2729]. In turn, the act of choosing may change preferences by reappraising aspects of choice options that may not have been considered thoroughly before [30]. When faced with a difficult decision, this may enable people to reassess option values until they reach a satisfactory level of confidence [3133]. This is important, because it allows for the possibility that preference changes may be instrumental for the process of decision making, which would resolve most theoretical concerns. This is the essence of our working hypothesis. We reason that decision difficulty drives people to reassess the values of the alternative options before committing to a particular choice. The ensuing refinement of internal value representations will eventually raise choice confidence enough to trigger the decision, which may or may not be aligned with pre-choice value ratings. Critically for our theory, the more difficult the decision, the more deliberation and potential reassessment of value representations, the more likely a change of mind and the related CIPC. In brief, post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory (hereafter: post-choice CDRT) states that people come to like what they have chosen. We rather suggest, somewhat trivially, that they may simply be choosing what they have come to like.

Importantly, our working hypothesis makes two original predictions that deviate from standard post-choice CDRT. Recall that the magnitude of CIPC is known to increase with the absolute difference between pre-choice option values, which is typically taken as a proxy for choice difficulty [4,23]. We argue, however, that choice difficulty is better defined in terms of the similarity of value representations. The critical difference is that value representations may be uncertain, i.e. peoples’ feeling of liking and/or wanting a given choice option may be imprecise. In other terms, subjective estimates of choice difficulty derive from both value difference and metacognitive judgments about value uncertainty. Our first prediction regards the impact of the latter. We note that pre-choice value uncertainty is collected for each item, and is different from choice confidence (which we collect for each choice). In particular, we predict that CIPC should decrease with pre-choice value certainty. This is because pre-choice value certainty lowers choice difficulty, which de-motivates value reassessment. The prediction of standard post-choice CDRT regarding the impact of pre-choice value certainty is less clear. But if anything, we would argue that post-choice dissonance should be highest when pre-choice values were certainly equal, i.e. for choices with minimal value distance and maximal value certainty. Thus, under post-choice CDRT, CIPC should rather increase with pre-choice value certainty. Second, we predict that CIPC should positively correlate with choice confidence, controlling for the impact of decision difficulty. This is because, under our hypothesis, CIPC indirectly signals a successful improvement of choice confidence, due to reassessed values spreading apart. In contrast, post-choice CDRT would posit that choices made with low confidence should trigger the strong aversive dissonance feelings that eventually lead to CIPC. Thus, under post-choice CDRT, CIPC should decrease with choice confidence. These predictions are summarized in Fig 1 below.

Fig 1. Comparison of predicted relationships between meta-cognitive judgments and CIPC.

Fig 1

Here, we summarize the main predictions of how CIPC relate to meta-cognitive judgments under post-choice CDRT (left panel), and under our hypothesis (right panel). Blue bars depict putative partial correlations between CIPC on the one hand, and absolute pre-choice value difference (between options), pre-choice value certainty (averaged across both options), and choice confidence, on the other hand. One can see that, except for the effect of absolute value difference, our hypothesis make qualitatively distinct predictions from post-choice CDRT.

That CDRT predicts the above three-way relationship between CIPC, choice confidence and value uncertainty, was, to the best of our knowledge, never stated until now. It is thus legitimate to criticize this prediction. We will briefly comment on this in the Discussion section. At this point, suffice it to say the primary goal of this study is to ask whether CIPC can be explained without invoking CDRT. We reason that it would be the case, should CIPC vary according to the predictions made under our working (alternative) hypothesis.

Methods

Ethics statement

Our analysis involved de-identified participant data and was approved by the ethics committee of the Institut du Cerveau et de la Moelle épinière (Paris, France). In accordance with the Helsinki declaration, all participants gave informed consent prior to commencing the experiment.

Overview

We adapted the experimental design of Chen and Risen (2010), which includes two groups of participants. The so-called RCR (Rating, Choice, Rating) group of participants was asked to rate the value of a series of items both before and after making choices from pairs of items. In contrast, the RRC (Rating, Rating, Choice) group of participants rated the items twice before making the choices. As we will see, comparisons between the RCR and the RRC (control) group serve to rule out variants of Chen and Risen’s statistical confound. In our adapted experimental design, when evaluating subjective values, participants now also rated their subjective certainty regarding their value judgment. In addition, they also reported how confident they were when making their choices. This allows us to assess the impact of both subjective uncertainty about value judgments and choice confidence on CIPC.

Participants

A total of 123 people participated in this study. The RCR group included 65 people (45 female; age: mean = 29, stdev = 9, min = 19, max = 53). The RRC group included 58 people (34 female; age: mean = 33, stdev = 11, min = 18, max = 55). These groups did not show any significant difference in terms of age (p = 0.06) or gender (p = .27). All participants were native French speakers. Each participant was paid a flat rate of 12€ as compensation for one hour of time.

Materials

We wrote our experiment in Matlab, using the Psychophysics Toolbox extensions [34]. The experimental stimuli consisted of 108 digital images, each representing a distinct sweet snack item (including cookies, candies, and chocolates). Prior to the experiment, participants received written instructions about the sequence of tasks, including typical visual examples of rating and choice trials.

Experimental design

The experiment was divided into three sections, following the classic Free-Choice Paradigm protocol: Rating #1, Choice, Rating #2 (RCR group) or Rating #1, Rating #2, Choice (RRC group). Note that only in the RCR group do Rating #1 and Rating #2 correspond to pre-choice and post-choice ratings, respectively. Participants underwent a brief training session prior to the main testing phase of the experiment. There was no time limit for the overall experiment, nor for the different sections, nor for the individual trials. Within-trial event sequences are described below (see Fig 2 below).

Fig 2. Behavioural paradigm (RCR group).

Fig 2

The experiment was divided into three sessions. First, participants were asked to rate each item’s value and report their level of uncertainty regarding this value rating. In the main text, we refer to these as "pre-choice value" and "pre-choice value certainty", respectively. Second, participants are asked to chose between pair of items and report their confidence about this decision. In the main text, we refer to the latter as "choice confidence". The third session is identical to the first one, and we refer to the corresponding measures as "post-choice value" and "post-choice value certainty".

Rating

Participants rated the stimulus items in terms of how much each item pleased them. The entire set of stimuli was presented to each participant, one at a time, in a random sequence (randomized across participants). At the onset of each trial, a fixation cross appeared at the center of the screen for 750ms. Next, a solitary image of a food item appeared at the center of the screen. Participants had to respond to the question, “Does this please you?” using a horizontal Likert scale (from “not at all” to “immensely”) to report their subjective valuation of the item. Participants then had to respond to the question, “Are you sure?” using a vertical Likert scale (from “not at all” to “immensely”) to indicate their level of subjective uncertainty regarding the preceding value judgment. We refer to the latter as a value uncertainty rating (which is not to be confounded with choice confidence ratings, see below). At that time, the next trial began.

Choice

Participants chose between pairs of items in terms of which item they preferred. The entire set of stimuli was presented to each participant, one pair at a time, in a random sequence of pairs. Each item appeared in only one pair. The algorithm that created the choice pairs first sorted all items into 10 bins, then paired off (at least) half of the items within each bin, then paired off all remaining items across bins. This ensured that at least half of choices would be between items of similar subjective value (value rating difference < 1/10 of the full rating scale, as shown in previous studies to cause CIPC), but that a substantial portion would be associated with greater value differences. At the onset of each trial, a fixation cross appeared at the center of the screen for 750ms. Next, two images of snack items appeared on the screen: one towards the left and one towards the right. Participants had to respond to the question, “What do you prefer?” using the left or right arrow key. Participants then had to respond to the question, “Are you sure about your choice?” using a vertical Likert scale to report their level of confidence in the preceding choice. We refer to the latter as a choice confidence rating (not to be confounded with value uncertainty ratings, see above). At that time, the next trial began.

