Skip to main content
Wellcome Open Research logoLink to Wellcome Open Research
. 2020 Jun 11;5:138. [Version 1] doi: 10.12688/wellcomeopenres.16022.1

What is the functional/organic distinction actually doing in psychiatry and neurology?

Vaughan Bell 1,2,a, Sam Wilkinson 3, Monica Greco 4, Callum Hendrie 5, Ben Mills 5, Quinton Deeley 2,6
PMCID: PMC7338913  PMID: 32685699

Abstract

The functional-organic distinction aims to distinguish symptoms, signs, and syndromes that can be explained by diagnosable biological changes, from those that cannot. The distinction is central to clinical practice and is a key organising principle in diagnostic systems. Following a pragmatist approach that examines meaning through use, we examine how the functional-organic distinction is deployed and conceptualised in psychiatry and neurology. We note that the conceptual scope of the terms ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ varies considerably by context. Techniques for differentially diagnosing ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ diverge in the strength of evidence they produce as a necessary function of the syndrome in question. Clinicians do not agree on the meaning of the terms and report using them strategically. The distinction often relies on an implied model of ‘zero sum’ causality and encourages classification of syndromes into discrete ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ versions. Although this clearly applies in some instances, this is often in contrast to our best scientific understanding of neuropsychiatric disorders as arising from a dynamic interaction between personal, social and neuropathological factors. We also note ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ have loaded social meanings, creating the potential for social disempowerment. Given this, we argue for a better understanding of how strategic simplification and complex scientific reality limit each other in neuropsychiatric thinking. We also note that the contribution of people who experience the interaction between ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ factors has rarely informed the validity of this distinction and the dilemmas arising from it, and we highlight this as a research priority.

Keywords: neuropsychiatry, neurology, psychiatry, functional, organic


The functional-organic distinction attempts to differentiate symptoms, signs and syndromes that can be explained by diagnosable biological changes from those that cannot 1. It has been a central conceptual tool used to categorise cause and organise diagnosis in neuroscientific medicine 2, 3. It is cited as one of the main distinguishing characteristics of patients seen by, and referred to, psychiatrists and neurologists 4. It remains one of the central organising principles in current diagnostic systems, despite efforts to deemphasise the distinction in recent years 5.

The distinction has long been derided. In his landmark textbook of neurology, Wilson (1940) 6 wrote that the functional-organic distinction “lingers at the bedside and in medical literature, though it is transparently false and has been abandoned long since by all contemplative minds”. More recently it has been criticised for maintaining an artificial distinction between psychiatry and neurology 7, promoting naïve dualism in neuroscientific medicine 1, promoting diagnostic incoherence 8, and encouraging the continued stigmatisation of mental health problems 9.

Although there has been much discussion of the required conceptual basis of the functional-organic distinction, much less has been written on how it is actually used in practice. Following a pragmatist approach to conceptual analysis in psychology and medicine 10, 11, we examine how the functional-organic distinction has been, and is, used in medical classification, by clinicians, and in research. We use this analysis to highlight inconsistencies and contradiction. We go on to illustrate the many roles the functional-organic distinction attempts to fulfil, and then suggest how future research programmes could address some of the practical and conceptual shortcomings we identify.

Historical shifts in the meaning of ‘functional’ and ‘organic’

Historically, the categories ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ have not retained a consistent meaning, scope, or relationship to diagnostic categorisation 2, 3, 12. ‘Madness’ has been considered primarily ‘organic’ or primarily ‘functional’ at different times or by different classification schemes, regardless of neurological findings 13, 14. Brain pathologies without structural lesions (such as seizures) have been included in both ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ categories 2. More recently, neuropsychiatric disorders have been interpreted in the light of cognitive science, suggesting that syndromes could be explained by impairment to distinct levels of function – either information processing (functional) or implementation (organic) 1, 15, 16.

Diagnostically, ‘organic’ has been used to label a specific syndrome of cognitive disturbance that explicitly excludes certain neurological disorders (as in the DSM-II diagnosis of “organic brain syndrome”) or categories of psychiatric syndromes akin to ‘functional’ diagnoses but accompanied by diagnosable neuropathology (e.g. “organic psychosis”). More recent diagnostic manuals have attempted to de-emphasise the functional-organic distinction although the changes are mostly cosmetic – by altering the terminology used to refer to ‘organic’ and changing how diagnoses are grouped. Psychiatric syndromes are now more commonly labelled as “secondary” to “disorders or diseases classified elsewhere” or “due to another medical condition” rather than ‘organic’ in both the DSM-5 and ICD although the implications are virtually identical.

Inconsistencies in the conceptual scope of the functional-organic distinction

Although the functional-organic distinction is often cited as a tool used to differentially diagnose ‘organic’ from ‘non-organic’ disorders 17, the terms ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ are clearly deployed in ways that indicate more complex scope when used in practice.

‘Functional’ is often used to indicate that there is no diagnosable pathophysiology sufficient to account for the aetiology of the symptoms – as implied by the use of the term ‘functional psychiatric disorder’. However, this applies to some diagnoses and not others, despite them being identical in this regard. For example, discussion of ‘functional psychosis’ 18 and ‘functional depression’ 19 but not ‘functional autism’ or ‘functional Tourette syndrome’.

Indeed, tic disorders are diagnosed solely on behavioural characteristics, and, in fact, specifically require the exclusion of “underlying neurological disorder” (e.g. F95 Tic disorders, ICD-10) and so might be considered ‘functional’. However, ‘functional’ or ‘psychogenic’ tics are considered to be a distinct category from tics diagnosed using tic disorder criteria which are considered ‘organic’ 20, 21. This is also despite the existence of tic disorders that are attributed to the direct effects of neurological disorders such as traumatic brain injury 22, 23 and stroke 24, 25. As currently used, ‘organic’ tic disorder refers to the diagnosis established through the orthodox diagnostic criteria that excludes neurological damage, but also refers to tic disorder after acquired brain injury, while ‘functional’ refers to tic disorder without neurological damage but with atypical presentation and ‘psychological’ causation. Here, the conceptualisation of ‘organic’ in tic disorders covers what would otherwise be considered ‘functional’ in other disorders.

One important use of ‘functional’ is to categorise disorders that appear ‘organic’ but aren’t 26. For example, ‘functional neurological disorders’ are disorders that present similarly to neurological disorders but without evidence for impaired neurophysiology in the individual patient that would explain the disability, indicating their aetiology is ‘not organic’ 27. However, the use of ‘functional’ more broadly to signal ‘not organic’ may solely refer to diagnosable damage to the nervous system, or may also include disorders that include damage to other bodily systems. For example, the ‘functional erectile dysfunction’ indicates an erectile problem in the absence of neurological or vascular impairment 28. Here, both uses of ‘functional’ imply ‘not organic’ but the scope to which ‘organic’ refers, differs.

With the rise of ‘functional neurological disorder’ as the preferred terminology for conditions previously labelled ‘hysteria’ or ‘psychogenic’ 29, authors have been increasingly careful to distinguish between functional disorders, malingering and other forms of illness deception 30. Nevertheless, disability that presents like neurological disorder but arises without diagnosable damage to the nervous system and is not under voluntary control (‘functional neurological disorder’), is still often grouped together with the faking of symptoms under the banner of ‘functional’ syndrome or disorder 3133. Here, problems of markedly different causation, and indeed, a markedly different nature, are equally referred to as ‘functional’.

These cases illustrate that ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ are often used to indicate ‘not the other’, although the scope of the ‘other’ varies greatly depending on the context of use.

Varying relationship to diagnostic practices that establish causality

The distinction between ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ is often treated as if the distinction is self-evident within diagnostic systems and is used as an unambiguous exclusion criteria in research (“Patients were excluded if they had an organic disorder”) and a maxim in clinical practice (“Always exclude organic causes of psychiatric symptoms”) 34. In practice, however, this process can be far more complex, and far more uncertain, than such statements would suggest.

