Abstract
Ritual is not a proper scientific object, as the term is used to denote disparate forms of behaviour, on the basis of a faint family resemblance. Indeed, a variety of distinct cognitive mechanisms are engaged, in various combinations, in the diverse interactions called ‘rituals’ – and each of these mechanisms deserves study, in terms of its evolutionary underpinnings and cultural consequences. We identify four such mechanisms that each appear in some ‘rituals’, namely (i) the normative scripting of actions; (ii) the use of interactions to signal coalitional identity, affiliation, cohesiveness; (iii) magical claims based on intuitive expectations of contagion; and (iv) ritualized behaviour based on a specific handling of the flow of behaviour. We describe the cognitive and evolutionary background to each of these potential components of ‘rituals’, and their effects on cultural transmission.
This article is part of the theme issue ‘Ritual renaissance: new insights into the most human of behaviours'.
Keywords: rituals, evolutionary psychology, cultural evolution, conventions, magic
1. Introduction
The term ‘ritual’ is commonly used, on the basis of a family resemblance, to denote situations as disparate as, e.g. the Hajj or pilgrimage to Mecca; the repetitive behaviours of young children before going to sleep; the recitation of a magical incantation or formula; participation in a Thanksgiving dinner; the compulsive actions of an obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD) patient; military rules for standing, walking, saluting; and many others. It is a fool's errand to search for causally relevant common features in such disparate behaviours.
We cannot have a theory of rituals, nor do we need one, but we can have something much more productive, a precise understanding of the different kinds of mental systems activated, in diverse combinations, in the very diverse forms of behaviour and social interaction that have been called ‘rituals’, and a better understanding of their likely cognitive and social effects.
The point of understanding ‘rituals’ is to explain why people engage in those behaviours, and how they become ‘cultural’, that is, represented in roughly similar ways among individuals, as a result of interaction and communication [1]. Evolved predispositions make some kinds of representations easier to acquire than others, and make it likely that individuals will re-construct those particular representations on the basis of fragmentary, noisy or variable inputs, actualizing attractors in the space of possible cultural representations [2,3].
For each of the different mental systems described below, we try to show how it contributes to the cultural success of forms of interaction (including some ‘rituals’) that activate it, over behaviours or representations that do not.
2. Scripted, normative interactions: coordination effects
(a). The phenomenon
Among the Swazi of South Africa, incwala is the name of a long sequence of social interactions, following particular scripts that all participants are expected to follow closely. For instance, incwala must occur just before people have started consuming their new crops; only a member of the royal clan may organize the ceremony; a black ox must be taken from a commoner's herd for sacrifice; and there are many other conditions [4,5]. Change some of those prescriptions and people would certainly have the intuition that incwala had not really been performed. People share expectations about the way specific interactions are expected to unfold, and what different participants should do. Violations of these rules, e.g. performing your bar-mitzvah on your own, or without wearing the tefillin, often triggers the intuition that the interaction that occurred was not ‘really’ an instance of that named category.
(b). The evolutionary–cognitive background: normativity
We know that many instances of social interaction are scripted, which means that participants hold a mental representation of the various parts of the interaction, the various roles, their causal dependencies, and so on [6]. Among scripted actions, some are named, so that (i) participants know that there is a set of actions that define the interaction, (ii) they also know that others have some representation of these actions, and (iii) they assume that it probably is the same representation as theirs [7]. Which interactions are scripted of course is a matter of local conventions. For instance, a romantic ‘date’ is a named interaction in the USA but is not so in other countries, e.g. France or Italy.
The fact that people name and thereby categorize scripted interactions is obviously related to human social capacities, notably the evolved capacities that sustain coordination. In game-theory, the term denotes those interactions in which the different players are better off, as long as they either do the same as the others (e.g. drive on the left side of the road) or do the opposite (e.g. walk through the door if someone holds it for you) [8]. Most coordination games in actual social interaction are much more complicated, as they require the orchestration of many different behaviours from many different actors.
Named and scripted interactions are often the object of normative expectations, in the sense that (i) one expects others to follow the rules, and (ii) one expects others to expect one to follow them [9]. These expectations are grounded in an underlying norm psychology that seems to appear early in development [10]. Indeed, children as young as 3 years of age spontaneously attach normative rules to an arbitrary sequence of acts that they learn, when they try to transmit it to other children [11]. Young children also react to violations of such ‘norms’ even if they have no detrimental practical consequences [12]. Even though young children are sensitive to the difference between mere conventions (that could be different in different places) and moral rules (that, in their view, could not be different) [13], they do not conclude that conventions are therefore optional. The fact that ‘elsewhere people do things differently’ does not for them entail that ‘you may violate the norm’ [10].