Results

Before testing our hypothesis (against both statistical confounds and standard post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory), we performed a number of simple data quality checks. First, we assessed the test-retest reliability of both value judgments and their associated value certainty reports. For each participant, we thus measured the correlation between ratings #1 and #2 (across items). We found that both ratings were significantly reproducible (value ratings: correlation = 0.862, 95% CI [0.838, 0.886], p<0.001; value certainty ratings: correlation = 0.472, 95% CI [0.409, 0.535], p<0.001). Second, we asked whether choices were consistent with value ratings #1. For each participant, we thus performed a logistic regression of paired choices against the difference in pre-choice value ratings. We found that the balanced prediction accuracy was beyond chance level (prediction accuracy given pre-choice ratings = 0.685, 95% CI [0.666, 0.703], p<0.001). Third, we checked that choice confidence increases both with the absolute value difference between paired items, and with the average value certainty rating (of the paired items). For each participant, we thus performed a multiple linear regression of choice confidence against pre-choice absolute value difference and pre-choice mean value certainty (ratings #1). A random effect analysis shows that both have a significant effect at the group level (R2 = 0.223, 95% CI [0.188, 0.258]; absolute value difference: GLM beta = 9.046, 95% one-sided CI [7.841, ∞], p<0.001; mean value certainty: GLM beta = 3.157, 95% one-sided CI [2.137, ∞], p<0.001). Fourth, we asked whether we could reproduce previous findings that CIPC is higher in the RCR group than in the RRC group. For each participant, we thus measured the magnitude of CIPC in terms of the so-called "spreading of alternatives" (SoA), calculated as the mean difference in value rating gains between chosen and unchosen items (SoA = [rating#2-rating#1]chosen—[rating#2-rating#1]unchosen). As expected, we found that SoA is significant in both groups (RCR group: SoA = 5.033, 95% CI [4.118, 5.949], p<0.001; RRC group: SoA = 2.635, 95% CI [2.047, 3.224], p<0.001). In addition, SoA is significantly higher in the RCR group than in the RRC group (SoA difference = 2.398, p<0.001) (Fig 3).

Fig 3. Comparison of RCR and RRC groups.

Fig 3

The mean spreading of alternatives (SoA = [rating#2-rating#1]chosen—[rating#2-rating#1]unchosen) is shown for both the RCR (blue) and the RRC (red) group. Error bars depict 95% confidence intervals. This reproduces the results of Chen and Risen (2010).

In what follows, and unless stated otherwise, we focus on the RCR group of participants. Recall that, under our hypothesis, the deliberation that takes place during the decision process is expected to cause a refinement of internal value representations until a target level of choice confidence is met and the decider commits to a choice. To begin with, we thus asked whether certainty about value judgments improved after the choice had been made. For each participant, we thus estimated the mean difference between post-choice and pre-choice value certainty ratings (across all items). A random effect analysis then shows that post-choice value certainty ratings are significantly higher than pre-choice value certainty ratings (value certainty increase = 3.781, 95% CI [1.810, 5.752], p<0.001). This finding supports our claim but does not provide evidence for or against classical post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory. We then asked whether post-choice ratings better predict choice (and choice confidence) than pre-choice ratings. First, we performed another logistic regression of choices, this time against the difference in post-choice value ratings (ratings #2). The ensuing balanced prediction accuracy is significantly higher than with pre-choice value ratings: prediction accuracy given post-choice ratings = 0.787, 95% CI [0.770, 0.804], prediction accuracy gain (post-pre) = 0.103, 95% CI [0.082, 0.124], p<0.001 (Fig 4). Second, we regressed choice confidence, this time against post-choice absolute value difference and mean value certainty. The ensuing amount of explained variance is higher than with pre-choice ratings: R2 given post-choice ratings = 0.245, 95% CI [0.209, 0.281], R2 gain (post-pre) = 0.022, 95% CI [0.001, 0.042], p = 0.02 (Fig 4). When testing for the significance of differences in pre-choice and post-choice regression parameters, we found that this gain in explanatory power is more likely to be due to value ratings (GLM beta difference = 0.763, 95% one-sided CI [0.180, ∞], p = 0.018) than to value certainty ratings (GLM beta difference = 0.158, 95% one-sided CI [-0.451, ∞], p = 0.34).

Fig 4. Prediction accuracy of choice and choice confidence.

Fig 4

Left: Mean choice prediction accuracy is plotted for pre-choice (left) and post-choice (right) value ratings. Right: Mean choice confidence prediction accuracy is plotted for pre-choice (left) versus post-choice (right) value and value uncertainty ratings. Error bars depict 95% confidence intervals.

The above results are important, because they validate basic requirements of our working hypothesis. However, they are equally compatible with both CDRT and our working hypothesis. Thus, we now focus on testing the predicted three-way relationship between CIPC, value certainty and choice confidence, which discriminates the alternative mechanisms (cf. Fig 1 above). For each participant, we performed a multiple linear regression of SoA onto absolute difference in pre-choice value ratings (within choice pairs), mean pre-choice judgment certainty reports (within choice pairs), and choice confidence (Fig 5). As expected, a random effect analysis on the ensuing parameter estimates shows that SoA significantly decreases when the absolute difference in pre-choice value ratings increases (GLM beta = -0.295, 95% one-sided CI [-∞, -0.265], p<0.001). More importantly, we found that SoA significantly decreases when pre-choice value certainty ratings increases (GLM beta = -0.065, 95% one-sided CI [-∞, -0.036], p<0.001) and significantly increases when choice confidence increases (GLM beta = 0.200, 95% one-sided CI [0.170, ∞], p<0.001). The latter findings support our hypothesis, and are incompatible with classical post-choice CDRT.

Fig 5. Observed relationships between meta-cognitive judgments and CIPC.

Fig 5

This figure shows the results of a multiple linear regression of CIPC onto absolute value difference, value certainty and choice confidence, in terms of the mean standardized regression coefficients (error bars depict 95% confidence intervals). Note that regressors were orthogonalized in that order, i.e. rightmost bars show partial correlation coefficients (after having accounted for the effects depicted by the leftmost bars). Compare this figure to Fig 1 above.

Finally, we aimed at ruling out statistical confounds. This can be done by showing that if the above statistical relationships exist in the RRC group, they should be significantly weaker than in the RCR group. We thus performed the above analyses on data acquired in participants from the RRC group, which we compared to the RCR group of participants using standard random effect analyses. First, the gain in choice prediction accuracy (from rating #1 to rating #2) is significantly higher in the RCR group than in the RRC group (accuracy gain difference = 0.0362, p = 0.008). Second, and most importantly, both the impact of absolute pre-choice value difference (GLM beta diff = -0.095, p = 0.0039) and choice confidence (GLM beta diff = 0.044, p = 0.049) on SoA are significantly higher in the RCR than in the RRC group. Note that some comparisons between the two groups turned out not to be significant (gain in value certainty ratings: p = 0.17, gain in confidence prediction accuracy: p = 0.58, impact of value certainty on SoA: p = 0.096). Nevertheless, taken together, these findings are unlikely under a chance model of random variations in value ratings.

Discussion

In this work, we have presented empirical evidence that challenges standard interpretations of CIPC, in particular: post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory or CDRT (and its "self-perception" variants). According to standard post-choice CDRT, choices made with low confidence trigger strong aversive dissonance feelings that are resolved by retrospectively matching internal value representations to the choice. We would rather say that no choice commitment is made until internal value representation refinements allow choice confidence to reach a satisfying (non-aversive) level. Our results show that CIPC varies as predicted by the latter scenario. This is important, because this implies that CIPC may be explained without referring to CDRT.

