Skip to main content
Sage Choice logoLink to Sage Choice
. 2020 Jun 9;29(5):473–491. doi: 10.1177/0963662520924259

Science-related populism: Conceptualizing populist demands toward science

Niels G Mede 1,, Mike S Schäfer 1
PMCID: PMC7411529  PMID: 32515652

Abstract

Populism is on the rise in many countries. Scholars have stated that it is characteristic for political populism to describe society as a fundamental struggle between an allegedly virtuous people and political elites which are portrayed negatively. This anti-elitist sentiment not only targets politicians, however, but also other representatives of the alleged establishment—including scientists and scholarly institutions. But the specifics of such science-related populism have not yet been conceptualized. We aim to do so, integrating scholarship on political populism, the “participatory turn,” and alternative epistemologies. We propose to conceptualize science-related populism as a set of ideas which suggests that there is a morally charged antagonism between an (allegedly) virtuous ordinary people and an (allegedly) unvirtuous academic elite, and that this antagonism is due to the elite illegitimately claiming and the people legitimately demanding both science-related decision-making sovereignty and truth-speaking sovereignty.

Keywords: attitudes toward science, epistemology, populism, science, theory

1. Introduction

Populist movements have emerged around the globe. Populist politicians and parties, claiming to promote the will of an allegedly virtuous people and challenging established political elites and structures (Rooduijn, 2019), have positioned themselves prominently on issues like immigration and climate change (Berbuir et al., 2015; Hultman et al., 2019) and gained considerable voter support (Lewis et al., 2018). This led some scholars to diagnose an “age of populism” (Smith, 2018).

But populists do not only target political elites. They also criticize other institutions they see as representing the societal establishment (Wirth et al., 2016), such as mainstream media, legal elites, big business—and academics, scholars, and experts (Forchtner et al., 2018). Former UK Secretary of State for Justice Michael Gove, for example, famously claimed that the British people “have had enough of experts […] from organizations with acronyms saying that they know what is best” (Simons, 2016). Mexican President Andrés López Obrador contended that corrupt “mafia” scientists would waste government funds for conference travel (Wade, 2019), and in 2020, US president Donald Trump suggested his “gut instinct” superseded scientific evidence on how to contain the COVID-19 pandemic (Crowley et al., 2020). Journalists (Yiannopoulos, 2015), celebrities (e.g. Gwyneth Paltrow; Caulfield, 2020), or businessmen (e.g. Peter Thiel; Schwab, 2018) have endorsed similar anti-scientific positions.

Opinion polls (Motta, 2018), experiments (Myrick and Comfort, 2020), qualitative interviews (Sarathchandra and Haltinner, 2020), and discourse analyses (Poberezhskaya, 2018) show that segments of the broader public also criticize scientific research, both on controversial topics like climate change (Ylä-Anttila, 2018) or vaccination (Davis, 2019) and on less politicized topics like nutrition or physical therapy (Harambam and Aupers, 2015). Not all of these criticisms follow the populist logic of portraying the people and the elite as antagonists—but some of them do, accusing climate scientists, for example, of being “part of the ‘elite groups’ who fool people” (Poberezhskaya, 2018: 947), describing climate research as “mob science” that conceals the “truth” (Sarathchandra and Haltinner, 2020: 56) or suggesting that “experts ought to be less trusted than ordinary people” (Motta, 2018: 483). Further scholarship indicates that such anti-scientific positions can be associated with political populism. Merkley (2020), for example, discovered a strong relationship between populist sentiment and mistrust toward intellectuals and experts. Both Saarinen et al. (2020) and Filc and Lebel (2005) showed that populist party supporters tend to have lower trust in universities. And Oliver and Rahn (2016: 198) revealed that many voters of populist US candidates rather “trust in the wisdom of ordinary people than the opinions of experts and intellectuals.”

Such findings illustrate that “it is more relevant than ever to study the linkage between populism and the production and communication of knowledge” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018: 357), and to assess empirically and conceptually whether the abovementioned anti-scientific positions are indicative of recent essayistic diagnoses of “a new anti-knowledge, anti-science era” (Livni, 2016) or a “post-truth world” (Williamson, 2019) in which “expertise is suspect and truth is relative” (Glaubke, 2018). However, scholarship on this linkage has empirical gaps and conceptual shortcomings. Empirically, it has only analyzed specific aspects: scholars have investigated conspiracy theorists (Harambam, 2017) or supporters of far-right ideologies (Hultman et al., 2019) and published case studies of right-wing online platforms (Ylä-Anttila, 2018) or conservative radio shows (Saurette and Gunster, 2011), but were often not, or not primarily, concerned with populism related to science (e.g. Harsin, 2018). Conceptually, scholarship on “populism and the production and communication of knowledge” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018: 357) has remained somewhat disconnected until now: scholars have employed different frameworks and did not scrutinize whether a specific phenomenon with parallels (but also crucial differences) to political populism has emerged—a phenomenon we propose to call science-related populism.

Science-related populism, as we understand it, is not intended as an umbrella term for all forms of critique directed against science. There are many variants of criticizing science, some of which are not science-related populism—for example, concerns about the ethical, legal, and social implications of biotechnology (MacDonald et al., 2020), “counterresearch” commissioned by corporations aiming to contradict scientific findings about smoking or global warming (Oreskes and Conway, 2010) or religiously motivated objections to certain scientific fields (McPhetres and Zuckerman, 2018)—whereas other variants are, and with this article, we aim to offer a conceptual framework for them. We, therefore, propose an analytical model of science-related populism that identifies its key elements and their mutual relations, and can be the foundation for empirical analyses of its prevalence, preconditions, and impacts.

2. Political populism, the “participatory turn,” and alternative epistemologies: Reviewing relevant scholarship

Our conceptualization of science-related populism rests on three strands of scholarship. From each strand, we borrow core ideas which serve as building blocks for our conceptualization. First, we rely on scholarship on political populism, because it provides an understanding of the fundamental populist logic, its core protagonists and principles (see section “Scholarship on political populism”). Second, we draw on scholarship on the “participatory turn,” because it shows that demands for public participation—one of the key principles of political populism—have emerged beyond politics, and that such participatory demands follow different core logics in different societal fields (see section “Scholarly diagnoses of a ‘participatory turn’”). Third, we rely on scholarship that has focused on the core logic of science, its epistemology, demonstrating that the epistemic authority of science has been increasingly challenged while alternative epistemologies have gained importance (see section “Scholarship on alternative epistemologies”).