David 17 has noted that “it is clear that the line of demarcation between organic and non-organic psychiatric disorders is not hard and fast, and in a substantial number of cases there can be continuing uncertainty” although stresses that this is not an excuse to abandon “very real distinctions between classes of disorder”. Importantly, we are not arguing here for abandoning the functional-organic distinction as entirely incoherent or futile. Indeed, there are clearly problems that unambiguously arise as a result of diagnosable biological changes, and clearly those that arise without. Nevertheless, ambiguity is probably the rule rather than exception in many practical instances of differential diagnosis.

One of the central tasks in making this distinction is attributing causality. Even when disturbed physiology is identified, clinicians then need to confidently identify it as the cause of the relevant signs or symptoms. Lishman’s criteria 17 suggests that organic disorders are diagnosed on the basis of “a high probability that appropriate examination and investigation will uncover some cerebral or systemic pathology responsible for, or contributing to, the mental condition”. What counts as “high probability” here remains undefined and, often, largely unexamined. In fact, the extent to which diagnosable biological changes need to be established, or causality can be confidently attributed, varies significantly between disorders as an inherent consequence of their diagnostic criteria and the investigative methods that become relevant because of them.

Delirium, a confusional state involving disturbances to cognition, behaviour and emotion, has a varying relationship to diagnosed physiological change in diagnostic manuals. In the ICD-10, “F05 Delirium, not induced by alcohol and other psychoactive substances” is an organic disorder but requires no physiological findings for confirmation. If someone fulfils the criteria for delirium (“disturbances of consciousness and attention, perception, thinking, memory, psychomotor behaviour, emotion, and the sleep-wake schedule”) they have an organic disorder by definition. The DSM-5 definition of delirium lists similar symptoms but includes the specifier that “There is evidence from the history, physical examination, or laboratory findings that the disturbance is a direct physiological consequence of another medical condition” although does not state how to establish what counts as a “direct physiological consequence”. Diagnostically, delirium is defined in a way that implies its organic nature from its presentation to the point where, in one definition, no further investigation is necessary and in another, simply stating it should be a ‘physiological consequence’ is sufficient, despite the fact that the causes of delirium are typically nonspecific and multifactorial 35.

In some cases, an organic basis for a disorder can be established through a hypothetico-deductive approach. For example, a patient presenting with symptoms fulfilling a DSM-5 diagnosis of panic disorder and hypercalcemia may suggest the hypothesis that the anxiety symptoms are primarily caused by hyperparathyroidism, which can cause a disturbance in blood calcium levels and increase anxiety. If the anxiety symptoms resolve or reduce after high calcium levels are treated, a diagnosis of an organic anxiety syndrome is recommended 36. Here a diagnosis is based on a mechanistic understanding of the pathophysiology, and an interventionist approach to hypothesis testing.

Other forms of ‘organic’ aetiology are established through apparent temporal relationship between the incident disturbance of the nervous system and the onset of psychiatric symptoms. Indeed, the psychoses of epilepsy are primarily diagnosed based on their temporal relationship to seizure events 37 and substance-induced psychosis is primarily diagnosed based on its temporal relationship to drug use 38. However, the extent to which the timing of these events can be confidently established is likely to vary due to the reliability of the informants, and the difficulty with judging the onset of psychosis itself, potentially leading to a significant role of informed speculation in the diagnostic process to help account for uncertainty.

In contrast, some organic disorders are diagnosed on a more general process of inductive inference. As Gagnon et al. 39 note, socially challenging or inappropriate behaviour is often diagnosed as organic personality disorder following a brain lesion without establishing that the particular lesion is causally responsible for the change or that personality difficulties were not present before the brain injury occurred. Evidence suggests that personality change can occur regardless of lesion location although personality change is more common in those with pre-frontal cortex lesions 40. However, the process of attributing the cause to a specific lesion, rendering it ‘organic personality change’, is under-determined by the presence of a lesion itself. This is particularly in light of the wide range of biopsychosocial factors that can lead to personality change after the experience of brain injury 41. In law, the process of attributing cause is conceptualised as the ‘but for test’ where causation is granted where the outcome would not occur ‘but for’ the injury, although even with this depth of examination, considerable ambiguity can remain 42. Hence, a diagnosis of ‘organic personality change’ requires a separation of ‘organic’ causes from ‘psychological’ ones, before ordering them into a hierarchy of likely importance which can only be made on a ‘most likely’ basis.

Inconsistent use and interpretation in clinical practice

Considering there are no accepted criteria for distinguishing ‘functional’ from ‘organic’ problems across diagnoses, nor are there reliable concepts to which the terms apply across all use cases, one question is how clinicians understand the terms and concepts they regularly use. Given the importance of the functional-organic distinction for diagnosis and the prioritisation of treatment, it is perhaps surprising this has not been researched more widely. However, some existing studies have examined the question.

A mixed-methods study by Kanaan et al. 26 asked neurologists what they understood by the term ‘functional’. Survey options included “Abnormal brain function”, “Abnormal body function”, “Psychiatric problem”, and “Not organic”. The results are reproduced in Table 1 but notably all options were considered to be valid meanings of ‘functional’ by at least 20% of respondents with “not organic” being the most frequently chosen with many respondents choosing several meanings.

Table 1. Responses to survey question by neurologists on the meaning of ‘functional’ from Kanaan et al. 26.

This table is reproduced under the terms of the Creative Common Attribution Non-commercial 2.0 (CC BY-NC 2.0) license.

Selection Proportion (%)
choosing the selection
at all
Proportion (%) of those
choosing only that
selection
Abnormal brain function 127/349 (36%) 45/127 (35%)
Abnormal body function 77/349 (22%) 17/77 (22%)
Psychiatric problem 104/349 (30%) 29/104 (28%)
Not organic 216/349 (62%) 128/216 (59%)

An earlier study by Kanaan et al. 43 conducted in-depth interviews with consultant neurologists about how they understood conversion disorder – perhaps the paradigmatic functional disorder for neurologists. They endorsed psychological models of causation but didn’t feel that it was their role to derive a psychological explanation and didn’t clearly distinguish involuntary symptoms from deliberately feigning and deception under this definition.

A survey by Mace and Trimble 44 asked 168 British neurologists which terminology they preferred for syndromes that lack a physical explanation for the symptoms and also included a question on which syndromes should be classified as ‘functional’. The top three responses covered a remarkably wide range and included “pseudoseizures” (68%) – episodes that typically resemble tonic-clonic seizures but without accompanying seizure activity in the brain, “anxiety neurosis” (62%) – psychiatric disorders of disabling anxiety, and “Munchausen's syndrome” (61%) – a form of illness deception involving the conscious presentation of sham symptoms.

A survey of 391 Canadian psychiatrists and psychiatric residents by Benrimoh et al. 45 asked respondents to give opinions on the use of the phrase “organic causes” in their clinical work, and in psychiatry more generally. Over half of respondents (55.9%) reported they used the phrase regularly. There was considerable variation in whether the phrase was considered stigmatising, implied dualism, or led to unhelpful treatment by the medical system. Indeed, while almost 56% of psychiatrists reported using it regularly, far fewer (just under 30%) thought its use was appropriate. Many reported using it due to its assumed pragmatic function within the healthcare system, assuming, for example, that other clinicians would dismiss psychiatric patients’ reports of physical health symptoms unless they communicated ‘organic’ causation on the patients’ behalf.

Although small in number, these studies suggest that clinicians do not have a clear or consistent conceptual basis when interpreting or deploying the terms ‘functional’ and ‘organic’, despite using them frequently.