In our experiment, the correlation between CIPC and RT turns out to be significant and negative, even when controlling for pre-choice decision variables (mean correlation = -0.1236, p<0.001). Can we interpret this result as providing evidence in favor or against our working assumption? Recall that we hypothesize that value reassessment during decision-making is a critical determinant of CIPC. This might tempt one to predict that longer RT should lead to greater CIPC. The logic of this idea would be that difficult decisions cause people to deliberate longer, which in turn allows for larger changes in value estimates. But in fact, predictions regarding the relationship between RT and CIPC actually depend upon two types of implicit assumptions. First, decision deliberation is likely to unfold along two dimensions, namely: intensity and duration. From this perspective, trial-by-trial variations in RT are a good proxy for trial-by-trial variations in decision deliberation only if intensity is constant over trials. But this may not be the case. In particular, information processing rate may vary. If such variations in intensity overcompensate for variations in duration, then short RT would signal intense decision deliberation. Second, even if RT were a reliable empirical proxy for decision deliberation, the expected relationship between RT and CIPC would remain ambiguous. This is because it would still depend upon how decisions are triggered. Consider, for example, drift-diffusion decision models of value-based decision making [35,36]. Here, a decision is triggered when some decision variable (e.g., value difference) eventually reaches a collapsing bound. Importantly, those decisions that encounter little or no value spreading take more time because the system has to wait until the bound (i.e., the evidence that is demanded for triggering a decision) is small enough. In turn, choices with long RT would be those made with low confidence and small CIPC. The interested reader will find numerical simulations demonstrating this effect in the Supporting Information (S1 Text). Although the observed correlation between CIPC and RT corroborates this scenario, other alternative computational scenarios (that suggest different mechanisms for how decisions are triggered) may make qualitatively different predictions. For example, if bounds are not collapsing, then drift-diffusion models would predict no systematic relationship between RT and CIPC. Taken together, these issues suggest that the observed correlation between CIPC and RT cannot be taken as clear direct evidence that CIPC is driven by value reassessment that happens during the decision.

As a side note, we acknowledge that our group comparison (cf. RCR group versus RRC control group) suffers from the typical limitations of between-subject designs. In particular, and although we did not find any significant age difference between the two groups, trivial age differences may still in principle confound our comparison. If this was the case, then one may challenge the validity of our control RRC group. Recall that this control is important for demonstrating that CIPC exists above and beyond the expected statistical bias reported in Chen and Risen (2010). Here, we used the RRC control group to show that the magnitude of the statistical relationship between CIPC and metacognitve judgments (in the RCR group) exceeds what can be expected from a situation where decision processes cannot interfere (cf. RRC group). Given that virtually nothing is known about the effect of age on CIPC [37], it is thus theoretically possible that our observed group differences may in fact be driven by some variant of Chen and Risen’s statistical artifact. However, Chen and Risen’s reasoning does not apply straightforwardly to predictions regarding statistical relationships between CIPC and metacognitive judgments. In addition, such age confound is a priori unlikely, given that many studies previously already reported a significant difference between RRC and RCR groups or conditions [2123,38].

One might challenge our interpretation of the observed relationship between confidence and CIPC, in terms of evidence against post-choice CDRT. For example, one might argue that CIPC could occur after people commit to a choice, but before they get a feel for how confident they are about that choice. This would seem paradoxical, however, in the sense that experiencing cognitive dissonance in this context simply means feeling uneasy about one’s choice, i.e. lacking confidence about it. In any case, this line of reasoning cannot apply to the observed impact of value certainty on CIPC. Recall that we probe metacognitive judgments about value certainty before the choice, using rating scales at the time when each item is presented (immediately after first-order value judgments). Therefore, the relationship between CIPC and value certainty that we disclose empirically cannot derive from metacognitive processes that occur after the choice has been made. In any case, we are not trying to provide evidence for the fact that CIPC occurs during -as opposed to after- the decision (we discuss the related literature below). Rather, we are trying to provide evidence in favor of another interpretation of CIPC, namely: that people reassess option values until they reach a satisfactory level of confidence (at which point they commit to a choice). Or more precisely, we are trying to show that CIPC is in fact expected, without referring to any post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction mechanism. It turns out that our working hypothesis makes two quantitative predictions that deviate from standard post-choice CDRT. These predictions regard the relationship between CIPC and meta-cognitive judgments. For the purpose of validating these predictions, and therefore showing that CIPC behaves as expected, these meta-cognitive measures are, in our opinion, reliable enough.

Let us now discuss our results in the context of the existing literature affording evidence in favor of post-choice CDRT. In particular, CIPC was recently shown to only occur for choices where the agent is later able to recall which option was chosen and which was rejected [21]. This is somewhat problematic because remembering choices has no causal role under our pre-choice value refinement hypothesis. This contrasts with standard CDRT, where post-choice option re-evaluation requires the memory trace of relevant choices. The latter interpretation is compatible with the observation that, when re-evaluating items after the choice, activity in the hippocampus discriminates between remembered and non-remembered choices [39]. These two studies thus provide apparent evidence for post-choice CDRT. However, we contend that this theory remains unsupported until empirical evidence is found for memory traces of information that is critical for post-choice CIPC (namely: whether an option was chosen or rejected, what was the option’s pre-choice value, and which option was the alternative during the relevant choice). In addition, the relationship between CIPC and memory might be confounded by choice difficulty. In brief, the more difficult a decision is, the more value reassessment it will eventually trigger, the more likely the agent is to remember his/her choice. Alternatively, post-choice reports of internal values may rely on slightly unstable episodic memory traces of intra-choice CIPC. The latter scenario is actually compatible with the fact that activity in the left dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (during choice) predicts the magnitude of CIPC only when the choices are remembered [7], and also with the intra-choice CIPC interpretation of the causal impact of post-choice activity perturbations (see below). In any case, either or both of these scenarios would explain why intra-choice CIPC might exhibit an apparent (non-causal) relationship with choice memory. Finally, note that the causal implication of memory is inconsistent with the assessment of amnesic patients, who exhibit normal CIPC despite severe deficits in choice memory [40].

Now recent neuroimaging findings shed light on the question of whether CIPC occurs during or after the decision. This question is important, because evidence for a post-choice CIPC disconfirms our working hypothesis. On the one hand, a few brain stimulation studies suggest that perturbing brain activity after the choice (in particular: in the left dorsolateral and/or posterior medial frontal cortices) disrupts the observed CIPC [41,42]. Although compatible with post-choice CDRT, such causal effects can be due to the post-choice disturbance of value representations that resulted from intra-choice CIPC. On the other hand, many recent studies show that brain activity measured during the choice process is predictive of the magnitude of CIPC [7,24,25,43,44]. Unsurprisingly, key regions of the brain’s valuation and cognitive control systems are involved, including: the right inferior frontal gyrus, the ventral striatum, the anterior insula and the anterior cingulate cortex (ACC). Note that current neurocomputational theories of ACC suggest that it is involved in controlling how much mental effort should be allocated to a given task, based upon the derivation of the so-called "expected value of control" [45,46]. This is highly compatible with our results, under the assumption that pre-choice value reassessment is a controlled and effortful process that trades mental effort against choice confidence [47]. We will pursue this computational scenario in subsequent publications.

Nevertheless, we consent that CIPC may be driven by both pre-choice value reassessment and post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction mechanisms. The quantitative contribution of the latter effect, however, may have been strongly overestimated. In our view, this is best demonstrated, though perhaps unintentionally, in the results of the “blind choice” study from Sharot and colleagues [48]. Here, participants rated items both before and after making a blind choice that could not be guided by pre-existing preferences (because the items were masked). Critically, although blind choice precludes any instrumental value refinement process, preferences were altered after the choice. Interestingly, the effect size is rather small, i.e. the ensuing CIPC magnitude was estimated to be around 0.07 ± 0.03. This is to be compared with the CIPC magnitude of the RCR and RRC conditions in two other studies by the same authors [23,30], namely: 0.38 ± 0.08 (RCR condition, with non-blind choices) and 0.11 ± 0.06 (RRC condition, which was not included in the “blind choice” study). In other terms, CIPC under blind choice is smaller than the apparent CIPC that unfolds from the known statistical confounds of the free choice paradigm. Note that if this had not have been the case, then post-choice CIPC cognitive reduction effects would dominate and we would not have confirmed our predictions.

Conclusion

In conclusion, our results lend support to the hypothesis that choice-induced preference change is caused, at least partially, by an intra-choice refinement of option value representations that is motivated by difficult decisions. Such mechanism is qualitatively distinct from those considered in the context of post-choice cognitive dissonance resolution theories. We also demonstrate the relevance of meta-cognitive processes (cf. reports of choice confidence and certainty about value judgments) to choice-induced preference change. This contributes to moving forward the state of the 60-year-old research on the reciprocal influence between decision making and subjective values.

Supporting information

S1 Text. This note discusses the relationship between responses times (RT) and choice-induced preference changes (CIPC), from a computational standpoint.

In particular, this note summarizes numerical simulations performed under so-called drift-diffusion decision models.

(PDF)

S1 Code

(ZIP)

Data Availability

All relevant data are within the paper and its Supporting Information files.