Scholarship on political populism

Scholars of political populism have had difficulty agreeing on a definition that captures populist phenomena in different cultural and historical contexts (Rooduijn, 2019). Substantial discrepancies concerned the genus of populism (Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, 2018: 1669). Some scholars saw it as a political style (Jagers and Walgrave, 2007), others as a discourse (Hawkins, 2010) or ideology (Mudde, 2004). Currently, many scholars agree that populism is a set of ideas describing society as a morally charged conflict over political decision-making sovereignty between an allegedly virtuous people and an allegedly corrupt elite (Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, 2018: 1669; Rooduijn, 2019: 363–364). This “ideational approach” is related to the notion that populism can be conceived as a thin-centered ideology which entails a core of normative ideas about how society should be structured, but is “thin” as these ideas (unlike “thick” ideologies) have limited “intellectual refinement” (Mudde, 2017: 30), do not “transcend the proximate context in which they emerge” (Stanley, 2008: 106), and are “moralistic rather than programmatic” (Mudde, 2004: 544).1

Our conceptualization of science-related populism follows this ideational approach, not only because it is well accepted in research on political populism,2 but also for other reasons: First, it is able to grasp the “supply” and “demand” sides of populism (Hawkins and Rovira Kaltwasser, 2017), that is, arguments and positions used by populist leaders as well as attitudes held by their followers. Second, it has already been operationalized for both quantitative and qualitative empirical work (Mudde, 2017: 39), which is instructive since only few and mostly qualitative analyses of science-related populism and similar phenomena exist (e.g. Ylä-Anttila, 2018). Third, it can be used to scrutinize possible combinations of populism and “thick” ideologies (Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, 2018: 1670). Fourth, and importantly, it is an analytically clear approach with a fixed set of sub-concepts that are well-suited for further conceptual work (Mudde, 2017: 34–36). These sub-concepts, which we will adapt later for our purposes, are the people, the elite, and sovereignty.

Core protagonists: “The people” versus “the elite”

Scholars agree that the concept of “the people” is key to (political) populism (Wirth et al., 2016: 9). Importantly, the term usually does not denote a concrete physical group of individuals. “The people” rather functions as an “empty signifier” that is strategically used by populist leaders and followers to refer to an alleged popular majority supporting their cause (Reinemann et al., 2017: 16). Implicitly or explicitly, populism describes the people as a homogeneous entity of citizens who are considered to act virtuously thanks to their impeccable character (Taggart, 2000). Homogeneity can be defined in different ways, for example, politically (“those deprived of power”), economically (“those with few financial resources”), or culturally (“those who belong to the national community”; Wirth et al., 2016). Due to their alleged homogeneity, the people are seen as having a unified voice and a common will—a volonté générale (Mudde, 2004). And due to their purported moral superiority, this will is considered to be the legitimate foundation for political and societal decisions (Hawkins, 2010).

Taggart (2000: 95–98) adds that populists often commit themselves to a once-existent ideal state of society in which politics and societal life had been pervaded by orderliness, dutifulness, and predictability. He refers to this state as “the heartland” and conceptualizes the people as its inhabitants. Whenever populists refer to “the people,” he suggests, they essentially call for the (re)establishment of the heartland.

In contrast, “the elite” is seen as the villainous antagonist of the people (Mudde, 2017). Sociologists describe elites as societal minorities wielding political, economic, social, or intellectual power and influencing individual citizens (Bottomore, 1964). Generally, this description includes political, economic, legal, cultural, and intellectual elites (Hartmann, 2004). This pluralism renders the term “the elite” as vague as the term “the people” (Moffitt and Tormey, 2014: 395). But this very vagueness also makes it possible to conceive elites as a cohesive, monolithic entity detached from the people but ultimately deciding over their future (Mills, 1956).

Populists suggest that the power of elites over the people is unjust, because elites are allegedly morally inferior to the people. They are portrayed as being “corrupt” (Rooduijn, 2014: 588), “conspiring” (Hawkins, 2010: 5), and “unwilling or unable to address the demands of the people” (Panizza and Miorelli, 2009: 42). In Taggart’s (2000) terms, elites are portrayed as invaders of the heartland, keeping the people from reaching it.

Core principle: Sovereignty

Populism describes the people and the elite as moral antagonists, perceiving the people as virtuous and the elite as “evil” (Mudde, 2004: 544). These contrasting attributions are due to a conflict over political sovereignty, which is why sovereignty has been described as populism’s “core principle” (Wirth et al., 2016: 8).

Sovereignty is generally conceived as supreme authority in politics and collective decision-making (Williams, 1996). Authority itself is described as the “right to command, and correlatively, the right to be obeyed” (Wolff, 1998: 4). In democracies, this right is ascribed to representatives nominated by citizens to assert authority on their behalf (Lefort, 1988). But populism rejects the idea of democratic representation (Mény and Surel, 2002). It posits that politics should be an unmediated expression of the popular will, and that representation not only impedes this expression but also constitutes an illegitimate claim to sovereignty itself (Abts and Rummens, 2007). Political elites, who enact this representation, are therefore seen as illegitimate sovereigns (Wirth et al., 2016). Populism further suggests that, to enable politics to embody the popular will, the people themselves must have, or reclaim, authority as they are the only legitimate sovereigns (Abts and Rummens, 2007).

The fundamental structure of populism described by scholars of political populism is instructive for us as it has similarities to science-related populism. But as we will see, science-related populism also has distinct qualities deviating from political populism. Let us turn to our second conceptual building block: scholarship of a “participatory turn”.

Scholarly diagnoses of a “participatory turn”

From the 1960s onwards, social scientists have described a decline in traditional forms of citizen or lay participation such as elections (Kostelka, 2017). In turn, however, non-traditional forms of participation have been increasingly demanded in many realms of society, a development labeled “participatory turn” (Bherer et al., 2016), “participatory revolution” (Blühdorn, 2014), or “rebellion of the citizens” (Gerhards, 2001). This development has been connected, first, to fundamental changes in social structures. Scholars argued that because social strata had less influence on individual behavior, people were less bound to predetermined social positions, adopted individualized lifestyles, and gained more freedom to participate in various realms of society (Armingeon, 2007). Second, people have been further enabled to do so by the increasing reach and improved quality of education (Meyer et al., 1977), visible in the widening of tertiary education or higher education reforms (World Bank, 2002). Third, scholars described the “participatory turn” as connected to an increased emphasis on democratic ideals and to the perception that societies do not live up to these ideals. Participatory demands were interpreted as “a strong critique of liberal and representative democracy” (Bherer et al., 2016: 225) going along with “[d]istrust in established elites, dissatisfaction with existing political institutions, and growing confidence in the capabilities of the increasingly educated citizenry” (Blühdorn, 2014: 407), all of which fueled “a general shift of preference from representative democracy to more direct forms of participation” (Blühdorn, 2014: 407) and a “radicalization of democratic practices” (Bherer et al., 2016: 225).

Two aspects of this literature are noteworthy here. On the one hand, it shows that popular demands for participation—which are also inherent in political populism—have emerged in fields beyond politics. Even though they are pronounced in the political realm (Saurugger, 2010), “participatory discourses and techniques have been at the core of decision-making processes in a variety of sectors of society” (Bherer et al., 2016: 225), from social movements (Della Porta and Rucht, 2013) over companies and trade unions (Lee, 2014) to bureaucratic organizations (Nabatchi, 2010) and art (Bishop, 2012). A rise of participatory demands has also been described for science (Gregory and Miller, 1998), including the implementation of citizen participation in science-related decision-making (Einsiedel and Eastlick, 2000), public control of scientific work (Fähnrich et al., 2015; Ford, 2013), the crowd funding of science (Schäfer et al., 2018b), or citizen science (Füchslin et al., 2019).

On the other hand, scholarship on the “participatory turn” demonstrates that participatory demands take different forms in different realms of society. Gerhards (2001) interprets these differences using general systems theory: He argues that different core logics prevail in different societal “systems” and that participatory demands follow these core logics. Accordingly, participation in politics—whose core logic is the production of collectively binding decisions—aims for (more) decision-making power for citizens, participation in art aims for the inclusion of citizens in the creation and evaluation of aesthetic products, and participation in economics aims for the articulation of consumer needs (Gerhards, 2001).