Cultural perceptions and political uses

The functional-organic distinction has an important political dimension as attributing causes at the level of mind and body, to give a typical lay reading, or to ‘functional’ or ‘organic’, in its broader and more complex bio-medical application, imply very different things about the patient’s autonomy, responsibility and deservedness with ‘organic’ disorders seen as more deserving of care and individuals less responsible for their predicament 46, 47. The distinction also affects the prestige of the illness, with ‘organic’ disorders considered more prestigious than ‘functional’ disorders by both professionals and the public 48, 49 and with the prestige conferred on relevant medical specialities tending to reflect this same hierarchy 50.

The functional-organic distinction is also a basis for challenging medical authority. Challenges to the legitimacy of psychiatry have frequently suggested that valid medical specialities are necessarily identified by their focus on ‘organic’ conditions 51, 52 with some authors explicitly adopting the functional-organic distinction to argue against the legitimacy of psychiatric practice in the domain of ‘functional’ diagnoses 53, 54 although seemingly without a critical insight into the difficulties inherent in this distinction itself. Similarly, most debates over the legitimacy of syndromes included under the broad category of ‘medically unexplained symptoms’ tend to involve grassroots patient pressure to accept a largely or solely ‘organic’ explanation for the symptoms 55. Examples where patients lobby for non-organic explanations of controversial syndromes are far harder to come by.

Implications

The functional-organic distinction is unhelpfully linear and unhelpfully static

One of the notable things about the functional-organic distinction is its implied commitment to ‘zero sum’ causality 1. ‘Functional’ and ‘organic’ aetiology is conceived as if attributing more ‘organic’ causality necessarily implies the attribution of less ‘functional’ causality. This is apparent in the concept of “functional overlay” 56, 57 where a certain proportion of the total presentation is attributed to either ‘organic’ or ‘functional’ aetiology, and the wide-ranging discussion of differential diagnosis between syndromes apparently on either side of the aetiological distinction 5860. These diagnostic categories imply syndromes exist in “purely functional” or “purely organic” equivalents, presumably representing the far ends of a functional-organic spectrum.

This conceptualisation largely rejects a dynamic relationship between neurological disorder, experience, behaviour, and context. This is despite the fact that the interaction between neurocognitive capacity, perception, affect, action, and context is perhaps one of the central assumptions of the neurocognitive sciences 6165. These dynamic considerations become starker still when considering the range of difficulties likely to be analysed in terms of potential ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ components. While functions like memory may provide a relatively straightforward case (and are clearly complicated enough as they are), emotional responses and related psychiatric disorders become more complex still.

Taking depression as an example, it is very likely that the risk of depression after stroke is raised by damage to brain circuits involved in the control of emotion 66 and although there may be instances of post-stroke depression which are almost entirely accounted for these brain changes, the causal factors for the majority of patients are likely to include a dynamic interaction between personal, social and neuropathological factors 6769. Here, it is clear there is a marked disconnect between the best available science on the causes of depression after neurological disorder and the extent to which the functional-organic distinction can encapsulate these complex causal pathways, either through formal diagnoses or as a way of ‘apportioning causality’.

Current diagnostic technology defines the limits of the functional-organic distinction

Another limitation of the functional-organic distinction is its reliance on clinical diagnostic technology as an arbiter of what is considered ‘organic’. Consequently, its limits lie within the extent to which this technology can detect neuropathology on an individual basis, rather than the best available science on likely causation.

In several instances, we know that damage to the nervous system is a major contributor to causality but because clinical diagnosis is unable to measure its presence, the relevant syndromes are rarely considered ‘organic’. For example, Haag et al.’s 70 review of brain injury in women subject to intimate partner violence report a prevalence of between 19% and 75% – most commonly in the form of mild traumatic brain injury where no changes can be detected on diagnostic neuroimaging. However, brain changes can be detected in group studies as altered cognition and disturbed functional connectivity 71. More generally, the neuropathological contributions to mild traumatic brain injury have been well-established 72 and the increased risk of mental health problems confidently identified 73. Nevertheless, the mental health consequences of intimate partner violence are almost always conceptualised in terms of social and emotional causality, with no mention of brain injury 74, 75. Importantly, this is not simply a matter for researchers and the development of better theoretical models. A clinician who is presented with someone who has mental health problems for which mild traumatic brain injury has been a significant causal factor will be unable to confidentially establish any ‘organic’ changes through neurological examination because such damage does not lead to neuropathology than can be currently detected on an individual basis 76.

It is also worth noting the reverse scenario, where clinical diagnostics regularly result in evidence for neuropathology that is often dismissed as aetiologically irrelevant despite good evidence that it is a risk factor for poor functioning and poor mental health. For example, clinically abnormal computed tomography (CT) or magnetic resonance imagining (MRI) findings are present in high proportions of individuals with first episode psychosis (64.2% 77; 17.6% 78; 19.2% 79). The vast majority of these findings are small but detectable pathologies, typically white matter hyperintensities, that are frequently dismissed as ‘not clinically relevant’. This is despite the fact that exactly these changes have been found to predict mental health problems, poor outcome for mental health problems 8083 and poor cognition 84 in otherwise neurologically unaffected adults across the lifespan.

We note psychosis is typically considered a ‘functional’ disorder, a framing which we speculate might at least partly account for why such clinical neurological findings are more likely to be dismissed in terms of explaining causality. But we also note the criterion for which abnormal findings were considered ‘organic’ and aetiologically relevant to psychosis in these studies 7779, namely that they were of a nature that ‘changed clinical management’ – presumably leading to a referral to neurologists for additional treatment. Here, ‘organic’ is not signifying the best evidence for likely causality but indicating a need to change clinical management.

Social power in definition and application

Epistemic and testimonial injustice refers to the situation where a person's testimony and the credibility of their claims are questioned on the basis of negative stereotypes 85. Kidd and Carel 86 have cited ill persons as particularly likely to be subjective to testimonial injustice, due to wide-ranging stereotypes about the effect of pathologies on individuals. Neurological disorders can obviously affect the accuracy of someone’s testimony (for example, through memory deficits). However, as Kidd and Carel note, this does not change the fact that people with neurological disorders may still be subject to unjustified dismissals of valid concerns based on inaccurate ideas about personal unreliability.

We note here the significant potential for epistemic injustice given common stereotypes about ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ illnesses in terms of autonomy, responsibility and deservedness 46. Research on carer and professional perceptions of ‘challenging’ behaviour in survivors of brain injury show clear evidence for the active construction of the causes of behaviour 87, 88. Here, the extent to which the person’s troubling behaviour is given a ‘brain injury’ or ‘intentional’ explanation depends heavily on the motivations of the individual doing the interpretation. Huet et al. 89 reported exactly this process of active interpretation by health professionals who tended to reframe aggressive and angry behaviour as involuntary, thereby maintaining a ‘good person’ understanding of the patient. However, this interpretation also has the potential to erase any valid frustrations or concerns that may have motivated the behaviour and renders the individual socially inert.

Although not widely researched, we note that the concept of ‘inappropriate’ or ‘challenging’ behaviour relies heavily on social and cultural norms and has the potential to raise important ethical issues. Cases of changes in sexual preference and sexual orientation after brain injury have been interpreted in terms of pathological alteration to the brain circuits mediating sexual preference 90. But it is also possible that the brain injury altered the capacity to strategically inhibit pre-existing desires, or that the change was a conscious decision after an important life event, although these latter interpretations require a starker form of social attribution that may involve re-evaluating, rightly or wrongly, the person in question, depending on others’ approval of their new behaviour. We note that changes subject to fewer prejudices and typically seen in more benign light, such as a sudden interest in producing art after brain injury, are usually explained in terms of ‘disinhibition’ 91, 92 which has the function of attributing the new socially acceptable activity to the ‘self’ rather than to pathology, which has simply ‘released’ it.

Common to these accounts is that the testimony of patients features little in the explanation of the behaviour and we suggest that this situation occurs frequently in the process of providing both clinical accounts and scientific explanations. Furthermore, we also note that the testimony of people affected by neurological and neuropsychiatric conditions is almost entirely absent from the scientific and clinical debates that have formed the conceptual basis of the functional-organic distinction. Here, we argue that inclusion of first-person perspectives is essential to inform several important areas of practice and scientific understanding.