We would expect scripted interactions to be all the more culturally successful, as they include material that activates this normative psychology, as is often the case in forms of interaction identified as ‘rituals’. The latter are culturally transmitted, to the extent that individuals are motivated to reiterate past instances, and do it in (roughly) the same way. Prescriptions formulated as norms (e.g. ‘one must use a black ox, only from a non-royal clan’) would enhance the motivation to replicate the behaviours in detail.
3. Coalitional signalling: affiliation and cohesion
(a). The phenomenon
In the modern USA, displaying an archaic version of the nation's flag can be seen as clearly expressing the view that some groups are not part of the nation [14]. For British people, notions of what the nation is or should be have been for a long time evoked by civil ceremonies like the Opening of Parliament, but also by festive occasions like the British Broadcasting Corporation's Promenade concerts (Proms) [15]. In a very different context, shared material objects and practices are vested with great significance for cohesion in small groups such as terrorist cells [16]. The connections between engaging in a normative, scripted interaction, and conveying information about group identity and commitment, are too familiar to require further illustrations [17].
In many cases, as anthropologists have emphasized, the prescribed actions promote cohesiveness by including commentaries on the social order, ascribing positions and rank in hierarchies, identifying social units and their relations. For instance, the ekimomwar of Turkana pastoralists in Kenya includes splitting in half a sacrificed ox. All participants are then instructed to form a line and cross the scene of this sacrifice, in a prescribed order of clans, elders, then adult males crossing first, followed by the adolescent and girls of marriage-age, within each clan, providing a sequential representation of a (somewhat idealized) social structure [18]. In such occasions, performance contributes to common knowledge by creating an accessible reference point that results in similar representations in participants [19].
Another potential effect of these forms of interaction is to produce a strong feeling of cohesiveness in different individuals, or even a sense of ‘fusion’ of the self into the group [20]. This may be the effect of shared arousing experiences, but also of synchronized behaviour [21,22] that seem to enhance altruistic dispositions towards other group-members.
(b). The evolutionary–cognitive background: coalitional psychology
These aspects of scripted interactions are clearly connected to human adaptations for living in groups [23]. In social psychology, these phenomena are often described in terms of attitudes towards ‘ingroups’ versus ‘outgroups’ [24], but such attitudes are themselves the outcome of a broader set of evolved mechanisms, that allow humans to build and maintain coalitions [25,26].
Human coalitional psychology consists in a set of evolved mechanisms designed to garner support from conspecifics, organize and maintain alliances, and increase an alliance's chance of success against rival coalitions. This psychology is activated when conflicts or cooperation between non-kin go beyond a dyad [27]. It allows interactions to scale up to large numbers of individuals in highly similar manner, regardless of whether the alliance in question is construed in ethnic, racial, moral, or political terms [28]. Coalitional psychology allows human beings to entertain the notion of groups of any size as agents with beliefs, intentions and memories [29]. The evolutionary background (males engaging in group defence and inter-group conflict, women having to form alliances with unrelated females) would explain why men and women typically build different kinds of alliances (recruiting large groups for specific goals, and cultivating durable small-scale cooperation, respectively) [30,31].
Coalitional affiliation is uniquely beneficial to humans, as their fitness largely depends on collective action, and it is supported by unique human capacities, e.g. for memory and communication, that allow us to represent complex webs of past and present affiliations. Coalitional affiliation triggers the intuition that benefits (/costs) to one's group count as benefits (/costs) to self, as well as the frequent expectation that benefits accrued by distinct alliances are zero-sum [32]. It also triggers motivations (i) to join alliances, (ii) to convey one's commitment to others, and (iii) to monitor the commitment of others.
That is why signalling is crucial to coalitional mechanisms, and why some of the behaviours called ‘rituals’ seem quite natural in contexts of coalitional affiliation and conflict. First, specific signals serve to convey one's commitment to other members of the group, that is, one's willingness to incur costs for others in the future. As that is difficult to demonstrate ex ante, people often intuitively prefer ‘costly’ signals, for instance accepting heavy entry costs (e.g. painful initiation or effortful training) for the sake of joining a religious group, and being seen as a committed member [33]. Second, some behaviours create signals intended for other, possibly rival coalitions. Given widespread zero-sum assumptions, one is motivated to persuade other coalitions that one's own group is numerous, potentially aggressive (at least in its own defence) and highly cohesive. That is probably one of the reasons why participants in military groups, but also in large-scale religious groups, find it appropriate to create the illusion of a single, collective will, e.g. by identical uniforms, unison singing, synchronized gestures.