The core logic of science, in contrast, is the cumulative production of “true” knowledge (Baraldi et al., 1997: 211). This logic has also been addressed by participatory demands. We will illustrate this in the following by referring to a third strand of scholarship, focusing on alternative epistemologies.

Scholarship on alternative epistemologies

Scholarly literature on public participation in science has focused mostly on formats that are considered productive and instrumental for science, such as consensus conferences or citizen science (e.g. Einsiedel, 2008). Given that the phenomena we aim to conceptualize as science-related populism challenge organized science, however, another strand of scholarship is relevant for us. It analyzes the emergence and characteristics of alternative epistemologies that question the way in which science produces knowledge, its methods, and ultimately, its authority to make science-related decisions and claims about “true” knowledge.

A first wave of alternative epistemologies emerged in the second half of the twentieth century, driven by social movements around issues like environmentalism, international conflict, or globalization (van Zoonen, 2012). Recent developments—scholars mention the rise of political populism, societal value change toward “civic narcissism” (Papacharissi, 2009), the emergence of social media (Waisbord, 2018), and the increased “heterodoxy” (e.g. Schetsche and Schmied-Knittel, 2018) or “decentralization” (Gosa, 2011: 188) of knowledge in society as driving forces—have led to a second wave of alternative epistemologies. They have been labeled, for example, “post-truth” (e.g. Waisbord, 2018), “emo-truth” (Harsin, 2018), “populist epistemology” (Saurette and Gunster, 2011), “populist knowledge” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018), or “I-Pistemology” (van Zoonen, 2012). Many of these epistemologies offer alternatives to the scientific epistemology and criticize organized science. As such, they partly or fully address our understanding of science-related populism.

Scholarship on alternative epistemologies describes challenges to science and academic elites in two major ways. First, it has documented denials of the disinterestedness and objectivity of organized science and attempts to replace established knowledge with seemingly better (but still scientific) “counterknowledge.” Such challenges to organized science were analyzed in studies of populist online discourse (Ylä-Anttila, 2018) and conspiracy culture (Harambam, 2017; Harambam and Aupers, 2015), for example. Ylä-Anttila (2018), investigating immigration debates in two Finnish right-wing online media, shows how authors and users of these media generally subscribe to the scientific epistemology as an appropriate way to determine what is true—but believe that “the multiculturalist-relativist hegemony and the corrupt research community” (p. 369), for ideological reasons or because of personal vices, do not apply this epistemology correctly and thus suppress the actual “truth.” Ylä-Anttila (2018: 378) observes that supporters of this view “advocate a type of counterknowledge,” that is, a knowledge complying with the general epistemology of science but produced by “alternative knowledge authorities” which are not affected by the alleged corruption of “mainstream” science. Similarly, conspiracy theorists have been shown to adopt at least parts of the scientific epistemology in an attempt to describe epistemic authorities as part of a conspiring “regime of truth” (Harambam and Aupers, 2015: 467). In their view, the ability to truly “connect the dots” does not lie with organized science but, for example, with charismatic “conspiracy celebrities” (Harambam, 2017: 107–140). It is notable that the right-wing populists and conspiracy theorists analyzed in these studies do not challenge the scientific epistemology per se—in fact, they are described as “pro-science” (Harambam and Aupers, 2015: 471)—but that they see organized science as corrupt and want to replace it with alternative authorities and counterknowledge.

A second challenge to science and academic elites is more fundamental, rejecting the scientific epistemology as such and attempting to replace it with peoples’ common sense, their personal experiences, and emotional sentiments. This has been observed by Saurette and Gunster (2011), among others. In an analysis of a Canadian radio talk show, they describe an “epistemological populism” which

is established through a variety of rhetorical techniques and assumptions: the assertion that individual opinions based upon firsthand experience are much more reliable as a form of knowledge than those generated by theories and academic studies; the valorization of specific types of experience as particularly reliable sources of legitimate knowledge and the extension of this knowledge authority to unrelated issues; the privileging of emotional intensity as an indicator of the reliability of opinions; the use of populist-inflected discourse to dismiss other types of knowledge as elitist and therefore illegitimate; and finally, the appeal to “common sense” as a discussion-ending trump card. (Saurette and Gunster, 2011: 199)

Harsin, analyzing the rhetorical strategies of a right-wing political movement in France, focuses specifically on the “privileging of emotional intensity.” He finds that the movement promotes an “emo-truth […] where emotion serves as inference (prime or indexical sign, emotional or unconscious affective response, and presto: truth). It is felt (though not necessarily consciously), and not accompanied by long temporal reasoning” (Harsin, 2018: 45). While Harsin sees this emotional focus as an elaborate political strategy, van Zoonen (2012) has argued that individualized epistemologies—which she calls “I-Pistemologies”—have gained importance. She diagnoses a

contemporary cultural process in which people from all walks of life have come to suspect the knowledge coming from official institutions and experts, and have replaced it with the truth coming from their own individual experience and opinions. […] Where epistemology is concerned with the nature, sources and methods [of] knowledge, then I-pistemology answers these questions from the basis of I (as in me, myself). (van Zoonen, 2012: 56–60)

Both of these strands of scholarship offer comprehensive theoretical and empirical analyses of anti-elitist sentiments and challenges to science and epistemic authorities. As such, they address some of the core elements of science-related populism. Particularly, scholarship concerned with “epistemological populism,” “emo-truth,” and “I-Pistemology” is instructive for us as it describes phenomena that are well compatible with the populist narrative. They contain “the populist celebration of ‘the people’ and common sense” and also address “the other side of the populist trope—the attack on the elites—to dismiss contending forms of knowledge and of political opinions. The laudable voices of the people are contrasted with the ‘elitist’ views of academics” (Saurette and Gunster, 2011: 203).

So far, however, none of these strands or scholars has developed a broader conceptual framework aiming to grasp science-related populism. Some have focused on other, albeit related, concepts (Harambam, 2017; Harambam and Aupers, 2015; Ylä-Anttila, 2018). Some have focused on empirical work, and their conceptual ideas remained sketches embedded in case studies of Canadian talk radio (Saurette and Gunster, 2011) or French right-wing movements (Harsin, 2018). Others have focused not (Harsin, 2018) or not primarily (Gosa, 2011; Saurette and Gunster, 2011) on populist challenges to the scientific epistemology but on challenges to other elite epistemologies. Therefore, we feel that our conceptualization of science-related populism is worthwhile, and that it can build on the conceptual ideas of these works and usefully integrate them.

3. Conceptualizing science-related populism

Scholarship on political populism, the “participatory turn,” and alternative epistemologies provides the necessary building blocks for our concept of science-related populism. This concept adopts the fundamental structure of populism, its core protagonists, and their fundamentally antagonistic relations from scholarship on political populism. From scholarship on the “participatory turn,” it borrows the insight that participatory demands exist beyond politics and address the core logics of the fields in which they emerge. And from scholarship on alternative epistemologies, it adopts a detailed picture of how such demands may challenge science’s core logic, that is, its epistemology.

Core protagonists: “The ordinary people” versus “the academic elite”

The concept of science-related populism adopts the antagonistic core actors of political populism (“the people” and “the elite”), albeit with modifications. As science-related populism operates within the realm of scientific knowledge production, “the people” and “the elite” have to be understood in epistemological rather than in political, economic, or cultural terms. Consequently, it sees “the people” as being homogeneous not only in their values, but also in their common epistemological sense. We refer to this first protagonist in science-related populism as “the ordinary people.” Correspondingly, “the elite” denotes actors with epistemic authority. We refer to this second protagonist as “the academic elite.”