Firstly, it would inform clinical work in terms of better understanding the process of being subject to the functional-organic distinction, how it is perceived, experienced and understood by patients. Secondly, in terms of scientific understanding, it would provide a phenomenology of experience to better understand the interaction between, for example, injury and autonomy. These approaches are now commonplace in psychiatry, where understanding experience is considered to be a central component in advancing the development and delivery of health care systems 93 and where understanding subjective experience informs neuropsychological theories of causation 94. Although some studies have been conducted on the experience of health care, as far as we know, no research has ever been conducted with, for example, survivors of brain injury that aims to inform the science of how neurological-level and personal-level processes interact.

It is also the case that the priorities of people who use healthcare systems may differ markedly from the priorities of healthcare systems themselves. Similarly, the research priorities of researchers and patients have been found to differ substantially 95. We note here that the functional-organic distinction is a conceptual tool developed by medicine to try and solve a particular set of problems, but one important focus of research should be to investigate how well these problems actually map onto the priorities of those seeking help.

Conclusions

Before tackling the question of what the functional-organic distinction is doing in psychiatry and neurology, it is perhaps worth noting what it is not doing. It is not reliably distinguishing between aetiology at different levels (physiological, psychological etc) across contexts. Indeed, the extent to which it can reliably distinguish between types of causes for particular signs, symptoms and syndromes seems to differ depending on the signs, symptoms and syndromes being assessed. In some cases, conceptual inconsistencies and difficulties with practical diagnosis render this an ambition rather than a reliable outcome, partly due to the multiplicity of meanings represented by the terms themselves. Rather than a general distinction, it is more akin to various local distinctions, each defined and limited by context.

Importantly, it seems that one of the major functions of this distinction is to provide a justification and language to allow clinicians to prioritise healthcare interventions. Indeed, considering the complex nature of neuropsychiatric disorders where causes are likely dynamic, reciprocal and span levels of explanation, the functional-organic distinction often seems like a tool that helps determine treatment priority dressed up in the language of causation. To reiterate, it is clear that there are syndromes almost entirely accounted for by diagnosable pathophysiological changes, and those that are not, but most neuropsychiatric disorders are not at these extremes, and are caused by multiple interacting factors.

Rhetorically, however, talk of ‘organic’ causation retains a caché, influence and credibility that ‘functional’ causation does not, and it is clear that this rhetoric is used strategically by healthcare professionals to work within healthcare systems – mostly, it must be said, in good faith attempts to provide effective care. Nevertheless, the extent to which the strategic simplification and complex scientific reality influence and limit each other should be more widely investigated.

Perhaps most striking is the fact that these debates almost entirely exclude the priorities and experiences of those most affected by them – namely patients with challenges of mind, brain, emotion, behaviour, and society, whose difficulties are interpreted in terms of ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ components. We highlight how the inclusion of these perspectives are likely to be essential for better science and better healthcare in this area.

Data availability

Underlying data

No data are associated with this article.

Acknowledgements

Many thanks for Prof Adam Zeman for helpful comments during the preparation of this manuscript.

Funding Statement

This work was supported by the Wellcome Trust [200589]. This work was produced as part of Wellcome’s The Hub Award.

The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

[version 1; peer review: 3 approved]