Funding Statement

DL received a PhD fellowship from the Labex Bio-Psy (Laboratory of excellence of Biology for Psychiatry). https://biopsy.fr/index.php/en/ The funder had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

References

  • 1.Slovic P, Fischhoff B, Lichtenstein S. Behavioral Decision Theory. Annu Rev Psychol. 1977;28: 1–39. 10.1146/annurev.ps.28.020177.000245 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Brehm JW. Postdecision changes in the desirability of alternatives. J Abnorm Soc Psychol. 1956;52: 384–389. 10.1037/h0041006 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Harmon-Jones E, Harmon-Jones C. Cognitive dissonance theory after 50 years of development. Z Für Sozialpsychologie. 2007;38: 7–16. 10.1024/0044-3514.38.1.7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Izuma K, Murayama K. Choice-Induced Preference Change in the Free-Choice Paradigm: A Critical Methodological Review. Front Psychol. 2013;4 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00041 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Bem DJ. Self-perception: An alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance phenomena. Psychol Rev. 1967;74: 183–200. 10.1037/h0024835 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Izuma K, Matsumoto M, Murayama K, Samejima K, Sadato N, Matsumoto K. Neural correlates of cognitive dissonance and choice-induced preference change. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2010;107: 22014–22019. 10.1073/pnas.1011879108 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Voigt K, Murawski C, Speer S, Bode S. Hard Decisions Shape the Neural Coding of Preferences. J Neurosci. 2019;39: 718–726. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1681-18.2018 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Beasley RK, Joslyn MR. Cognitive Dissonance and Post-Decision Attitude Change in Six Presidential Elections. Polit Psychol. 2001;22: 521–540. [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Acharya A, Blackwell M, Sen M. Explaining Attitudes from Behavior: A Cognitive Dissonance Approach. J Polit. 2018;80: 400–411. [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Akerlof GA, Dickens WT. The Economic Consequences of Cognitive Dissonance. Am Econ Rev. 1982;72: 307–319. [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Gilad B, Kaish S, Loeb PD. Cognitive dissonance and utility maximization: A general framework. J Econ Behav Organ. 1987;8: 61–73. 10.1016/0167-2681(87)90021-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Perlovsky L. A challenge to human evolution—cognitive dissonance. Front Psychol. 2013;4 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00179 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Allahverdyan AE, Galstyan A. Opinion Dynamics with Confirmation Bias. PLOS ONE. 2014;9: e99557 10.1371/journal.pone.0099557 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Navajas J, Bahrami B, Latham PE. Post-decisional accounts of biases in confidence. Curr Opin Behav Sci. 2016;11: 55–60. 10.1016/j.cobeha.2016.05.005 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Harmon‐Jones E, Amodio DM, Harmon‐Jones C. Chapter 3 Action‐Based Model of Dissonance Advances in Experimental Social Psychology. Elsevier; 2009. pp. 119–166. http://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S0065260108004036 [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Harmon-Jones E, Harmon-Jones C, Levy N. An action-based model of cognitive-dissonance processes. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2015;24: 184–189. 10.1177/0963721414566449 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Harmon-Jones E, Amodio DM, Harmon-Jones C. Action-based model of dissonance: A review, integration, and expansion of conceptions of cognitive conflict Advances in experimental social psychology, Vol 41 San Diego, CA, US: Elsevier Academic Press; 2009. pp. 119–166. [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Egan LC, Santos LR, Bloom P. The origins of cognitive dissonance evidence from children and monkeys. Psychol Sci. 2007;18: 978–983. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.02012.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.West S, Jett SE, Beckman T, Vonk J. The phylogenetic roots of cognitive dissonance. J Comp Psychol Wash DC 1983. 2010;124: 425–432. 10.1037/a0019932 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Chen MK, Risen JL. How choice affects and reflects preferences: revisiting the free-choice paradigm. J Pers Soc Psychol. 2010;99: 573–594. 10.1037/a0020217 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Salti M, El Karoui I, Maillet M, Naccache L. Cognitive Dissonance Resolution Is Related to Episodic Memory. PLoS ONE. 2014;9 10.1371/journal.pone.0108579 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Coppin G, Delplanque S, Bernard C, Cekic S, Porcherot C, Cayeux I, et al. Choice both affects and reflects preferences. Q J Exp Psychol 2006. 2014;67: 1415–1427. 10.1080/17470218.2013.863953 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Sharot T, Fleming SM, Yu X, Koster R, Dolan RJ. Is Choice-Induced Preference Change Long Lasting? Psychol Sci. 2012;23: 1123–1129. 10.1177/0956797612438733 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Jarcho JM, Berkman ET, Lieberman MD. The neural basis of rationalization: cognitive dissonance reduction during decision-making. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci. 2011;6: 460–467. 10.1093/scan/nsq054 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Colosio M, Shestakova A, Nikulin VV, Blagovechtchenski E, Klucharev V. Neural Mechanisms of Cognitive Dissonance (Revised): An EEG Study. J Neurosci Off J Soc Neurosci. 2017;37: 5074–5083. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3209-16.2017 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26.De Martino B, Fleming SM, Garrett N, Dolan RJ. Confidence in value-based choice. Nat Neurosci. 2013;16: 105–110. 10.1038/nn.3279 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Tversky A, Thaler RH. Anomalies: Preference Reversals. J Econ Perspect. 1990;4: 201–211. [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Lichtenstein S, Slovic P. The Construction of Preference. First edition edition. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press; 2006. [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Warren C, McGraw AP, Van Boven L. Values and preferences: defining preference construction. Wiley Interdiscip Rev Cogn Sci. 2011;2: 193–205. 10.1002/wcs.98 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Sharot T, De Martino B, Dolan RJ. How choice reveals and shapes expected hedonic outcome. J Neurosci Off J Soc Neurosci. 2009;29: 3760–3765. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4972-08.2009 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Simon D, Stenstrom DM, Read SJ. The coherence effect: Blending cold and hot cognitions. J Pers Soc Psychol. 2015;109: 369–394. 10.1037/pspa0000029 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Simon D, Krawczyk DC, Holyoak KJ. Construction of preferences by constraint satisfaction. Psychol Sci. 2004;15: 331–336. 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.00678.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Reader SM, Laland KN. Social intelligence, innovation, and enhanced brain size in primates. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2002;99: 4436–4441. 10.1073/pnas.062041299 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Brainard DH. The Psychophysics Toolbox. Spat Vis. 1997;10: 433–436. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Ratcliff R, Smith PL, Brown SD, McKoon G. Diffusion Decision Model: Current Issues and History. Trends Cogn Sci. 2016;20: 260–281. 10.1016/j.tics.2016.01.007 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Tajima S, Drugowitsch J, Pouget A. Optimal policy for value-based decision-making. Nat Commun. 2016;7: 12400 10.1038/ncomms12400 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Cooper J, Feldman LA. Does cognitive dissonance occur in older age? A study of induced compliance in a healthy elderly population. Psychol Aging. 2019;34: 709–713. 10.1037/pag0000338 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38.Coppin G, Delplanque S, Porcherot C, Cayeux I, Sander D. When flexibility is stable: implicit long-term shaping of olfactory preferences. PloS One. 2012;7: e37857 10.1371/journal.pone.0037857 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Chammat M, Karoui IE, Allali S, Hagège J, Lehongre K, Hasboun D, et al. Cognitive dissonance resolution depends on episodic memory. Sci Rep. 2017;7 10.1038/srep41320 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Lieberman MD, Ochsner KN, Gilbert DT, Schacter DL. Do Amnesics Exhibit Cognitive Dissonance Reduction? The Role of Explicit Memory and Attention in Attitude Change. Psychol Sci. 2001;12: 135–140. 10.1111/1467-9280.00323 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Mengarelli F, Spoglianti S, Avenanti A, di Pellegrino G. Cathodal tDCS over the left prefrontal cortex diminishes choice-induced preference change. Cereb Cortex N Y N 1991. 2015;25: 1219–1227. 10.1093/cercor/bht314 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Izuma K, Akula S, Murayama K, Wu D-A, Iacoboni M, Adolphs R. A causal role for posterior medial frontal cortex in choice-induced preference change. J Neurosci Off J Soc Neurosci. 2015;35: 3598–3606. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4591-14.2015 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Kitayama S, Chua HF, Tompson S, Han S. Neural mechanisms of dissonance: an fMRI investigation of choice justification. NeuroImage. 2013;69: 206–212. 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.11.034 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.van Veen V, Krug MK, Schooler JW, Carter CS. Neural activity predicts attitude change in cognitive dissonance. Nat Neurosci. 2009;12: 1469–1474. 10.1038/nn.2413 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Musslick S, Shenhav A, Botvinick M, D Cohen J. A Computational Model of Control Allocation based on the Expected Value of Control. 2015.
  • 46.Shenhav A, Botvinick MM, Cohen JD. The Expected Value of Control: An Integrative Theory of Anterior Cingulate Cortex Function. Neuron. 2013;79: 217–240. 10.1016/j.neuron.2013.07.007 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Lee D, Daunizeau J. Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making. bioRxiv. 2019; 661116. 10.1101/661116 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Sharot T, Velasquez CM, Dolan RJ. Do Decisions Shape Preference? Evidence From Blind Choice. Psychol Sci. 2010;21: 1231–1235. 10.1177/0956797610379235 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Decision Letter 0