The ordinary people

Science-related populism refers to “the people” as a homogeneous collective of allegedly virtuous, lay, “ordinary” people. But unlike political populism (Wirth et al., 2016: 10), it conceives the people mainly with regard to their alleged epistemological ordinariness, homogeneity, and virtuousness. Accordingly, science-related populism derives the ordinariness of the people from their supposed reliance on common sense, everyday experience, or even gut feeling (Saurette and Gunster, 2011; Taggart, 2000). It further suggests that common sense, by reflecting truisms and anecdotes that are seemingly shared among ordinary people, functions as a common denominator of these people, and as such, reinforces their homogeneity. The ordinary people’s alleged homogeneity may eventually emerge from seemingly shared values, interests, and emotions that inform commonsensical epistemologies (Harsin, 2018; van Zoonen, 2012). Importantly, science-related populism attributes virtuousness to common sense and therefore to the people themselves. It suggests that commonsensical reasoning is the most—or even only—legitimate mode of thinking because it rests on authentic everyday experience (Saurette and Gunster, 2011).

Similar to scholars of political populism, the ordinary people can be conceptualized as inhabitants of a “science-related heartland”—an ideal world in which science does not disrupt people’s orderly lives with seemingly unnatural innovations (like gene-editing) and apocalyptic scenarios (like climate science), or by imposing decisions about issues like health, nutrition, vaccination, or mobility on them (see Taggart, 2000). Reference to the ordinary people and commitment to their common sense then essentially become an invocation of that heartland and an attack on a complex and ostensibly paternalistic science: “the heartland represents […] common sense against the knowledge elites” (Priester, 2011: 196).

The academic elite

While other forms of populism are concerned with political or other elites (Jagers and Walgrave, 2007: 324), science-related populism focuses on scientific elites, portraying them as antagonists of the ordinary people. These “academic elites,” as we term them, are a subset of a general elite—those who have supreme epistemic authority and can make science-related decisions, that is, organizations such as universities or research institutes as well as individual scholars and scientific experts (Hartmann, 2004: 3). Similar to other forms of populism, however, science-related populism also describes academic elites as morally inferior.

Even if academic elites can be affiliated with a broad range of institutions and research fields, and are thus quite fragmented, science-related populism describes them as relatively coherent because they collectively decide about science and research (i.e. agendas, methods, publications, etc.) and produce allegedly “true” knowledge. In the populist view, however, the “truths” determined by academic elites are “elusive, ephemeral, divided, [and] contested” (Waisbord, 2018: 20). They are seen as fundamentally detached from the everyday life of ordinary people—and so are scientists, scholars, and experts (Saurette and Gunster, 2011). Because their differentiated answers are often hedged and conditional, science-related populism pictures them as incapable of providing simple, hands-on solutions that ordinary people demand; because they apply seemingly artificial methodological procedures such as experiments, they are blamed of disregarding authentic daily-life experiences; and because of their obligation to scientific uncertainty, they are accused of undermining the predictability of an orderly life. Crucially, this apparent disregard of the ordinary people, their demands, and their virtues leads science-related populists to describe academic elites as an immoral collective of “boffins” (Taggart, 2004: 274), who cherish an artificial epistemology and disparage the simple, naturalistic, and reliable epistemology of ordinary people.

Core principles: Decision-making sovereignty and truth-speaking sovereignty

Scholars of political populism see competing claims for political decision-making sovereignty as the underlying reason for the antagonism between the political elite and the people (Wirth et al., 2016). But science-related populism is operating within the realms of science, whose primary role is to generate knowledge and not to take political decisions. Accordingly, science-related populism suggests that the relation between the “ordinary people” and the “academic elite” is defined by competing claims for epistemic authority, that is, for sovereignty over how “true knowledge” is produced. We propose to conceptualize this epistemic authority twofold: first, as science-related decision-making sovereignty, and second, as truth-speaking sovereignty.

Decision-making sovereignty

Science-related decision-making sovereignty is the authority over decisions about what is being, or should be, researched when, how, and by whom (Bimber and Guston, 1995: 557–558). It is the right to shape research agendas, allocate funding, develop study designs or, in turn, curtail research in fields that are seen as problematic—that is, the right to formulate science-related power claims.

What defines one part of the logic of science-related populism is a conflict between the people and the academic elite over these power claims (see Figure 1). Generally, science-related populism suggests that academic elites possess science-related decision-making sovereignty, which allows scientists to work “behind closed doors” (Smith, 2015) and “do what they think is best” (Lee et al., 2005: 251) without public oversight or control. Therefore, it considers academic elites to hold such sovereignty illegitimately. Their decisions are allegedly not guided by objective scientific norms but specific ideological agendas—a “multiculturalist-relativist hegemony” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018: 369), for example—which lead to resources being committed to faulty or even “broken and useless” (Knudsen, 2017: 908) research fields like climate science, gender studies, or the humanities in general. Science-related populism may also portray scientists’ decisions as driven by the aim to further their own careers or realize personal gains (Sarathchandra and Haltinner, 2020). Eventually, science-related populism pictures the “scientific establishment” as a conspiring “big brain league” (Yiannopoulos, 2015) or a “corrupt insiders’ club” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018: 372) which ignores the topical interests of the ordinary people and does not turn to research fields that would contribute substantially to the common good.

Figure 1.

Figure 1.

Heuristic model of science-related populism.

From the perspective of science-related populism, legitimate possessors of science-related decision-making sovereignty should be the ordinary people—because their ideas about the who, how, and why of scientific knowledge production are allegedly not biased by elite interests and “powers operative behind the scenes” (Harambam and Aupers, 2015: 474) but informed by “true practical relevance.” In this vein, Brazil’s president Jair Bolsonaro, shortly before the education ministry would announce budget cuts for public universities, claimed that legitimate scientific research must “generate immediate return to the taxpayer” (dos Santos Paula, 2019).

Truth-speaking sovereignty

Truth-speaking sovereignty is the authority over defining what constitutes “true” knowledge (Bimber and Guston, 1995: 556–557). It is the right to determine valid information about the world, from official statistics about alleged immigrant crimes to interpretations about the implications of global warming—that is, the right to formulate truth claims.

A conflict over these truth claims constitutes the second part of the logic of science-related populism (see Figure 1). Generally, science-related populism suggests that the academic elite holds truth-speaking sovereignty, manifested in a “scientific establishment” claiming that the scientific epistemology—based on its particular set of theories, methodologies, and methods—is superior to other epistemologies (Harambam and Aupers, 2015). The populist view, however, perceives this as illegitimate, because scientific approaches to knowledge production do not prioritize the everyday experiences and opinions of ordinary people, but rely on seemingly alienated theories developed in the proverbial ivory tower (Saurette and Gunster, 2011) and on “methods [that] are bunk,” as Breitbart writer James Delingpole (2017) pointed out when trying to refute climate science.