References

  • 1. Kendler KS: The dappled nature of causes of psychiatric illness: replacing the organic-functional/hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based pluralism. Mol Psychiatry. 2012;17(4):377–388. 10.1038/mp.2011.182 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2. Beer MD: The dichotomies: psychosis/neurosis and functional/organic: a historical perspective. Hist Psychiatry. 1996;7(26 Pt 2):231–255. 10.1177/0957154X9600702603 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3. Reynolds EH: Structure and Function in Neurology and Psychiatry. Br J Psychiatry. 1990;157:481–490. 10.1192/bjp.157.4.481 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4. Martin JB: The Integration of Neurology, Psychiatry, and Neuroscience in the 21st Century. Am J Psychiatry. 2002;159(5):695–704. 10.1176/appi.ajp.159.5.695 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5. Tyrer P: A comparison of DSM and ICD classifications of mental disorder. Advances in Psychiatric Treatment. 2014;20(4):280–285. 10.1192/apt.bp.113.011296 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 6. Wilson K: Neurology.Hafner Pub Co Inc New York.1940. [Google Scholar]
  • 7. Zeman A: Neurology is psychiatry—and vice versa. Pract Neurol. 2014;14(3):136–144. 10.1136/practneurol-2013-000761 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8. Sachdev P: A critique of ‘organic’ and its proposed alternatives. Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 1996;30(2):165–170. 10.3109/00048679609076090 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9. Ungar T, Knaak S: The hidden medical logic of mental health stigma. Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 2013;47(7):611–612. 10.1177/0004867413476758 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10. Cornish F, Gillespie A: A Pragmatist Approach to the Problem of Knowledge in Health Psychology. J Health Psychol. 2009;14(6):800–9. 10.1177/1359105309338974 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11. Lewis B: The Biopsychosocial Model and Philosophic Pragmatism: Is George Engel a Pragmatist? Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2007;14:299–310. 10.1353/ppp.0.0142 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 12. Berrios GE, Luque R, Villagrán JM: Schizophrenia: a conceptual history. International Journal of Psychology and Psychological Therapy. 2003;3:111–140. Reference Source [Google Scholar]
  • 13. Beer MD: The endogenous psychoses: a conceptual history. Hist Psychiatry. 1996;7(25):001–029. 10.1177/0957154X9600702501 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14. Berrios GE, Beer D: The notion of unitary psychosis: a conceptual history. Hist Psychiatry. 1994;5(17 Pt 1):013–036. 10.1177/0957154X9400501702 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15. Kahn RM, Arbib MA: A cybernetic approach to childhood psychosis. J Autism Child Schizophr. 1973;3(3):261–273. 10.1007/BF01538284 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16. Pylyshyn ZW: Computational models and empirical constraints. Behav Brain Sci. 1978;1:91–99. 10.1017/S0140525X00059793 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 17. David AS: Basic Concepts in Neuropsychiatry. Lishman’s Organic Psychiatry: A Textbook of Neuropsychiatry. 2009;1–27. 10.1002/9781444316803.ch1 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 18. Fryar-Williams S, Strobel JE: Biomarker Case-Detection and Prediction with Potential for Functional Psychosis Screening: Development and Validation of a Model Related to Biochemistry, Sensory Neural Timing and End Organ Performance. Front Psychiatry. 2016;7:48. 10.3389/fpsyt.2016.00048 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19. Starkstein SE, Rabins PV, Berthier ML, et al. : Dementia of depression among patients with neurological disorders and functional depression. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci. 1989;1(3):263–268. 10.1176/jnp.1.3.263 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20. Baizabal-Carvallo JF, Fekete R: Recognizing Uncommon Presentations of Psychogenic (Functional) Movement Disorders. Tremor Other Hyperkinet Mov (N Y). 2015;5:279. 10.7916/D8VM4B13 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 21. Demartini B, Ricciardi L, Parees I, et al. : A positive diagnosis of functional (psychogenic) tics. Eur J Neurol. 2015;22(3):527–e36. 10.1111/ene.12609 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22. Krauss JK, Jankovic J: Tics secondary to craniocerebral trauma. Mov Disord. 1997;12(5):776–782. 10.1002/mds.870120527 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23. Ranjan N, Nair KPS, Romanoski C, et al. : Tics after traumatic brain injury. Brain Injury. 2011;25(6):629–633. 10.3109/02699052.2011.572944 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 24. Gomis M, Puente V, Pont-Sunyer C, et al. : Adult onset simple phonic tic after caudate stroke. Mov Disord. 2008;23(5):765–766. 10.1002/mds.21955 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 25. Kwak CH, Jankovic J: Tourettism and dystonia after subcortical stroke. Mov Disord. 2002;17(4):821–825. 10.1002/mds.10207 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26. Kanaan RA, Armstrong D, Wessely SC: The function of ‘functional’: a mixed methods investigation. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 2012;83(3):248–250. 10.1136/jnnp-2011-300992 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27. Espay AJ, Aybek S, Carson A, et al. : Current Concepts in Diagnosis and Treatment of Functional Neurological Disorders. JAMA Neurol. 2018;75(9):1132–1141. 10.1001/jamaneurol.2018.1264 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28. Farre JM, Fora F, Lasheras MG: Specific aspects of erectile dysfunction in psychiatry. Int J Impot Res. 2004;16(Suppl 2):S46–S49. 10.1038/sj.ijir.3901243 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 29. Edwards MJ, Stone J, Lang AE: From psychogenic movement disorder to functional movement disorder: It’s time to change the name. Mov Disord. 2014;29(7):849–852. 10.1002/mds.25562 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30. Stone J, Zeman A, Sharpe M: Functional weakness and sensory disturbance. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 2002;73(3):241–245. 10.1136/jnnp.73.3.241 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31. Berry H: Chronic Whiplash Syndrome as a Functional Disorder. Arch Neurol. 2000;57(4):592–594. 10.1001/archneur.57.4.592 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32. Enzenauer R, Morris W, O’Donnell T, et al. : Terminology of Functional Disorders. In: Enzenauer R, Morris W, O’Donnell T, et al.(eds) Functional Ophthalmic Disorders: Ocular Malingering and Visual Hysteria Springer International Publishing, Cham.2014;1–10. 10.1007/978-3-319-08750-4_1 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 33. Silber TJ: Functional disorders during adolescence. Medical Aspects of Human Sexuality. 1985;19(9):42–57. Reference Source [Google Scholar]
  • 34. Amad A, Fovet T, Geoffroy PA: Keep calm: Psychiatric disorders are organic! The power of words in medicine. Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 2016;50(1):100–1. 10.1177/0004867415601730 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35. Lee S, Gottlieb M, Mulhausen P, et al. : Recognition, prevention, and treatment of delirium in emergency department: An evidence-based narrative review. Am J Emerg Med. 2020;38(2):349–357. 10.1016/j.ajem.2019.158454 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36. Geffken GR, Ward HE, Staab JP, et al. : Psychiatric Morbidity in Endocrine Disorders. Psychiatr Clin North Am. 1998;21(2):473–489. 10.1016/s0193-953x(05)70017-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37. Maguire M, Singh J, Marson A: Epilepsy and psychosis: a practical approach. Pract Neurol. 2018;18(2):106–114. 10.1136/practneurol-2017-001775 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38. Wilson L, Szigeti A, Kearney A, et al. : Clinical characteristics of primary psychotic disorders with concurrent substance abuse and substance-induced psychotic disorders: A systematic review. Schizophr Res. 2018;197:78–86. 10.1016/j.schres.2017.11.001 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 39. Gagnon J, Bouchard MA, Rainville C: Differential diagnosis between borderline personality disorder and organic personality disorder following traumatic brain injury. Bull Menninger Clin. 2006;70(1):1–28. 10.1521/bumc.2006.70.1.1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40. Barrash J, Asp E, Markon K, et al. : Dimensions of personality disturbance after focal brain damage: Investigation with the Iowa Scales of Personality Change. J Clin Exp Neuropsychol. 2011;33(8):833–852. 10.1080/13803395.2011.561300 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41. Yeates GN, Gracey F, Mcgrath JC: A biopsychosocial deconstruction of “personality change” following acquired brain injury. Neuropsychol Rehabil. 2008;18(5–6):566–589. 10.1080/09602010802151532 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 42. Morse SJ: Brain and Blame Essay. Geo LJ.1996;84:527–550. [Google Scholar]
  • 43. Kanaan R, Armstrong D, Barnes P, et al. : In the psychiatrist’s chair: how neurologists understand conversion disorder. Brain. 2009;132(Pt 10):2889–2896. 10.1093/brain/awp060 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44. Mace CJ, Trimble MR: 'Hysteria', 'functional' or 'psychogenic'? A survey of British neurologists’ preferences. J R Soc Med. 1991;84(8):471–475. 10.1177/014107689108400808 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45. Benrimoh D, Pomerleau VJ, Demoustier A, et al. : Why We Still Use “Organic Causes”: Results From a Survey of Psychiatrists and Residents. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci. 2019;31(1):57–64. 10.1176/appi.neuropsych.18050099 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 46. Greco M: On illness and value: biopolitics, psychosomatics, participating bodies. Med Humanit. 2019;45(2):107–115. 10.1136/medhum-2018-011588 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47. Miresco MJ, Kirmayer LJ: The Persistence of Mind-Brain Dualism in Psychiatric Reasoning About Clinical Scenarios. Am J Psychiatry. 2006;163(5):913–918. 10.1176/ajp.2006.163.5.913 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48. Album D, Westin S: Do diseases have a prestige hierarchy? A survey among physicians and medical students. Soc Sci Med. 2008;66(1):182–188. 10.1016/j.socscimed.2007.07.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 49. Rosoff SM, Leone MC: The public prestige of medical specialties: Overviews and undercurrents. Soc Sci Med. 1991;32(3):321–326. 10.1016/0277-9536(91)90110-x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50. Norredam M, Album D: Prestige and its significance for medical specialties and diseases. Scand J Public Health. 2007;35(6):655–661. 10.1080/14034940701362137 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51. Breggin PR: Extreme Psychospiritual States Versus Organic Brain Disease: Bringing Together Science and the Human Factor. J Humanist Psychol. 2019;59(5):686–696. 10.1177/0022167818761975 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 52. Szasz T: The myth of mental illness: 50 years later. The Psychiatrist. 2011;35(5):179–182. 10.1192/pb.bp.110.031310 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 53. Awenat F, Berger B, Coles S, et al. : Classification of behaviour and experience in relation to functional psychiatric diagnoses: Time for a paradigm shift. Leicester: British Psychological Society. 2013. Reference Source [Google Scholar]