Alireza Soltani

25 Jul 2019

PONE-D-19-17905

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

PLOS ONE

Dear Dr. Daunizeau,

Thank you for submitting your manuscript to PLOS ONE. After careful consideration, we feel that it has merit but does not fully meet PLOS ONE’s publication criteria as it currently stands. Therefore, we invite you to submit a revised version of the manuscript that addresses the points raised during the review process.

Although reviewers appreciate the addressed question, both reviewers raise serious concerns about the main claim of the manuscript and whether and how this claim is supported by the experimental results. In addition, Reviewer # 2 points out important issues about the overall tone of the manuscript and implications of the findings. I think you should fix these issues or conduct additional experiments to support your claims.

We would appreciate receiving your revised manuscript by Sep 24 2019 11:59PM. When you are ready to submit your revision, log on to https://www.editorialmanager.com/pone/ and select the 'Submissions Needing Revision' folder to locate your manuscript file.

If you would like to make changes to your financial disclosure, please include your updated statement in your cover letter.

To enhance the reproducibility of your results, we recommend that if applicable you deposit your laboratory protocols in protocols.io, where a protocol can be assigned its own identifier (DOI) such that it can be cited independently in the future. For instructions see: http://journals.plos.org/plosone/s/submission-guidelines#loc-laboratory-protocols

Please include the following items when submitting your revised manuscript:

  • A rebuttal letter that responds to each point raised by the academic editor and reviewer(s). This letter should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Response to Reviewers'.

  • A marked-up copy of your manuscript that highlights changes made to the original version. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Revised Manuscript with Track Changes'.

  • An unmarked version of your revised paper without tracked changes. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Manuscript'.

Please note while forming your response, if your article is accepted, you may have the opportunity to make the peer review history publicly available. The record will include editor decision letters (with reviews) and your responses to reviewer comments. If eligible, we will contact you to opt in or out.

We look forward to receiving your revised manuscript.

Kind regards,

Alireza Soltani

Academic Editor

PLOS ONE

Journal Requirements:

When submitting your revision, we need you to address these additional requirements.

1) Please ensure that your manuscript meets PLOS ONE's style requirements, including those for file naming. The PLOS ONE style templates can be found at

http://www.journals.plos.org/plosone/s/file?id=wjVg/PLOSOne_formatting_sample_main_body.pdf and http://www.journals.plos.org/plosone/s/file?id=ba62/PLOSOne_formatting_sample_title_authors_affiliations.pdf

2) Please ensure that you refer to Figure 4 in your text as, if accepted, production will need this reference to link the reader to the figure.

3) Please include captions for your Supporting Information files at the end of your manuscript, and update any in-text citations to match accordingly. Please see our Supporting Information guidelines for more information: http://journals.plos.org/plosone/s/supporting-information.

[Note: HTML markup is below. Please do not edit.]

Reviewers' comments:

Reviewer's Responses to Questions

Comments to the Author

1. Is the manuscript technically sound, and do the data support the conclusions?

The manuscript must describe a technically sound piece of scientific research with data that supports the conclusions. Experiments must have been conducted rigorously, with appropriate controls, replication, and sample sizes. The conclusions must be drawn appropriately based on the data presented.

Reviewer #1: Partly

Reviewer #2: No

**********

2. Has the statistical analysis been performed appropriately and rigorously?

Reviewer #1: Yes

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

3. Have the authors made all data underlying the findings in their manuscript fully available?

The PLOS Data policy requires authors to make all data underlying the findings described in their manuscript fully available without restriction, with rare exception (please refer to the Data Availability Statement in the manuscript PDF file). The data should be provided as part of the manuscript or its supporting information, or deposited to a public repository. For example, in addition to summary statistics, the data points behind means, medians and variance measures should be available. If there are restrictions on publicly sharing data—e.g. participant privacy or use of data from a third party—those must be specified.

Reviewer #1: No

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

4. Is the manuscript presented in an intelligible fashion and written in standard English?

PLOS ONE does not copyedit accepted manuscripts, so the language in submitted articles must be clear, correct, and unambiguous. Any typographical or grammatical errors should be corrected at revision, so please note any specific errors here.

Reviewer #1: No

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

5. Review Comments to the Author

Please use the space provided to explain your answers to the questions above. You may also include additional comments for the author, including concerns about dual publication, research ethics, or publication ethics. (Please upload your review as an attachment if it exceeds 20,000 characters)

Reviewer #1: This manuscript describes a study that purports to challenge the mechanistic basis of post-decision cognitive dissonance theory. The tone and language throughout the manuscript needs to be reigned in substantially – this was an incremental behavioral study that shows some evidence that value and choice confidence play a role in influencing changes in valuation quantified after decision-making – it is not a death knell to the theoretical postulates of post-decision cognitive dissonance theory. Some of the hypotheses are framed as novel, but as written, it is not clear that that is the case. Likewise, the discussion frames the report largely in the context of memory research, despite the fact that memory is not measured in the study. These and additional comments are provided below:

The use of parenthetical statements in the abstract and throughout the introduction is confusing.

The writing throughout has a tone that is quite unusual for an academic paper. Just a couple of examples from among: “We take inspiration from..”; “In essence, our experimental design is borrowed from...”

In the abstract and MS, the authors need to tone down their claims about whether or not CIPC is adaptive and the implications of CIPC from cognitive and evolutionary perspectives. This extends to claims that CIPC results in irrational biases etc.

The authors state that they have two hypotheses that are original predictions:

“First, the magnitude of CIPC should increase with decision difficulty.” This has been a hypothesis in the context of CIPC for quite sometime. That is why forced choices in the majority of CIPC studies are made between items that are rated as similarly attractive/valuable/desirable etc. At least as written, it is hard to see the distinction between subjective uncertainty and difficulty – they do not seem to be orthogonal factors, but confounded. E.g., This is difficult because I’m not sure which one I’m going to choose.

“In particular, we predict that CIPC should increase with subjective uncertainty regarding pre-choice value judgment. This goes against standard post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory, because post-choice dissonance should be highest when pre-choice values are similar, with a high judgment certainty.” This second statement doesn’t make sense. CIPC is typically larger when pre-choice values are similar and there is high UNcertainty. Choices are difficult because you are UNcertain which to choose. Prior work also demonstrates effects are greater when you value the items you are choosing about more. It is not clear what is new here.

Is there a significant difference in the age across the two groups? If so, all analyses must control for age.

There are infinity symbols in many of the confidence intervals.

“Recall that, under our hypothesis, effort allocation during the decision process is expected to refine internal value representations up until a target level of confidence is met and the decider commits to a choice.” Given that effort allocation is a construct of interest, response time should be reported and analyzed? Even this cannot determine that internal value representations are refined up until a target level of confidence is met. The authors need to reframe this construct in the context of what they are objectively measuring.

The discussion of memory steps beyond the data collected, yet seems to be the primary focus of the discussion. E.g., “Our results apparently contradict the recent finding that CIPC only occurs for choices where the agent is later able to recall which option was chosen and which was rejected (Salti et al, 2014).” The authors do not test memory, thus their results cannot contradict these findings. The majority of this entire paragraph seems inconsistent with the data that were actually collected.