Legitimate truth-speaking sovereigns are, according to science-related populism, only the ordinary people themselves, because they infer their knowledge from “experience-based common sense” (Ylä-Anttila, 2018: 363), “their proximity to everyday life” (Saurette and Gunster, 2011: 199), and “truths” that hold up in a public “opinion market” (Lewandowsky et al., 2017: 354). Thanks to their alleged homogeneity, this knowledge would not be fragmented but constitute a coherent body of evidence. As Taggart (2000) put it, “it is through their very collectiveness that [the people] are able to produce wisdom” (p. 96). Such a “cognitio populi,” which rejects deference to scientific authority (Anderson et al., 2012) by cherishing authenticity and lay negotiation, is seen as contradictory to the knowledge production by academic elites. It provokes a constellation in which both “‘the people’ and ‘the elites’ hold their own version of truth” (Waisbord, 2018: 25).

4. Science-related populism and its implications

Populism is on the rise in many countries, and its anti-elitist critique not only targets political elites, but also scientific elites. In this article, we propose a conceptualization of science-related populism. In doing so, we do not suggest that every criticism of science and its epistemology is an instance of science-related populism. Science-related populism has partial overlaps with other challenges to epistemic authorities, such as radical science movements (Quet, 2014), political or industrial efforts to undermine scientific evidence (Oreskes and Conway, 2010), science denial (Hansson, 2017), anti-intellectualism (Hofstadter, 1963), conspiracy cultures (Harambam, 2017), indigenous epistemologies (Horton, 1967), or religious doctrines (McPhetres and Zuckerman, 2018).3 But eventually, science-related populism describes one distinct variant of anti-scientific position—a variant that may be increasingly important in the wake of broader populist movements, can be distinguished from political populism, and had not yet been comprehensively conceptualized.

We understand science-related populism as a set of ideas suggesting an antagonism between an (allegedly) virtuous ordinary people and an (allegedly) unvirtuous academic elite—an antagonism that is due to the elite illegitimately claiming and the people legitimately demanding science-related decision-making sovereignty and truth-speaking sovereignty. Similar to political populism, this antagonism is seen as a conflict between a morally superior good side (the people) and a morally inferior bad side (the academic elite). Unlike political populism, however, science-related populism focuses on the core logic of science and epistemic authority. As such, it may occur in all contexts where scientific knowledge plays or may play a role, that is, in practically all areas of personal, organizational, and public life (Schäfer et al., 2015). Science-related populism may appear in different topical contexts (from strongly politicized topics like climate change or vaccination to less politicized ones like nutrition or homeopathy), may target different epistemic authorities (e.g. individual climate researchers or science in general; see Sarathchandra and Haltinner, 2020), may have different rationales (e.g. ideological agendas or vested interests; see Morgan et al., 2018), and may come in different intensities (e.g. rejection of science per se or resentment toward scientific institutions but acceptance of scientific methods; see Achterberg et al., 2017).

This conceptualization of science-related populism offers a threefold contribution to scholarship on the science–society nexus: First, it addresses current public debates, which have sometimes been operating with catchy yet vague labels like “post-truth” (Williamson, 2019) or “anti-science” (Livni, 2016) and may benefit from a more systematic understanding of the phenomenon in question. Second, it integrates existing studies of anti-academic sentiment and discourses (e.g. Davis, 2019; Harambam and Aupers, 2015; Ylä-Anttila, 2018) into a single coherent theoretical framework—which allows for (at least some of) these discourses to be interpreted as manifestations of the same phenomenon. Third, it has the potential to inspire and guide future empirical research on science-related populism, which may assess its prevalence in different national contexts or social strata, the sociodemographic or attitudinal drivers behind it, and its cognitive, affective, or behavioral impacts.

Ideally, our conceptualization would also stimulate the development of tools and methods to systematically collect data on manifestations of science-related populism. As our conceptualization relied on the “ideational approach,” which bears good operationalizability (Mudde, 2017: 39), we are confident that the key elements and principles of science-related populism can be usefully translated into survey scales, coding schemes for standardized content analyses, or qualitative approaches to text, corpus, or discourse analysis—similar to those that have been developed for measurements of political populism (e.g. Ernst et al., 2019; Hameleers, 2019; Schulz et al., 2018). This would allow for comprehensive investigations of individuals’ science-related populist attitudes (the “demand side” of science-related populism) and science-related populist communication of public figures and organizations (the “supply side”).

In fact, some prior studies have already investigated aspects of the “supply” and “demand” sides of science-related populism. They suggest that science-related populism may indeed exist as a “demand-side phenomenon,” indicating that segments of populations in different countries have low confidence in the scientific community (Motta, 2018), are skeptical toward expert opinion (Oliver and Rahn, 2016), distrust doctors, professors, and other experts (Merkley, 2020), feel controlled by science and technology (Finnish Society for Scientific Information, 2016), do not think that scientists act in the interest of the public (Funk et al., 2019), believe that scientists have a power that makes them dangerous (European Commission, 2010), and, in turn, want a say in science-related decision-making (Schäfer et al., 2018a), demand that scientists pay attention to the wishes of the public (Anderson et al., 2012), and think that people should rely more on common sense when dealing with issues such as the COVID-19 pandemic (Wissenschaft im Dialog, 2020). Other studies suggest that science-related populism also exists on the “supply side,” describing anti-scientific sentiments in political rhetoric, party programs, election posters, and slogans of populist parties and politicians in Belgium (Pauwels, 2010), France (Harsin, 2018), Germany (Berbuir et al., 2015), or Sweden (Hultman et al., 2019). But even if these studies provide first indications of the existence of science-related populism, they have not been connected to an umbrella framework like the one proposed here, and accordingly, only measure parts of science-related populism.

Furthermore, we hope that our conceptualization proves useful to future empirical research and inspires research aims and agendas. Using methodological tools such as those suggested above, scholars could assess the prevalence, spread, successes, and implications of science-related populism systematically. On its “demand side,” they could analyze the antecedents, consequences, and correlates of science-related populist attitudes. One aim would be to examine to what extent such attitudes exist apart from other populist attitudes, or if they differ along the political spectrum. On the “supply side” of science-related populism, scholars could scrutinize whether populist leaders try to connect science-related populism to host (“thick”) ideologies (Mudde, 2017), and whether these connections gain traction among followers. Such host ideologies could be, for example, economic liberalism promoting market solutions over solutions prescribed by experts (Panno et al., 2019), conservatism trying to withstand novel ideas coming from science (Rutjens et al., 2018), or libertarianism emphasizing individual freedom against compulsory measures such as vaccination or pandemic restrictions recommended by medical experts (Kennedy, 2019; Wissenschaft im Dialog, 2020). Also, scholars could examine the impact of populist leaders, such as politicians (Simons, 2016), influential entrepreneurs (Schwab, 2018), or media figures (Yiannopoulos, 2015) on the success of science-related populism.

Eventually, the normative implications of any such findings for science and society have to be discussed. On the one hand, wide-spread science-related populist attitudes among populations would necessitate a rethinking of science-society dialogue and science communication (Mede and Schäfer, forthcoming). The respective population segments would need to be addressed more specifically, with their specific attitudes in mind (Schäfer et al., 2018a). On the other hand, renewed debates about the role of science in democracy would be required—debates that have already begun but need to be continued in the future (Caramani, 2017; Collins et al., 2020).

Author biographies

Niels G. Mede is a Research and Teaching Assistant at the Department of Communication and Media Research, University of Zurich. In his research, he focuses on attitudes toward science and research, populism, and survey research methods.