  • 54. Johnstone L, Boyle M: The Power Threat Meaning Framework: An Alternative Nondiagnostic Conceptual System. J Humanist Psychol. 2018; 0022167818793289. 10.1177/0022167818793289 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 55. Greco M: The classification and nomenclature of ‘medically unexplained symptoms’: Conflict, performativity and critique. Soc Sci Med. 2012;75(12):2362–2369. 10.1016/j.socscimed.2012.09.010 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56. Carter AB: The Functional Overlay. Lancet. 1967;290(7527):1196–1200. 10.1016/S0140-6736(67)91909-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 57. Florence DW, Miller TC: Functional Overlay in Work-Related Injury. A System for Differentiating Conscious From Subconscious Motivation of Persisting Symptoms. Postgrad Med. 1985;77(8):97–108. 10.1080/00325481.1985.11699028 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58. Pandey S, Nahab F, Aldred J, et al. : Post-Traumatic Shoulder Movement Disorders: A Challenging Differential Diagnosis Between Organic and Functional. Mov Disord Clin Pract. 2014;1(2):102–105. 10.1002/mdc3.12016 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59. Pruszewicz A, Obrebowski A, świdziński P, et al. : Usefulness of Acoustic Studies on the Differential Diagnostics of Organic and Functional Dysphonia. Acta Otolaryngol. 1991;111(2):414–419. 10.3109/00016489109137412 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 60. Richter JE: Dyspepsia: Organic Causes and Differential Characteristics from Functional Dyspepsia. Scand J Gastroenterol Suppl. 1991;182:11–6. 10.3109/00365529109109531 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61. Caramazza A: Is Cognitive Neuropsychology Possible? J Cogn Neurosci. 1992;4(1):80–95. 10.1162/jocn.1992.4.1.80 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 62. Churchland PS, Sejnowski TJ: Perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Science. 1988;242(4879):741–745. 10.1126/science.3055294 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 63. Halligan PW, David AS: Cognitive neuropsychiatry: towards a scientific psychopathology. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2001;2(3):209–215. 10.1038/35058586 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 64. Mesulam MM: Principles of behavioral and cognitive neurology. Oxford University Press.2000. Reference Source [Google Scholar]
  • 65. Shallice T: From neuropsychology to mental structure. Cambridge University Press.1988. 10.1017/CBO9780511526817 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 66. Loubinoux I, Kronenberg G, Endres M, et al. : Post-stroke depression: mechanisms, translation and therapy. J Cell Mol Med. 2012;16(9):1961–1969. 10.1111/j.1582-4934.2012.01555.x [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 67. Robinson RG, Jorge RE: Post-Stroke Depression: A Review. AJP. 2016;173(3):221–231. 10.1176/appi.ajp.2015.15030363 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 68. Werheid K: A Two-Phase Pathogenetic Model of Depression after Stroke. Gerontology. 2015;62(1):33–39. 10.1159/000381876 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 69. Whyte EM, Mulsant BH: Post stroke depression: epidemiology, pathophysiology, and biological treatment. Biol Psychiatry. 2002;52(3):253–264. 10.1016/S0006-3223(02)01424-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 70. Haag HL, Jones D, Joseph T, et al. : Battered and Brain Injured: Traumatic Brain Injury Among Women Survivors of Intimate Partner Violence—A Scoping Review. Trauma Violence Abuse. 2019; 1524838019850623. 10.1177/1524838019850623 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 71. Valera E, Kucyi A: Brain injury in women experiencing intimate partner-violence: neural mechanistic evidence of an “invisible” trauma. Brain Imaging Behav. 2017;11(6):1664–1677. 10.1007/s11682-016-9643-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 72. Romeu-Mejia R, Giza CC, Goldman JT: Concussion Pathophysiology and Injury Biomechanics. Curr Rev Musculoskelet Med. 2019;12(2):105–116. 10.1007/s12178-019-09536-8 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 73. Perry DC, Sturm VE, Peterson MJ, et al. : Association of traumatic brain injury with subsequent neurological and psychiatric disease: a meta-analysis. J Neurosurg. 2016;124(2):511–526. 10.3171/2015.2.JNS14503 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 74. Beydoun HA, Williams M, Beydoun MA, et al. : Relationship of Physical Intimate Partner Violence with Mental Health Diagnoses in the Nationwide Emergency Department Sample. J Womens Health (Larchmt). 2017;26(2):141–151. 10.1089/jwh.2016.5840 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 75. Stewart DE, Vigod SN: Update on Mental Health Aspects of Intimate Partner Violence. Med Clin North Am. 2019;103(4):735–749. 10.1016/j.mcna.2019.02.010 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 76. Asken BM: Concussion Biomarkers: Deviating From the Garden Path. JAMA Neurol. 2019;76(5):515–516. 10.1001/jamaneurol.2019.0125 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 77. Khandanpour N, Hoggard N, Connolly DJA: The role of MRI and CT of the brain in first episodes of psychosis. Clin Radiol. 2013;68(3):245–250. 10.1016/j.crad.2012.07.010 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 78. Strahl B, Cheung YK, Stuckey SL: Diagnostic yield of computed tomography of the brain in first episode psychosis. J Med Imaging Radiat Oncol. 2010;54(5):431–434. 10.1111/j.1754-9485.2010.02196.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 79. Goulet K, Deschamps B, Evoy F, et al. : Use of Brain Imaging (Computed Tomography and Magnetic Resonance Imaging) in First-Episode Psychosis: Review and Retrospective Study. Can J Psychiatry. 2009;54(7):493–501. 10.1177/070674370905400711 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 80. Firth J, Smith L, Sarris J, et al. : Handgrip strength is associated with hippocampal volume and white matter hyperintensities in major depression and healthy controls: a UK. Biobank study. Psychosom Med. 2019;82(1):39–46. 10.1097/PSY.0000000000000753 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 81. Grangeon MC, Seixas C, Quarantini LC, et al. : White matter hyperintensities and their association with suicidality in major affective disorders: a meta-analysis of magnetic resonance imaging studies. CNS Spectr. 2010;15(6):375–381. 10.1017/s1092852900029242 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 82. Kieseppä T, Mäntylä R, Tuulio-Henriksson A, et al. : White matter hyperintensities and cognitive performance in adult patients with bipolar I, bipolar II, and major depressive disorders. Eur Psychiatry. 2014;29(4):226–232. 10.1016/j.eurpsy.2013.08.002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 83. Wadhwa R, Wen W, Frankland A, et al. : White matter hyperintensities in young individuals with bipolar disorder or at high genetic risk. J Affect Disord. 2019;245:228–236. 10.1016/j.jad.2018.10.368 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 84. Moura AR, Lee S, Habeck C, et al. : The relationship between white matter hyperintensities and cognitive reference abilities across the life span. Neurobiol Aging. 2019;83:31–41. 10.1016/j.neurobiolaging.2019.08.024 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 85. Fricker M: Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press.2007. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198237907.001.0001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 86. Kidd IJ, Carel H: Epistemic Injustice and Illness. J Appl Philos. 2017;34(2):172–190. 10.1111/japp.12172 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 87. Holloway M, Orr D, Clark-Wilson J: Experiences of challenges and support among family members of people with acquired brain injury: a qualitative study in the UK. Brain Inj. 2019;33(4):401–411. 10.1080/02699052.2019.1566967 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 88. Tam S, McKay A, Sloan S, et al. : The experience of challenging behaviours following severe TBI: A family perspective. Brain Inj. 2015;29(7–8):813–821. 10.3109/02699052.2015.1005134 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 89. Huet M, Dany L, Apostolidis T: Explain the ‘unexplainable’: A qualitative enquiry of the representations of the caregivers of brain-injured people. J Health Psychol. 2018;23(8):1050–1062. 10.1177/1359105316642834 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 90. Miller BL, Cummings JL, McIntyre H, et al. : Hypersexuality or altered sexual preference following brain injury. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 1986;49(8):867–873. 10.1136/jnnp.49.8.867 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 91. Midorikawa A, Kawamura M: The emergence of artistic ability following traumatic brain injury. Neurocase. 2015;21(1):90–94. 10.1080/13554794.2013.873058 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 92. Pollak TA, Mulvenna CM, Lythgoe MF: De novo Artistic Behaviour following Brain Injury.Neurological Disorders in Famous Artists - Part 2. Front Neurol Neurosci. 2007;22:75–88. 10.1159/000102873 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 93. Katsakou C, Priebe S: Patient’s experiences of involuntary hospital admission and treatment: A review of qualitative studies. Epidemiol Psichiatr Soc. 2007;16(2):172–178. 10.1017/s1121189x00004802 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 94. Uhlhaas PJ, Mishara AL: Perceptual Anomalies in Schizophrenia: Integrating Phenomenology and Cognitive Neuroscience. Schizophr Bull. 2007;33(1):142–156. 10.1093/schbul/sbl047 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 95. Selby JV, Beal AC, Frank L: The Patient-Centered Outcomes Research Institute (PCORI) National Priorities for Research and Initial Research Agenda. JAMA. 2012;307(15):1583–1584. 10.1001/jama.2012.500 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
Wellcome Open Res. 2020 Jul 21. doi: 10.21956/wellcomeopenres.17576.r39089