Reviewer #2: Choice induced preference change (CIPC) is a fascinating subject as a behavioral manifestation of the fundamental process of decision making. The problem has been around for almost 60 years. Yet how this phenomenon occur remains a mystery. One of the important questions about CIPC is when the processes causing preference change occur. The authors tried to address this question with a new behavioral paradigm, which included confidence reports at preference rating and choice between rated objects. The authors’ hypothesis is that the metacognitive processes occurring during a decision making induce the preference change. I have a sympathy to this claim itself. But the evidence presented in this study cannot prove this hypothesis.

Major Point

The processes related to the confidence report can occur after the decision making. Thus, whatever the relationship between the confidence reports and CIPC cannot prove the author’s claim.

**********

6. PLOS authors have the option to publish the peer review history of their article (what does this mean?). If published, this will include your full peer review and any attached files.

If you choose “no”, your identity will remain anonymous but your review may still be made public.

Do you want your identity to be public for this peer review? For information about this choice, including consent withdrawal, please see our Privacy Policy.

Reviewer #1: No

Reviewer #2: No

[NOTE: If reviewer comments were submitted as an attachment file, they will be attached to this email and accessible via the submission site. Please log into your account, locate the manuscript record, and check for the action link "View Attachments". If this link does not appear, there are no attachment files to be viewed.]

While revising your submission, please upload your figure files to the Preflight Analysis and Conversion Engine (PACE) digital diagnostic tool, https://pacev2.apexcovantage.com/. PACE helps ensure that figures meet PLOS requirements. To use PACE, you must first register as a user. Registration is free. Then, login and navigate to the UPLOAD tab, where you will find detailed instructions on how to use the tool. If you encounter any issues or have any questions when using PACE, please email us at figures@plos.org. Please note that Supporting Information files do not need this step.

Decision Letter 1

Alireza Soltani

22 Oct 2019

PONE-D-19-17905R1

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

PLOS ONE

Dear Dr. Daunizeau,

Thank you for submitting your manuscript to PLOS ONE. After careful consideration, we have decided that your manuscript does not meet our criteria for publication and must therefore be rejected.

More specifically, both reviewers think that the current experiment cannot discriminate between mechanisms of pre-choice value refinements from post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction, which severely undermines the main claim of the manuscript. On the one hand, choice confidence, or certainty about choice measures, is obtained only after the choice is made and not during decision-making processes. On the other hand, it is not clear that value certainty, which is recorded before the choice, can serve as metacognitive measure of decision process before it actually happens. As mentioned by Reviewer # 1, reaction time date could provide some insights but unfortunately were not included in the manuscript.   

I am sorry that we cannot be more positive on this occasion, but hope that you appreciate the reasons for this decision.

Yours sincerely,

Alireza Soltani

Academic Editor

PLOS ONE

[Note: HTML markup is below. Please do not edit.]

Reviewers' comments:

Reviewer's Responses to Questions

Comments to the Author

1. If the authors have adequately addressed your comments raised in a previous round of review and you feel that this manuscript is now acceptable for publication, you may indicate that here to bypass the “Comments to the Author” section, enter your conflict of interest statement in the “Confidential to Editor” section, and submit your "Accept" recommendation.

Reviewer #1: (No Response)

Reviewer #2: (No Response)

**********

2. Is the manuscript technically sound, and do the data support the conclusions?

The manuscript must describe a technically sound piece of scientific research with data that supports the conclusions. Experiments must have been conducted rigorously, with appropriate controls, replication, and sample sizes. The conclusions must be drawn appropriately based on the data presented.

Reviewer #1: No

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

3. Has the statistical analysis been performed appropriately and rigorously?

Reviewer #1: Yes

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

4. Have the authors made all data underlying the findings in their manuscript fully available?

The PLOS Data policy requires authors to make all data underlying the findings described in their manuscript fully available without restriction, with rare exception (please refer to the Data Availability Statement in the manuscript PDF file). The data should be provided as part of the manuscript or its supporting information, or deposited to a public repository. For example, in addition to summary statistics, the data points behind means, medians and variance measures should be available. If there are restrictions on publicly sharing data—e.g. participant privacy or use of data from a third party—those must be specified.

Reviewer #1: Yes

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

5. Is the manuscript presented in an intelligible fashion and written in standard English?

PLOS ONE does not copyedit accepted manuscripts, so the language in submitted articles must be clear, correct, and unambiguous. Any typographical or grammatical errors should be corrected at revision, so please note any specific errors here.

Reviewer #1: Yes

Reviewer #2: Yes

**********

6. Review Comments to the Author

Please use the space provided to explain your answers to the questions above. You may also include additional comments for the author, including concerns about dual publication, research ethics, or publication ethics. (Please upload your review as an attachment if it exceeds 20,000 characters)

Reviewer #1: The authors failed to address key issues raised in the prior review.

-From the most basic perspective, the methods utilized in this paper cannot discriminate mechanisms of pre-choice value refinements from post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction. Certainty about choice measures are obtained after the choice is made. There is no way to disentangle what happens during the decision to what happens after, as data about certainty were only collected after the decision. Moreover, the authors state: “Therefore, the relationship between CIPC and value certainty that we disclose empirically cannot derive from metacognitive processes that occur after the choice has been made.” As noted in the prior review, the authors have no data to support this and other assertions about the cognitive processes engaged during and after decision-making. Response times could perhaps provide some empirical support for their assertions, however, they failed to include these data in their revision.

- The authors contradict themselves when positing what standard theories predict. Here is one example: “In contrast, standard post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory predicts that post-choice dissonance should be highest when pre-choice values were a priori certainly equal, i.e. for choices with minimal value distance and maximal value certainty.” ... “In contrast, standard dissonance reduction theory would posit that choices made with low confidence should trigger the strong aversive dissonance feelings that eventually lead to CIPC.” First they state that CIPC would be highest when pre-choice are “certainly equal” – which I take to mean there is high confidence in their value. Second they say that CIPC would be highest when pre-choices are “made with low confidence” – which I take to mean there is low confidence in their value. These assertions continue to be problematic.

- The authors do not measure memory. As noted in the prior review, the paragraph claiming the results contradict recent memory-based findings steps well beyond the data. It should be removed.

- No statistics are provided regarding age and sex distributions across conditions.

- The authors fail to state that one-sided statistical tests were used in some analyses.

Reviewer #2: The authors addressed my concern about the confidence reports after the decision by stating that the other metacognitive measure, value certainty. Value certainty is recorded before the choice. But does this serve as metacognitive measure of intra-choice process? I commented on this measure (reports of choice confidence) because this is supposed to reflect the intra-choice process. The pre-choice measures of certainty about value judgments have limitations in estimating the intra-choice processes because the choice process has not happened yet. I recommend that the authors should be careful about the distinctions of the two metacognitive measures and clearly state the limitations.

**********

7. PLOS authors have the option to publish the peer review history of their article (what does this mean?). If published, this will include your full peer review and any attached files.

If you choose “no”, your identity will remain anonymous but your review may still be made public.

Do you want your identity to be public for this peer review? For information about this choice, including consent withdrawal, please see our Privacy Policy.

Reviewer #1: No

Reviewer #2: No

[NOTE: If reviewer comments were submitted as an attachment file, they will be attached to this email and accessible via the submission site. Please log into your account, locate the manuscript record, and check for the action link "View Attachments". If this link does not appear, there are no attachment files to be viewed.]

- - - - -

For journal use only: PONEDEC3

Decision Letter 2

Alireza Soltani

20 Jan 2020

PONE-D-19-17905R2

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

PLOS ONE

Dear Dr. Daunizeau,

Thank you for submitting your revised manuscript to PLOS ONE. After careful consideration and consultation between editorial members, we feel that your manuscript has merit but does not fully meet PLOS ONE’s publication criteria as it currently stands. More specifically, as pointed out by Reviewer #1, RT data could provide essential information about proving or disproving alternative hypotheses/models and therefore, analyses of RT data should be provided and discussed. In case RT data were not collected, this should be mentioned as a limitation of the study. We also feel that some of the statements about debunking cognitive dissonance theory based on the results of one experiment should be toned down. 