Coalitional psychology probably contributes to the cultural stability of particular ‘rituals’, inasmuch as these forms of interaction include signals of affiliation, of commitment to the group, or of group strength and cohesiveness. Also, we would expect those ‘rituals’ that include themes relevant to inter-group conflict to be typically performed by and for men. Our evolved motivation to send and monitor coalitional signals strengthen the motivation for reproducing interactions that include and require them.
4. Magical causation
(a). The phenomenon
In Brazil, the term simpatia denotes a very diverse set of actions from which people expect specific outcomes, such as good grades at school, recovery from illness, an untroubled marriage or economic success. Most simpatias take the form of highly specific prescriptions, e.g. ‘buy a new sharp knife and stick it four times into a banana tree on June 12th at midnight […] Catch the liquid that will drip from the plant's wound on a crisp, white paper that has been folded in two…’ and so forth [34]. In a similar way, among shepherds of northern Greece, touching sacred objects such as crucifixes or icons, or sprinkling water blessed at particular religious holidays over one's sheep, will impart protection against misfortune [35].
Many (but not all) of the behaviours and interactions commonly identified as ‘rituals’ come with the belief that, because of the specific choice of actions and words, equally specific, physical effects will occur through inscrutable causal processes. The individuals engaged in such activities rarely ponder the nature of the causal processes involved. Some people in some places may have theories about that, but such speculation is not necessary for belief.
(b). The evolutionary–cognitive background: contagion and relevance
Where does belief in magic come from? The phenomenon is widespread and has been the object of anthropological theorizing for more than a century [36]. Classical anthropologists noticed that claims to magical connections often mentioned some form of similarity or contiguity between cause and supposed effect; but this did not predict which kinds of similarity would be used, nor of course did it explain why people would find such connections of any special relevance [37].
Acceptance of some forms of magical processes is common in young children [38], and develops together with their more general understanding of causal processes in nature [39]. So it does not require a special ‘mentality’, or a suspension of ordinary causal cognition, to entertain magical claims. What is required are mechanisms that make those claims, in specific contexts, sufficiently compelling to be the object of what Sperber calls ‘reflective beliefs’, that is, not the belief that p but the belief that some version of p expresses some (undefined) truth [40].
One important factor in boosting the ‘naturalness’ of such beliefs is that they seem to activate heuristics and tacit assumptions that underpin our intuitions about illness and contagion. In many places in the world, people hold explicit beliefs about contagion (e.g. through ‘bad air’ or ‘miasma’). The theories are culturally successful because most human beings hold tacit intuitive expectations about disease transmission, specifying for instance: (i) that it involves invisible vectors, (ii) that use all modes of contact between people, and (iii) show no dose effect – i.e. minimal contact is just as dangerous as extensive interaction [41]. Even young children hold those principled expectations, before they acquire cultural theories of illness [42].
As a consequence, forms of interactions that include specific causal claims (e.g. sticking a knife in a banana as causing success in school exams) will be all the more intuitively compelling, and therefore privileged in cultural transmission, that they evoke cognitive systems like our contagion psychology, which by themselves include opaque causal expectations.
5. Ritualized behaviour
Finally, we must describe a specific kind of action that is for many people the hallmark of ‘rituals’, although it is neither universal in what are called ‘rituals’, nor in fact exclusive to them. Consider our previous Turkana example. An ox with a particular characteristic dreamt by a diviner (emuron) must be provided by a specific clan. The ox must be made to ambulate a specific number of times around the dancing participants. The animal must be made to gyrate in the direction opposite to the participants' round dance. The members of the clan who provided the ox must rub their bodies from head to loin on the forehead of the sacrificial animal. Each participant must step on the flat of an axe placed between the sacrificial animal's body parts. Such focal moments combine the following features:
-
(i)
compulsion: the agents feel a strong motivation to perform that set of actions, although they may not represent any specific reasons for performing it;
-
(ii)
scriptedness: the agent also feels that the actions must be performed in a specific way, and in a specific order. Again, the agent may or may not represent any reasons for the scriptedness;
-
(iii)
goal-demotion: the overall series of actions may be described as directed to a goal, but there is no representation of how the different parts contribute to that goal; and
-
(iv)
redundancy: in many cases actions are repeated, although people do not need to represent why they should be repeated.