Mike S. Schäfer is Professor of Science Communication at the Department of Communication and Media Research, University of Zurich. His research focuses on science communication, climate change communication, and online communication.

Notes

1

Scholars describing populism as a thin-centered ideology would argue that populism—just as other thin ideologies like feminism (Freeden, 1996)—has limited capacity to inspire a practical solution for how to tackle issues like economic crises, for example (see Stanley, 2008). In contrast, the “thick” ideology of liberalism and its emphasis on deregulation indeed suggest such a solution: lowering trade tariffs, for instance (see Freeden, 1996).

2

Critics of the ideational approach point out, however, that it does not consider the organizational structures of populist actors (Hawkins and Rovira Kaltwasser, 2017) and lacks a coherent conceptualization of ideological thinness (Aslanidis, 2016). We acknowledge these caveats, but think that they do not pose major obstacles to our argument.

3

Most of these overlaps are limited, however. The French radical science movement did not intend to replace the scientific method with common sense, for example, and political or industrial “campaigns of doubt” (Oreskes and Conway, 2010: 686) against scientific evidence do not aim to give any sovereignty to ordinary people.

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the editor, three anonymous reviewers, Sina Blassnig, Ralph Schroeder as well as our colleagues from the science communication research team at the University of Zurich for their valuable comments on this article and for many thought-provoking discussions, both of which have been great help in improving our argument.

Funding

The author(s) received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

ORCID iDs

Niels G. Mede https://orcid.org/0000-0001-5707-7568

Mike S. Schäfer https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0847-7503