Reviewer response for version 1

Ana Gómez-Carrillo 1

This incisive narrative review by Bell et al. provides an overview of the tensions – representatively captured in ongoing use of the organic/functional distinction — that likely divide(d) and continue to plague the fields of psychiatry and neurology.

The authors do an excellent job at reviewing a complex issue with a broad scope and bring imperative concerns to bear that research and practice must re-visit. In so doing it raises more questions than it answers. While serving to illustrate the complex scope of the distinction in practice the pragmatist approach falls short of considering deeper and earlier roots of the distinction further afield.

The review is timely in that it points out how clinical practice is stuck in paradigms that have not caught up with more contemporary theories in cognitive sciences central to psychiatry and neurology. Although hinted at in the abstract and in the section on implications (“the dynamic relationship between cognitive capacity, affect, perception, action and context”) the pragmatist approach taken leaves this divide between research and practice insufficiently addressed – as such this important discussion feels slightly stuck, seemingly engaging with older conceptions and less so with more contemporary ones. Perhaps this is simply a reflection of the slow uptake and resistance to change that characterizes clinical practice which is what the authors chose to focus on here.

By exposing the inconsistencies and contradictions of the uses of the f/o distinction the authors clearly question the usefulness and validity of this distinction and expose the dichotomies that it perpetuates. Beyond what the distinction is or is not doing – is the question of why it is still there (conceptually and causally)? There seems to be some value to this distinction, some functions or needs that it fulfills which apparently outweigh its conceptual (and pragmatic) incoherencies. In referring to Wilson’s quote on whether more contemporary understandings of the brain have perhaps left this distinction irrelevant the authors approach this issue but take it no further. A more explicit positioning or discussion on whether and, if so, how more contemporary theories may or may not be an alternative would strengthen the manuscript.

In what follows I share some suggestions that may help add clarity in structure and argumentation as well as reflections to further this discussion:

  • When reviewing historical shifts in the meaning of f/o, briefly linking the distinction to its conceptual origins would help untangle and frame some of the contradictions the authors eloquently exemplify. I was surprised to find no reference to the psychodynamic literature that largely shaped the use of “functional” as it relates to conversion disorders and variations thereof, including historical links to the polymorphous concept of hysteria. Aware that the literature on this is extensive and controversial as well as perhaps not central to this review – much of the uses of the ‘functional’ classifier across disciplines rely explicit or implicitly on psychodynamic theories. 

  • Also, briefly characterizing ‘dualism’ in a bit more detail and how it relates to the f/o distinction would serve to set the stage for the examples and analysis that follow e.g. substance dualism vs epistemic dualism or how the distinction relates to amoral naturalistic and moral super-naturalistic domains.

  • As the authors note, the use of this distinction varies significantly by context and although they provide a thorough overview of how the f/o distinction is used across contexts attempting to review its use in both psychiatry and neurology and research and practice at once poses a challenge. At times this comes at the cost of glossing over more necessary differentiations and risks producing an overview that is more complex than the use of this distinction already is. A clearer picture may emerge if a more systematic approach based on when, where and by whom the distinction is being applied structured the examples provided.

  • For example, psychosis is noted to be typically considered functional – from whose perspective? Interestingly, while from a neurologist perspective the f/o distinction may draw the boundaries of neurology and psychiatry, artificially or not, mainstream psychiatry currently continues to prioritize organic etiological understandings for its ‘classic’ diagnoses despite lacking the necessary evidence for now.

  • Indeed, the organic-functional distinction is intimately related to and perhaps even sustained by issues that underlie the stigma of mental disorders. But does the stigmatization stem from this distinction– or does this distinction merely reinforce it? Stigma and the f/o distinction share origins and possibly persist in one form or another globally because of an implicit ontology that emerges from a residual form of mind-body dualism . If so is it a matter of ridding ourselves from this distinction?

  • Regarding the inconsistent use of the f/o distinction, differentiating between the use of this terminology formally and its use as part of medical jargon across medical specialties (beyond its use for ‘turfing’) would lead to a clearer picture in the discussion and the examples provided. The authors seem to allude to this in saying that clinicians use the distinction strategically. But even the use of this distinction in medical jargon varies significantly across specialties, their agenda’s and who is being communicated with – so while generalizing allows to make the point, it may fail to capture the nuance needed to advance this analysis. Functional is used in some contexts as a pseudo-euphemism for psychosomatic (as if to avoid stigma related reactions), others use the terms interchangeably and some make a distinction. The authors may consider thinking one of the examples of the f/o distinction in detail through to the end including the multiple explanatory models and tensions it captures as well as the specific clinical niche and cultural practice it originates in. This would expose the potential imperatives that lead to the use of this distinction as well as the pitfalls. In the example of delirium, despite its multifactorial etiology, it is a clinical imperative for clinicians to consider delirium a consequence of an underlying medical disorder or physiological imbalance – why is this so? What would be the consequences of not making the distinction here? The example serves to convey the complexity of this distinction however a straightforward pragmatic clinical predicament underlies the issue here. The examples provided in the manuscript are very good and I am not suggesting others should necessarily be added.

  • While in some cases the uses of the f/o distinction in multifactorial pathologies relate more to clinical management of ambiguity and uncertainty e.g. delirium requiring a binary clinical decision tree, other uses are better explained by the forms of ambiguity and uncertainty that underlie cultural ascriptions and understandings of agency, moral and responsibility e.g. organic personality change. It is always some degree of both. The authors rightly highlight how the terminology fails to cover the pragmatic and philosophical function of this use but no alternative is discussed. The extent to which the tensions uncovered are bound to management of ambiguity and uncertainty in both clinical practice and a person’s illness experiences remains to be discussed and the insights of people who experience the interaction between function and organic will be of great value here. Ambiguity lends itself to be exploited to project one’s own intentions, motivations, understandings, models and needs. The ambiguity will likely remain and be shaped by individuals’ needs and perspectives again and again. Overcoming these tensions will require better training in and integration of complex thinking on one level, and alternate ways to reduce complexity to the binary choices that permit action on another. This is easier in theory and discourse but harder when faced with the pragmatic reality of life, clinical decision making, insurance claims or court rooms…

This is a worthy discussion with impact for people who experience the interaction between function and organic and clinicians alike. The points above may help look beyond the conundrum of this distinction to see if the issues that are linked to it are deeper rooted and prone to prevail until a more widespread social paradigm change is achieved, independently of changes to nomenclature or advances in theoretical understandings. Can the f/o distinction be viewed as other than two complementary aspects of illness and disease in line with Bohr’s notion of complementarity? The contribution of people who experience the interaction between function and organic will be central here – more than to clarify its use or validity, to unpack the origin of the problems this distinction has tried to solve and help advance better alternatives. I look forward to more work on this topic by the group and to the conclusions they may reach.

Is the review written in accessible language?

Yes

Are all factual statements correct and adequately supported by citations?

Yes

Are the conclusions drawn appropriate in the context of the current research literature?

Yes

Is the topic of the review discussed comprehensively in the context of the current literature?

Partly

Reviewer Expertise:

transcultural psychiatry, philosophy and psychiatry, mood disorders

I confirm that I have read this submission and believe that I have an appropriate level of expertise to confirm that it is of an acceptable scientific standard.

Wellcome Open Res. 2020 Jul 6. doi: 10.21956/wellcomeopenres.17576.r39086

Reviewer response for version 1

Jesús Ramirez-Bermudez 1,2

This is a necessary scientific essay dealing with the conceptual duality between “the organic” and “the functional” as analitic categories in clinical practice. Opening review and the definitions provided by the authors are useful and I would not recommend further bibliography regarding this part. Also, the critique is well developed, although I think the authors should discuss the alternatives to this conceptual duality in clinical practice. A few notes:

  1. The paragraphs dedicated to Historical shifts in the meaning of ‘functional’ and ‘organic’ are fine and I have no further comments.