Therefore, we invite you to submit a revised version of the manuscript that fully addresses these and other last points raised by Reviewer #1, along with a response letter. Your revised manuscript and response letter will not be sent out to review again and instead, will be evaluated at the editorial level. 

We would appreciate receiving your revised manuscript by Mar 05 2020 11:59PM. When you are ready to submit your revision, log on to https://www.editorialmanager.com/pone/ and select the 'Submissions Needing Revision' folder to locate your manuscript file.

If you would like to make changes to your financial disclosure, please include your updated statement in your cover letter.

To enhance the reproducibility of your results, we recommend that if applicable you deposit your laboratory protocols in protocols.io, where a protocol can be assigned its own identifier (DOI) such that it can be cited independently in the future. For instructions see: http://journals.plos.org/plosone/s/submission-guidelines#loc-laboratory-protocols

Please include the following items when submitting your revised manuscript:

  • A rebuttal letter that responds to each point raised by the academic editor and reviewer(s). This letter should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Response to Reviewers'.

  • A marked-up copy of your manuscript that highlights changes made to the original version. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Revised Manuscript with Track Changes'.

  • An unmarked version of your revised paper without tracked changes. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Manuscript'.

Please note while forming your response, if your article is accepted, you may have the opportunity to make the peer review history publicly available. The record will include editor decision letters (with reviews) and your responses to reviewer comments. If eligible, we will contact you to opt in or out.

We look forward to receiving your revised manuscript.

Kind regards,

Alireza Soltani

Darrell A. Worthy, Ph.D

Academic Editors

PLOS ONE

Journal Requirements:

1) When submitting your revision, we need you to address these additional requirements.

Please ensure that your manuscript meets PLOS ONE's style requirements, including those for file naming. The PLOS ONE style templates can be found at

http://www.journals.plos.org/plosone/s/file?id=wjVg/PLOSOne_formatting_sample_main_body.pdf and http://www.journals.plos.org/plosone/s/file?id=ba62/PLOSOne_formatting_sample_title_authors_affiliations.pdf

2) Your ethics statement must appear in the Methods section of your manuscript. If your ethics statement is written in any section besides the Methods, please move it to the Methods section and delete it from any other section. Please also ensure that your ethics statement is included in your manuscript, as the ethics section of your online submission will not be published alongside your manuscript.

Additional Editor Comments (if provided):

[Note: HTML markup is below. Please do not edit.]

Reviewers' comments:

Reviewer's Responses to Questions

Comments to the Author

1. If the authors have adequately addressed your comments raised in a previous round of review and you feel that this manuscript is now acceptable for publication, you may indicate that here to bypass the “Comments to the Author” section, enter your conflict of interest statement in the “Confidential to Editor” section, and submit your "Accept" recommendation.

Reviewer #1: (No Response)

**********

2. Is the manuscript technically sound, and do the data support the conclusions?

The manuscript must describe a technically sound piece of scientific research with data that supports the conclusions. Experiments must have been conducted rigorously, with appropriate controls, replication, and sample sizes. The conclusions must be drawn appropriately based on the data presented.

Reviewer #1: Partly

**********

3. Has the statistical analysis been performed appropriately and rigorously?

Reviewer #1: Yes

**********

4. Have the authors made all data underlying the findings in their manuscript fully available?

The PLOS Data policy requires authors to make all data underlying the findings described in their manuscript fully available without restriction, with rare exception (please refer to the Data Availability Statement in the manuscript PDF file). The data should be provided as part of the manuscript or its supporting information, or deposited to a public repository. For example, in addition to summary statistics, the data points behind means, medians and variance measures should be available. If there are restrictions on publicly sharing data—e.g. participant privacy or use of data from a third party—those must be specified.

Reviewer #1: No

**********

5. Is the manuscript presented in an intelligible fashion and written in standard English?

PLOS ONE does not copyedit accepted manuscripts, so the language in submitted articles must be clear, correct, and unambiguous. Any typographical or grammatical errors should be corrected at revision, so please note any specific errors here.

Reviewer #1: Yes

**********

6. Review Comments to the Author

Please use the space provided to explain your answers to the questions above. You may also include additional comments for the author, including concerns about dual publication, research ethics, or publication ethics. (Please upload your review as an attachment if it exceeds 20,000 characters)

Reviewer #1: The authors were able to address some, but not all, issues raised in prior reviews. Further clarification shed light on other issues that need to be addressed.

1. The authors suggest that change in value occurs during decision-making. They state in their abstract “…that CIPC is at least partially- due to the refinement of option value representations that occurs while people are pondering about choice options. For example, contemplating competing possibilities during a choice may highlight aspects of the alternative options that were not considered before. In the context of difficult decisions, this would enable people to reassess option values until they reach a satisfactory level of confidence.” And then later: “Critically for our theory, the more difficult the decision, the more deliberation and potential reassessment of value representations, the more likely a change of mind and the related CIPC.” And then after that: “Recall that, under our hypothesis, the deliberation that takes place during the decision process is expected to cause a refinement of internal value representations until a target level of choice confidence is met and the decider commits to a choice.” Similar statements are made at various other points in the manuscript.

As noted in both prior reviews – if reassessing values during decision-making is a critical feature driving CIPC, then response time is an important data point that could corroborate the authors’ assumptions. Namely – the more people are “contemplating competing possibility”, the longer the decision should take to make (i.e., longer the RT). This should, in turn relate to change in values. Failure to report RT because it was not collected is at minimum a critical limitation of the study. If RT was collected and does not relate to change in value, this is an important point that must be discussed as it is inconsistent with the explanation the authors describe throughout the manuscript. I disagree with the authors’ conclusion that RT is irrelevant to supporting the contentions they explicitly note above and throughout the manuscript. If the authors have misspoken throughout the manuscript about the cognitive mechanisms they believe are implicated in CIPC, then those inaccuracies need to be corrected.

2. Grammar problems in this sentence: “In brief, post-choice cognitive dissonance reduction theory (hereafter: post-choice CDRT) states that people come to liking what they have chosen. We rather suggest, somewhat trivially, that they may simply be choosing what they have come to liking.”

3. I appreciate the inclusion of the new figure 1. Unfortunately, it was not as helpful as it could have been. This may be due to insufficient description/labeling of the Y axis (is it appropriate to conceptualize this more simply as partial correlation with SoA?) and lack of clarity about what value certainty and choice confidence represent (selected – unselected items; unselected – selected; something else?).

4. It’s great that the authors collected more data to deal with the apparent age difference across groups. I also appreciate that the authors provided statistics about sex and age differences across conditions – I am not entirely clear on why they deemed such a request as unfair as it is standard practice in most journals to report statistics on demographic features of samples. Because p = .06 is still a marginal difference, this issue should be noted as a limitation in the discussion section. Additionally, please demonstrate that results are significant after controlling for age.

5. Given that the authors are testing competing models that have different predicted directionality (positive vs. negative correlations, if Figure 1 is in fact depicting partial correlations with SoA), the use of one-sided tests in some of their most critical analyses are not appropriate. For example, results from a one-sided analysis are purported to demonstrate: “The latter findings support our hypothesis, and are incompatible with classical post-choice CDRT.”

6. “We then asked whether post-choice ratings better predict choice (and choice confidence) than pre-choice ratings. First, we performed another logistic regression of paired choices, this time against the difference in post-choice value ratings (ratings #2). The ensuing choice prediction accuracy is higher than with pre-choice value ratings (accuracy = 0.787, 95% CI [0.770, 0.804], accuracy gain = 0.103, 95% CI [0.082, 0.124], p<0.001) (Figure 3).” The second sentence does not mention anything about pre-choice ratings. Clarify. Same comment on the next analysis described in the “Second, we regressed choice confidence…” part.

7. The traditional result is that the difference in value for two items in a pair increases when the pair are similar in pre-choice value. As described in the results section: “ "spreading of alternatives" (SoA), calculated as the mean difference in value rating gains between chosen and unchose items (SoA = [rating#2-rating#1]chosen - [rating#2-rating#1]unchosen).” It is unclear if this is the effect described here: “As expected, a random effect analysis on the ensuing parameter estimates shows that SoA significantly decreases with the absolute difference in pre-choice value ratings.” Is it that SoA decreases as the absolute difference in pre-choice value ratings increase? Likewise, description of directionality is needed for results that describe SoA in relation to pre-choice value certainty ratings (i.e., SoA decreases when pre-choice value certainty ratings are higher/lower) and choice confidence (SoA increases with higher/lower levels of choice confidence).