References

  1. Abts K, Rummens S. (2007) Populism versus democracy. Political Studies 55(2): 405–424. [Google Scholar]
  2. Achterberg P, de Koster W, van der Waal J. (2017) A science confidence gap: Education, trust in scientific methods, and trust in scientific institutions in the United States, 2014. Public Understanding of Science 26(6): 704–720. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Anderson AA, Scheufele DA, Brossard D, Corley EA. (2012) The role of media and deference to scientific authority in cultivating trust in sources of information about emerging technologies. International Journal of Public Opinion Research 24(2): 225–237. [Google Scholar]
  4. Armingeon K. (2007) Political participation and associational involvement In: van Deth JW, Montero JR, Westhol A. (eds) Citizenship and Involvement in European Democracies. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 382–407. [Google Scholar]
  5. Aslanidis P. (2016) Is populism an ideology? A refutation and a new perspective. Political Studies 64(1): 88–104. [Google Scholar]
  6. Baraldi C, Corsi G, Esposito E. (1997) Glossar zu Niklas Luhmanns Theorie sozialer Systeme [Glossary on Niklas Luhmann's Systems Theory]. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
  7. Berbuir N, Lewandowsky M, Siri J. (2015) The AfD and its sympathisers: Finally a right-wing populist movement in Germany? German Politics 24(2): 154–178. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bherer L, Dufour P, Montambeault F. (2016) The participatory democracy turn: An introduction. Journal of Civil Society 12(3): 225–230. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bimber B, Guston DH. (1995) Politics by the same means: Government and science in the United States In: Jasanoff S, Markle G, Petersen J, Pinch T. (eds) Handbook of Science and Technology Studies. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE, pp. 554–571. [Google Scholar]
  10. Bishop C. (2012) Artificial Hells: Participatory Art and the Politics of Spectatorship. London: Verso. [Google Scholar]
  11. Blühdorn I. (2014) The participatory revolution In: Larres K. (ed.) A Companion to Europe Since 1945. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 407–431. [Google Scholar]
  12. Bottomore T. (1964) Elites and Society. London: C. A: Watts. [Google Scholar]
  13. Caramani D. (2017) Will vs. reason: The populist and technocratic forms of political representation and their critique to party government. American Political Science Review 111(1): 54–67. [Google Scholar]
  14. Caulfield T. (2020) Gwyneth Paltrow’s new Goop Lab is an infomercial for her pseudoscience business. Available at: https://theconversation.com/gwyneth-paltrows-new-goop-lab-is-an-infomercial-for-her-pseudoscience-business-129674
  15. Collins HM, Evans R, Durant D, Weinel M. (2020) Experts and the Will of the People. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  16. Crowley M, Thomas K and Haberman M (2020) Ignoring expert opinion, Trump again promotes use of hydroxychloroquine. Available at: https://www.nytimes.com/2020/04/05/us/politics/trump-hydroxychloroquine-coronavirus.html. [Google Scholar]
  17. Davis M. (2019) “ Globalist war against humanity shifts into high gear”: Online anti-vaccination websites and “anti-public” discourse. Public Understanding of Science 28(3): 357–371. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Delingpole J. (2017) Now 400 scientific papers in 2017 say “Global Warming” is a myth. Available at: https://www.breitbart.com/politics/2017/10/24/delingpole-now-400-scientific-papers-in-2017-say-global-warming-is-a-myth/
  19. Della Porta D, Rucht D. (2013) Meeting Democracy: Power and Deliberation in Global Justice Movements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. dos Santos Paula RF. (2019) Brazilian universities fear Bolsonaro plan to eliminate humanities and slash public education budgets. Available at: https://theconversation.com/brazilian-universities-fear-bolsonaro-plan-to-eliminate-humanities-and-slash-public-education-budgets-117530
  21. Einsiedel E. (2008) Public participation and dialogue In: Bucchi M, Trench B. (eds) Handbook of Public Communication of Science and Technology. London: Routledge, pp. 173–184. [Google Scholar]
  22. Einsiedel E, Eastlick DL. (2000) Consensus conferences as deliberative democracy. Science Communication 21(4): 323–343. [Google Scholar]
  23. Ernst N, Esser F, Blassnig S, Engesser S. (2019) Favorable opportunity structures for populist communication: Comparing different types of politicians and issues in social media, television and the press. The International Journal of Press/Politics 24(2): 165–188. [Google Scholar]
  24. European Commission (2010) Science and technology: Special Eurobarometer 340. Available at: http://ec.europa.eu/commfrontoffice/publicopinion/archives/ebs/ebs_340_en.pdf
  25. Fähnrich B, Janssen Danyi C, Nothhaft H. (2015) The German plagiarism crisis: Defending and explaining the workings of scholarship on the front stage. Journal of Communication Management 19(1): 20–38. [Google Scholar]
  26. Filc D, Lebel U. (2005) The post-Oslo Israeli populist radical right in comparative perspective. Mediterranean Politics 10(1): 85–97. [Google Scholar]
  27. Finnish Society for Scientific Information (2016) Summary of the Finnish science barometer 2016. Available at: http://www.tieteentiedotus.fi/files/Sciencebarometer_2016_web.pdf
  28. Forchtner B, Kroneder A, Wetzel D. (2018) Being skeptical? Exploring far-right climate-change communication in Germany. Environmental Communication 12(5): 589–604. [Google Scholar]
  29. Ford E (2013) Defining and characterizing open peer review: A review of the literature. Journal of Scholarly Publishing 44(4), 311–326. [Google Scholar]
  30. Freeden M. (1996) Ideologies and Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Füchslin T, Schäfer MS, Metag J. (2019) Who wants to be a citizen scientist? Identifying the potential of citizen science and target segments in Switzerland. Public Understanding of Science 28(6): 652–668. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Funk C, Hefferon M, Kennedy B, Johnson C. (2019) Trust and mistrust in Americans’ views of scientific experts. Available at: https://www.pewresearch.org/science/2019/08/02/trust-and-mistrust-in-americans-views-of-scientific-experts/
  33. Gerhards J. (2001) Der Aufstand des Publikums [The rebellion of the audience]. Zeitschrift für Soziologie 30(3): 463. [Google Scholar]
  34. Glaubke R. (2018) Communicating science in an era of post-truth. Available at: https://quillette.com/2018/05/29/communicating-science-era-post-truth/
  35. Gosa TL. (2011) Counterknowledge, racial paranoia, and the cultic milieu: Decoding hip hop conspiracy theory. Poetics 39(3): 187–204. [Google Scholar]
  36. Gregory J, Miller S. (1998) Science in Public: Communication, Culture, and Credibility. New York: Plenum Press. [Google Scholar]
  37. Hameleers M. (2019) The populism of online communities. Communication, Culture and Critique 12(1): 147–165. [Google Scholar]
  38. Hansson SO. (2017) Science denial as a form of pseudoscience. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 63: 39–47. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  39. Harambam J. (2017) “The truth is out there”: Conspiracy culture in an age of epistemic instability. Ph.D. Dissertation, Erasmus University Rotterdam, Rotterdam.
  40. Harambam J, Aupers S. (2015) Contesting epistemic authority: Conspiracy theories on the boundaries of science. Public Understanding of Science 24(4): 466–480. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Harsin J. (2018) Post-truth populism: The French anti-gender theory movement and cross-cultural similarities. Communication, Culture and Critique 11(1): 35–52. [Google Scholar]
  42. Hartmann M. (2004) The Sociology of Elites. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  43. Hawkins KA. (2010) Venezuela’s Chavismo and Populism in Comparative Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  44. Hawkins KA, Rovira Kaltwasser C. (2017) What the (ideational) study of populism can teach us, and what it can’t. Swiss Political Science Review 23(4): 526–542. [Google Scholar]
  45. Hofstadter R. (1963) Anti-Intellectualism in American Life. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
  46. Horton R. (1967) African traditional thought and western science. Africa 37(2): 155–187. [Google Scholar]
  47. Hultman M, Björk A, Viinikka T. (2019) The far right and climate change denial In: Forchtner B. (ed.) The Far Right and the Environment. London: Routledge, pp. 121–135. [Google Scholar]
  48. Jagers J, Walgrave S. (2007) Populism as political communication style. European Journal of Political Research 46(3): 319–345. [Google Scholar]
  49. Kennedy J. (2019) Populist politics and vaccine hesitancy in Western Europe. European Journal of Public Health 29(3): 512–516. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  50. Knudsen S. (2017) Thinking inside the frame: A framing analysis of the humanities in Danish print news media. Public Understanding of Science 26(8): 908–924. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  51. Kostelka F. (2017) Does democratic consolidation lead to a decline in voter turnout? American Political Science Review 111(4): 653–667. [Google Scholar]
  52. Lee C-J, Scheufele DA, Lewenstein BV. (2005) Public attitudes toward emerging technologies. Science Communication 27(2): 240–267. [Google Scholar]
  53. Lee CW. (2014) Do-It-Yourself Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  54. Lefort C. (1988) Democracy and Political Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
  55. Lewandowsky S, Ecker UKH, Cook J. (2017) Beyond misinformation: Understanding and coping with the “post-truth” era. Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition 6(4): 353–369. [Google Scholar]
  56. Lewis P, Clarke S, Barr C, Holder J, Kommenda N. (2018) Revealed: One in four Europeans vote populist. Available at: https://gu.com/p/9kfjd
  57. Livni E. (2016) Trump’s Skepticism about climate change is turning scientists into activists. Available at: https://qz.com/862921/
  58. MacDonald EA, Balanovic J, Edwards ED, Abrahamse W, Frame B, Greenaway A, et al. (2020) Public opinion towards Gene Drive as a pest control approach for biodiversity conservation and the association of underlying worldviews. Environmental Communication. Epub ahead of print 27 January. DOI: 10.1080/17524032.2019.1702568. [Google Scholar]