  2. Regarding the paragraphs dedicated to Inconsistencies in the conceptual scope of the functional-organic distinction and Varying relationship to diagnostic practices that establish causality: I agree with the authors’ discussion, although some other clinical problems merit consideration:
    1. First, the case of migraine and other disorders which are considered “neurological” and are attended by neurologists, although the clinical diagnosis is not based in biological markers; the scientific epistemology and the clinical approach to patients with migraine is similar to the epistemology/approach which is used in psychiatric patients (a diagnosis based in symptoms by means of clinical interviews, etc). However, this clinical problems are not grouped traditionally with the “functional” disorders nor are dismissed as “psychological”.
    2. Second: Parkinson’s Disease, among other neurological diagnoses, is interesting also for the discussion, because in clinical practice, rarely the diagnosis is based in technological procedures. Some difficult cases may be solved with support of PET, but the significant majority of cases are diagnosed by means of the identification of a clinical phenotype which is captured by means of the highly trained visual and tactile abilities of the clinician, and some times with support of clinical scales and pharmacologic trials (UPDRS, l-dopa test). Although the neuropathology of Parkinson’s Disease is well stablished, the recognition of the disease in clinical practice is based in most cases purely by clinical skills, and other resources (brain imaging, etc) are used to rule out other etiologies which may produce similar phenotypes. Certainly, Parkinson’s Disease is considered organic. Clinicians may use similar approaches in field of dementias, although in this case the technological devices have a more prominent role. In our center, MRI and PET scans are quite relevant in the diagnosis of Alzheimer’s Disease, Frontotemporal Dementia and so on, but those diagnosis are also made with less emphasis in technology in different settings, and the logic of this issue is the same: the recognition of the clinical phenotype is enough to classify the patient as having an “organic” disorder. The authors pose a similar problem regarding the “delirium” diagnosis.
    3. I include this discussion related to migraine, Parkinson’s Disease and the Dementias as it serves me to pose some general questions, although I don’t think these diagnoses should be necessarily included in the manuscript.
  3. The paragraphs related to Inconsistent use and interpretation in clinical practice and Cultural perceptions and political uses are fine from my perspective.

  4. Regarding the Implications section, I only have two comments:
    1. I totally agree with the paragraphs related to Social power in definition and application, but it is not clear to me how this is particularly relevant to the discussion between “Organic vs Functional”. Or is it a general issue related to psychiatric stigma?
    2. I totally agree that the utility and the scientific value of the “Organic vs Functional” distinction is limited, to say the least. However, I wonder if the authors can discuss more the alternatives. In the Perminder Sachdev paper, some of the alternative terms and views are discussed, including concepts as “primary” “secondary” “symptomatic” “idiopathic”. This terminologies, along with their conceptual implications, are relevant from my point of view to the discussion. Although I understand that the authors are not arguing simply for a change in terminologies and go on to discuss the validity of the dichotomic perspectives, it would be of great value if they can advance at some degree their alternative proposals. Perhaps this could be related to the following paragraph: “No research has ever been conducted with, for example, survivors of brain injury that aims to inform the science of how neurological-level and personal-level processes interact.” The Sachdev paper discusses practical approaches beyond terminology that go to the attribution of causality.
    3. Perhaps a general discussion of what clinical-epidemiological sciences tell us of the attribution of causality in groups of patients is important, as a background reflection. Myself, I find a great approach in the Elwood’s textbook: Critical Appraisal of Epidemiological Studies and Clinical Trials. However, a different question is how clinicians establish causality at the individual level? This question is quite relevant along the neurological-psychiatric spectrum of problems and is probably overlooked in the scientific & philosophic literature.

Is the review written in accessible language?

Yes

Are all factual statements correct and adequately supported by citations?

Yes

Are the conclusions drawn appropriate in the context of the current research literature?

Yes

Is the topic of the review discussed comprehensively in the context of the current literature?

Yes

Reviewer Expertise:

Clinical neuropsychiatry

I confirm that I have read this submission and believe that I have an appropriate level of expertise to confirm that it is of an acceptable scientific standard.

Wellcome Open Res. 2020 Jun 25. doi: 10.21956/wellcomeopenres.17576.r39090

Reviewer response for version 1

Norman A Poole 1

Bell et al's paper is a useful and thoughtful reappraisal of the widely used but under examined functional vs organic distinction in neurology and psychiatry. In particular, it draws attention to the incoherence of the distinction, which differs in content across its various applications and they illustrate the point with well observed examples such as differentiating between organic and functional tics. 

Given the longstanding conceptual incoherence of the distinction - they approve Wilson's skewering of it in his 1940's textbook - why then does it endure in clinical practice and research? The evidence they cite addressing this is limited but telling. Neurologists are prone to equate functional with feigned or demarcating a psychological terrain not to be explored while psychiatrists employ organic when they fear their patient's symptoms will be ignored by medical colleagues. This functional - that word again! - analysis  seems to me to approach the nub of the issue and overlaps with but is not quite the same as the question of aetiology.

It is probably a reification of the dichotomy to believe that it does any real work differentiating biomedical from psychosocial causality and the biopsychosocial model can be applied to most conditions doctors treat. In clinical practice the terms are largely used where there is a dispute about which specialism should take the lead in the patient's care. What is being communicated when neurologists say 'functional' and psychiatrists invoke 'organic' is really one saying to the other, 'Over to you.' This can be read as a base  abdication of clinical responsibility or an act of deference to the appropriate specialism, and in truth is probably a bit of both.

It has become a truism that organic conditions and their attendants are somehow superior in the hierarchy of disease and this narrative review falls prey to the same assumption. The organic/functional dichotomy maps neatly on to folk theorising about mental disorder; lay people quite naturally understand mental symptoms to be biologically or psychologically caused with the one negating the other 1. However, the assumptions that flow from this turn out to be unreliable. Biological explanations are in fact more stigmatising and fatalistic than those that utilise psychological concepts 2.

This tendency to dichotomise ought to be challenged though, as it does not conform to current scientific knowledge while fostering therapeutic nihilism, and this paper marks a significant attempt to do just that. It accords moves elsewhere in the literature. After facing some sustained criticism the concerns about vagueness 3 and incompatible levels 4 within the biopsychosocial model of disease are being addressed. Doctors must recognise and communicate aetiological complexity to protect themselves and their patients from falling into simplistic, but seemingly inherent, patterns of thought.

Yet I was left slightly confused as to whether the authors are rejecting the distinction outright, or not. And if so what would it be replaced with? I am in full agreement that it fails to carve nature at her joints aetiologically, but perhaps less convinced that this is its real purpose. The clinical use of 'functional' exposes biomedicine's abhorrence of the 'other' while 'organic' is psychiatry's codeword for medics to take the patient seriously. Sadly, it will take more than a new set of terms for that to change.

Is the review written in accessible language?

Yes

Are all factual statements correct and adequately supported by citations?

Yes

Are the conclusions drawn appropriate in the context of the current research literature?

Yes

Is the topic of the review discussed comprehensively in the context of the current literature?

Yes

Reviewer Expertise:

Neuropsychiatry, Philosophy and psychiatry, Psychopathology

I confirm that I have read this submission and believe that I have an appropriate level of expertise to confirm that it is of an acceptable scientific standard.

References

  • 1. : Psychiatric categories as natural kinds: Essentialist thinking about mental disorder. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/286866478_Psychiatric_categories_as_natural_kinds_Essentialist_thinking_about_mental_disorder.2000;
  • 2. Natural Kinds in Psychiatry: Conceptually Implausible, Empirically Questionable, and Stigmatizing.2014; 10.7551/mitpress/8942.003.0003 10.7551/mitpress/8942.003.0003 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 3. : The Biopsychosocial Model of Health and Disease New Philosophical and Scientific Developments. Palgrave Macmillan.2019; [PubMed]
  • 4. : Levels of analysis in psychopathology: cross-disciplinary perspectives. Cambridge University Press.2020;

Associated Data

    This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

    Data Availability Statement

    Underlying data

    No data are associated with this article.


    Articles from Wellcome Open Research are provided here courtesy of The Wellcome Trust

    RESOURCES