**********

7. PLOS authors have the option to publish the peer review history of their article (what does this mean?). If published, this will include your full peer review and any attached files.

If you choose “no”, your identity will remain anonymous but your review may still be made public.

Do you want your identity to be public for this peer review? For information about this choice, including consent withdrawal, please see our Privacy Policy.

Reviewer #1: No

[NOTE: If reviewer comments were submitted as an attachment file, they will be attached to this email and accessible via the submission site. Please log into your account, locate the manuscript record, and check for the action link "View Attachments". If this link does not appear, there are no attachment files to be viewed.]

While revising your submission, please upload your figure files to the Preflight Analysis and Conversion Engine (PACE) digital diagnostic tool, https://pacev2.apexcovantage.com/. PACE helps ensure that figures meet PLOS requirements. To use PACE, you must first register as a user. Registration is free. Then, login and navigate to the UPLOAD tab, where you will find detailed instructions on how to use the tool. If you encounter any issues or have any questions when using PACE, please email us at figures@plos.org. Please note that Supporting Information files do not need this step.

Decision Letter 3

Alireza Soltani

28 Feb 2020

PONE-D-19-17905R3

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

PLOS ONE

Dear Dr. Daunizeau,

Thank you for submitting your manuscript to PLOS ONE.

Another Associate Editor and I have now read your response to the final reviewer's criticisms/comments. Overall, we think that you have addressed all issues except one (about the relationship between RT and CIPC). As a result, we feel that your manuscript has merit but does not fully meet PLOS ONE’s publication criteria as it currently stands. Therefore, we invite you to submit a revised version of the manuscript that addresses this issue as described below.

Specifically, it is not clear how "efforts" is defined for making decisions and what does "enough efforts" mean.

It seems that more efforts is needed for difficult decisions, which should result in longer RT and larger or at least similar CIPC (if the efforts are not being wasted in distinguishing between the two options), which predict no relationship between RT and CIPC, instead of negative correlation as suggested in the manuscript.

Alternatively, the same amount of effort could mean the same amount of time or even less time on difficult decisions (because the rate of effort spent should be higher for difficult decisions), which predicts that difficult trials should be faster and thus more confident, as predicted by the negative correlation between RT and confidence (e.g., Kiani et al 2014; De Martino et al, 2013). In summary, the use of "effort" to explain the observed negative correlation with RT and CIPC does not seem well justified. Therefore, we suggest that instead of using this observation as an evidence supporting their hypothesis, the authors should accept their finding on the negative correlation between RT and CIPC as a piece of evidence that might not support their hypothesis.

We would appreciate receiving your revised manuscript by Apr 13 2020 11:59PM. When you are ready to submit your revision, log on to https://www.editorialmanager.com/pone/ and select the 'Submissions Needing Revision' folder to locate your manuscript file.

If you would like to make changes to your financial disclosure, please include your updated statement in your cover letter.

To enhance the reproducibility of your results, we recommend that if applicable you deposit your laboratory protocols in protocols.io, where a protocol can be assigned its own identifier (DOI) such that it can be cited independently in the future. For instructions see: http://journals.plos.org/plosone/s/submission-guidelines#loc-laboratory-protocols

Please include the following items when submitting your revised manuscript:

  • A rebuttal letter that responds to each point raised by the academic editor and reviewer(s). This letter should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Response to Reviewers'.

  • A marked-up copy of your manuscript that highlights changes made to the original version. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Revised Manuscript with Track Changes'.

  • An unmarked version of your revised paper without tracked changes. This file should be uploaded as separate file and labeled 'Manuscript'.

Please note while forming your response, if your article is accepted, you may have the opportunity to make the peer review history publicly available. The record will include editor decision letters (with reviews) and your responses to reviewer comments. If eligible, we will contact you to opt in or out.

We look forward to receiving your revised manuscript.

Kind regards,

Alireza Soltani

Academic Editor

PLOS ONE

[Note: HTML markup is below. Please do not edit.]

[NOTE: If reviewer comments were submitted as an attachment file, they will be attached to this email and accessible via the submission site. Please log into your account, locate the manuscript record, and check for the action link "View Attachments". If this link does not appear, there are no attachment files to be viewed.]

While revising your submission, please upload your figure files to the Preflight Analysis and Conversion Engine (PACE) digital diagnostic tool, https://pacev2.apexcovantage.com/. PACE helps ensure that figures meet PLOS requirements. To use PACE, you must first register as a user. Registration is free. Then, login and navigate to the UPLOAD tab, where you will find detailed instructions on how to use the tool. If you encounter any issues or have any questions when using PACE, please email us at figures@plos.org. Please note that Supporting Information files do not need this step.

Decision Letter 4

Alireza Soltani

17 Mar 2020

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making

PONE-D-19-17905R4

Dear Dr. Daunizeau,

We are pleased to inform you that after a discussion between editors, your manuscript has been judged scientifically suitable for publication and will be formally accepted for publication once it complies with all outstanding technical requirements, and fulfills our final editorial request below.

Specifically, we found the discussion of how the DDM with collapsing bounds can account for a different relationship between CIPC and RT very useful for the readers. Therefore, we would like to ask you to include a more detailed explanation of that in the Discussion and include your "A note on DDM with collapsing bounds" as a supplemental material. We did not want burden you and/or delay the publication with another round of "minor revision" assuming that you will fulfill our request in your final submission.

Within one week, you will receive an e-mail containing information on the amendments required prior to publication. When all required modifications have been addressed, you will receive a formal acceptance letter and your manuscript will proceed to our production department and be scheduled for publication.

Shortly after the formal acceptance letter is sent, an invoice for payment will follow. To ensure an efficient production and billing process, please log into Editorial Manager at https://www.editorialmanager.com/pone/, click the "Update My Information" link at the top of the page, and update your user information. If you have any billing related questions, please contact our Author Billing department directly at authorbilling@plos.org.

If your institution or institutions have a press office, please notify them about your upcoming paper to enable them to help maximize its impact. If they will be preparing press materials for this manuscript, you must inform our press team as soon as possible and no later than 48 hours after receiving the formal acceptance. Your manuscript will remain under strict press embargo until 2 pm Eastern Time on the date of publication. For more information, please contact onepress@plos.org.

With kind regards,

Alireza Soltani

Academic Editor

PLOS ONE

Additional Editor Comments (optional):

Reviewers' comments:

Acceptance letter

Alireza Soltani

6 Apr 2020

PONE-D-19-17905R4

Choosing what we like vs liking what we choose: How choice-induced preference change might actually be instrumental to decision-making.

Dear Dr. Daunizeau:

I am pleased to inform you that your manuscript has been deemed suitable for publication in PLOS ONE. Congratulations! Your manuscript is now with our production department.

If your institution or institutions have a press office, please notify them about your upcoming paper at this point, to enable them to help maximize its impact. If they will be preparing press materials for this manuscript, please inform our press team within the next 48 hours. Your manuscript will remain under strict press embargo until 2 pm Eastern Time on the date of publication. For more information please contact onepress@plos.org.

For any other questions or concerns, please email plosone@plos.org.

Thank you for submitting your work to PLOS ONE.

With kind regards,

PLOS ONE Editorial Office Staff

on behalf of

Dr. Alireza Soltani

Academic Editor

PLOS ONE

Associated Data

    This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

    Supplementary Materials

    S1 Text. This note discusses the relationship between responses times (RT) and choice-induced preference changes (CIPC), from a computational standpoint.

    In particular, this note summarizes numerical simulations performed under so-called drift-diffusion decision models.

    (PDF)

    S1 Code

    (ZIP)

    Attachment

    Submitted filename: PLOS ONE - response to reviewers.docx

    Attachment

    Submitted filename: Response to Reviewers.docx

    Attachment

    Submitted filename: Response to Reviewers.docx

    Attachment

    Submitted filename: Response to Reviewers.docx

    Data Availability Statement

    All relevant data are within the paper and its Supporting Information files.


    Articles from PLoS ONE are provided here courtesy of PLOS

    RESOURCES