  59. McPhetres J, Zuckerman M. (2018) Religiosity predicts negative attitudes towards science and lower levels of science literacy. PLoS ONE 13(11): e0207125. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Mede NG and Schäfer MS (forthcoming) Kritik der Wissenschaftskommunikation und ihrer Analyse: PUS, PEST, Politisierung und wissenschaftsbezogener Populismus: [Critique of science communication and its analysis: PUS, PEST, politicization and science-related populism]. In: Bucher H-J (ed.) Medienkritik: Zwischen ideologischer Instrumentalisierung und kritischer Aufklärung: [Media critique: Between ideological instrumentalization and critical enlightenment]. Köln: Herbert von Halem. [Google Scholar]
  61. Mény Y, Surel Y. (2002) The constitutive ambiguity of populism In: Mény Y, Surel Y. (eds) Democracies and the Populist Challenge. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 1–21. [Google Scholar]
  62. Merkley E. (2020) Anti-intellectualism, populism, and motivated resistance to expert consensus. Public Opinion Quarterly. Epub ahead of print 26 February. DOI: 10.1093/poq/nfz053. [Google Scholar]
  63. Meyer JW, Ramirez FO, Rubinson R, Boli-Bennett J. (1977) The world educational revolution, 1950-1970. Sociology of Education 50(4): 242–258. [Google Scholar]
  64. Mills CW. (1956) The Power Elite. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  65. Moffitt B, Tormey S. (2014) Rethinking populism: Politics, mediatisation and political style. Political Studies 62(2): 381–397. [Google Scholar]
  66. Morgan M, Collins W, Sparks G, Welch JR. (2018) Identifying relevant anti-science perceptions to improve science-based communication: The negative perceptions of science scale. Social Sciences 7(4): 64–82. [Google Scholar]
  67. Motta M. (2018) The dynamics and political implications of anti-intellectualism in the United States. American Politics Research 46(3): 465–498. [Google Scholar]
  68. Mudde C. (2004) The populist zeitgeist. Government and Opposition 39(4): 542–563. [Google Scholar]
  69. Mudde C. (2017) Populism: An ideational approach In: Rovira Kaltwasser C, Taggart PA, Ochoa Espejo P, Ostiguy P. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of Populism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 27–47. [Google Scholar]
  70. Mudde C, Rovira Kaltwasser C. (2018) Studying populism in comparative perspective. Comparative Political Studies 51(13): 1667–1693. [Google Scholar]
  71. Myrick JG, Comfort SE. (2020) The pope may not be enough: How emotions, populist beliefs, and perceptions of an elite messenger interact to influence responses to climate change messaging. Mass Communication and Society 23(1): 1–21. [Google Scholar]
  72. Nabatchi T. (2010) Addressing the citizenship and democratic deficits: The potential of deliberative democracy for public administration. American Review of Public Administration 40(4): 376–399. [Google Scholar]
  73. Oliver JE, Rahn WM. (2016) Rise of the Trumpenvolk: Populism in the 2016 election. The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 667(1): 189–206. [Google Scholar]
  74. Oreskes N, Conway EM. (2010) Defeating the merchants of doubt. Nature 465(7299): 686–687. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Panizza F, Miorelli R. (2009) Populism and democracy in Latin America. Ethics & International Affairs 23(1): 39–46. [Google Scholar]
  76. Panno A, Carrus G, Leone L. (2019) Attitudes towards Trump policies and climate change. Journal of Social Issues 75(1): 153–168. [Google Scholar]
  77. Papacharissi Z. (2009) The virtual sphere 2.0 In: Chadwick AJ, Howard PN. (eds) Routledge Handbook of Internet Politics. London: Routledge, pp. 230–245. [Google Scholar]
  78. Pauwels T. (2010) Explaining the success of neo-liberal populist parties. Political Studies 58(5): 1009–1029. [Google Scholar]
  79. Poberezhskaya M. (2018) Blogging about climate change in Russia: Activism, scepticism and conspiracies. Environmental Communication 12(7): 942–955. [Google Scholar]
  80. Priester K. (2011) Definitionen und Typologien des Populismus [Definitions and typologies of populism]. Soziale Welt 62(2): 185– 198. [Google Scholar]
  81. Quet M. (2014) Science to the people! (and experimental politics): Searching for the roots of participatory discourse in science and technology in the 1970s in France. Public Understanding of Science 23(6): 628–645. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  82. Reinemann C, Aalberg T, Esser F, Strömbäck J, de Vreese CH. (2017) Populist political communication: Towards a model of its causes, forms, and effects In: Aalberg T, Esser F, Reinemann C, Strömbäck J, de Vreese C. (eds) Populist Political Communication in Europe. London: Routledge, pp. 12–25. [Google Scholar]
  83. Rooduijn M. (2014) The nucleus of populism. Government and Opposition 49(4): 573–599. [Google Scholar]
  84. Rooduijn M. (2019) State of the field: How to study populism and adjacent topics? European Journal of Political Research 58(1): 362–372. [Google Scholar]
  85. Rutjens BT, Sutton RM, van der Lee R. (2018) Not all skepticism is equal: Exploring the ideological antecedents of science acceptance and rejection. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 44(3): 384–405. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  86. Saarinen A, Koivula A, Keipi T. (2020) Political trust, political party preference and trust in knowledge-based institutions. International Journal of Sociology and Social Policy 40(1–2): 154–168. [Google Scholar]
  87. Sarathchandra D, Haltinner K. (2020) Trust/distrust judgments and perceptions of climate science. Public Understanding of Science 29(1): 53–60. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  88. Saurette P, Gunster S. (2011) Ears wide shut: Epistemological populism, argutainment and Canadian conservative talk radio. Canadian Journal of Political Science 44(1): 195–218. [Google Scholar]
  89. Saurugger S. (2010) The social construction of the participatory turn. European Journal of Political Research 49(4): 471–495. [Google Scholar]
  90. Schäfer MS, Füchslin T, Metag J, et al. (2018. a) The different audiences of science communication: A segmentation analysis of the Swiss population’s perceptions of science and their information and media use patterns. Public Understanding of Science 27(7): 836–856. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  91. Schäfer MS, Kristiansen S, Bonfadelli H. (2015) Wissenschaftskommunikation im Wandel: Relevanz, Entwicklung und Herausforderungen des Forschungsfeldes [Changes in science communication: Relevance, development and challenges of the research field]. In: Schäfer MS, Kristiansen S, Bonfadelli H. (eds) Wissenschaftskommunikation im Wandel [Changes in science communication]. Köln: Herbert von Halem, pp. 10–42. [Google Scholar]
  92. Schäfer MS, Metag J, Feustle J, et al. (2018. b) Selling science 2.0: What scientific projects receive crowdfunding online? Public Understanding of Science 27(5): 496–514. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  93. Schetsche M, Schmied-Knittel I. (2018) Heterodoxie: Konzepte, Traditionen, Figuren der Abweichung [Heterodoxy: Concepts, traditions, patterns of deviation]. Köln: Herbert von Halem Verlag. [Google Scholar]
  94. Schulz A, Müller P, Schemer C, Wirz DS, Wettstein M, Wirth W. (2018) Measuring populist attitudes on three dimensions . International Journal of Public Opinion Research 30(2): 316–326. [Google Scholar]
  95. Schwab F. (2018) “Hypnotic mass phenomena”: Interview of the Week: Peter Thiel. Available at: https://www.weltwoche.ch/ausgaben/2018-29/titelgeschichte/en-hypnotische-massenphanomene-die-weltwoche-ausgabe-29-2018.html
  96. Simons N. (2016) Michael Gove accused of “Donald Trump politics” in Feisty Sky news EU referendum TV debate. Available at: https://www.huffingtonpost.co.uk/entry/5751e4bde4b04a0827f1a12d
  97. Smith A. (2018) Divided nations: Democracy in an age of populism. The Sociological Quarterly 59(1): 3–4. [Google Scholar]
  98. Smith L. (2015) Changing the data to get climate change. Available at: https://www.breitbart.com/politics/2015/11/16/changing-the-data-to-get-climate-change/
  99. Stanley B. (2008) The thin ideology of populism. Journal of Political Ideologies 13(1): 95–110. [Google Scholar]
  100. Taggart P. (2000) Populism. Buckingham: Open University Press. [Google Scholar]
  101. Taggart P. (2004) Populism and representative politics in contemporary Europe. Journal of Political Ideologies 9(3): 269–288. [Google Scholar]
  102. van Zoonen L. (2012) I-Pistemology: Changing truth claims in popular and political culture. European Journal of Communication 27(1): 56–67. [Google Scholar]
  103. Wade L. (2019) Mexico’s new President shocks scientists with budget cuts and disparaging remarks. Available at: 10.1126/science.aay8526 [DOI]
  104. Waisbord S. (2018) The elective affinity between post-truth communication and populist politics. Communication Research and Practice 4(1): 17–34. [Google Scholar]
  105. Williams M. (1996) Rethinking sovereignty In: Kofman E, Youngs G. (eds) Globalization: Theory and Practice. London: Pinter, pp. 109–122. [Google Scholar]
  106. Williamson T. (2019) In the post-truth world, we need to remember the philosophy of science. Available at: https://www.newstatesman.com/2019/01/post-truth-world-we-need-remember-philosophy-science
  107. Wirth W, Esser F, Wettstein M, Engesser S, Wirz D, Schulz A, et al. (2016) The appeal of populist ideas, strategies and styles: A theoretical model and research design for analyzing populist political communication NCCR working paper no. 88. Zürich: National Centre of Competence in Research (NCCR; ). [Google Scholar]
  108. Wissenschaft im Dialog (2020) Science barometer special edition on Corona. Available at: https://www.wissenschaft-im-dialog.de/en/our-projects/science-barometer/science-barometer-special-edition-on-corona/. [Google Scholar]
  109. Wolff RP. (1998) In Defense of Anarchism. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
  110. World Bank (2002) Constructing Knowledge Societies. Washington, DC: World Bank. [Google Scholar]
  111. World Bank (2002) Constructing Knowledge Societies. Washington, DC: World Bank. [Google Scholar]
  112. Yiannopoulos M. (2015) Scientists who are actually really stupid: #1, Neil Degrasse Tyson. Available at: https://www.breitbart.com/tech/2015/12/21/scientists-who-are-actually-really-stupid-1-neil-degrasse-tyson/
  113. Ylä-Anttila T. (2018) Populist knowledge: “Post-truth” repertoires of contesting epistemic authorities. European Journal of Cultural and Political Sociology 5(4): 356–388. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Public Understanding of Science (Bristol, England) are provided here courtesy of SAGE Publications

RESOURCES