These features define what we called ritualized behaviour [43], a special form of action that is not present in all ‘rituals’, in fact usually occurs only at particular, limited moments of some ceremonies, and is found outside collective ‘rituals’, in some children's repetitive actions [44] and in the behaviour of obsessive–compulsive patients [45].
Ritualized behaviour is the opposite of routinized behaviour, where the performance and sequencing of actions are automatic [46,47]. In ritualized behaviour as described here, the agent's attention is entirely captured by explicit representation of the rules, while by contrast routinized automatic behaviour can be accomplished without engaging attentional networks.
Whether a specific action does or does not constitute ritualized behaviour in this sense, only depends on the agent's cognitive processes. So a specific set of actions may be ritualized behaviour for one participant, and automatic routine for another. That may be the case for instance in adult baptism, in which the patient is representing all the rules as imperative and causally opaque, while the religious specialist may carry them out in a routinized manner.
(a). Background: threat-detection psychology
We hypothesized that the attractiveness of ritualized behaviour, in the precise sense used here, is best explained in the context of the human capacities for the detection and prevention of potential threats [43,48,49]. Evolved neuro-cognitive structures specialized in potential danger differ from those responding to actual, imminent threats. The threat-detection system is specifically focused on potential hazards that were recurrent in ancestral conditions, such as predation, intrusion by strangers, contamination, contagion, social offence and harm to offspring [50].
Disruption of threat-detection systems results in specific pathologies, such as phobias, post-traumatic stress disorder, and, most relevant here, OCD. Typical presentations of OCD include intrusive thoughts about potential dangers, as well as compulsive, repetitive scripted behaviours. Among the mechanisms involved is a biased appraisal of potential dangers [51], combined with an increased generation of risk scenarios [52]. A major component of OCD ‘rituals’ is the failure of precautionary behaviours to raise the patient's intuitive security appraisal, leading to pathological repetition [49,53]. Because of their roots in evolved threat-detection, these pathological presentations combine the formal aspects of ritualized behaviour (repetition, compulsion, redundancy, goal-demotion) with a very special set of themes, such as a concern with predators, invisible and dangerous agents, as well as cleanliness and protection from invisible pathogens, and a strong motivation to re-organize one's environment in a regular, predictable manner [54,55].
Both ritualized behaviour (in our precise sense) and the specific themes of OCD cognition are also present in many collective ceremonies, as noticed by many anthropologists and by Freud, who saw religious rituals as a collective form of the ‘repetitive neurosis’ [56]. A more sober interpretation is that people who participate in ritualized behaviour find ritual prescriptions intuitively natural and compelling, to the extent that these rules and themes activate associations with our threat-detection psychology [43]—for instance in the case of such rules as ‘pass the carefully cleaned chicken seven times, clockwise, around the participants, to protect the community against impurity’. We need not postulate that people reiterate past ritualized behaviour because of a belief in its effects—all that is required is that the details of prescribed performance activate our threat-detection psychology, more than possible cultural variants.
6. No need for a theory of ‘ritual’
What we commonly call ‘rituals’ are, in many cases, named social interactions that include some of the ingredients described above. Some, but not all of these interactions, include some representation of magical causation. Some, but not all, include normative behaviours, with potential signalling of group identity or cohesion. Some include ritualized behaviour in the precise sense defined here, but that is not true of all things called ‘rituals’ and in general is only a small part of the ‘rituals’ that include it. For instance, the simpatias described by Legare & Souza [34] include primarily some magical causation and some normative scripted action sequences. The ox sacrifice among the Turkana includes some ritualized behaviour (in the precise sense used here), as well as signalling, and some coordination effect from scripts with normative entailments. Figure 1 sketches a more general map of these possible combinations.
Each of the features or processes described here, and often found in interactions called rituals, (i) have specific effects on social interaction, (ii) engage specific cognitive processes, and (iii) are connected in specific ways to evolution by natural selection. The study of these processes has only just begun in evolutionary anthropology and psychology. If, like other mature disciplines, this field abandons familiar but misleading everyday categories (‘ritual’ being like ‘religion’ or ‘family’), it may well make much progress in explaining similarities and differences in interaction in human communities.
Data accessibility
This article has no additional data.
Authors' Contributions
Both authors contributed materials and collaborated in the writing.
Competing interests
We declare we have no competing interests.
Funding
We received no funding for this study.
References
- 1.Sperber D. 1996. Explaining culture: a naturalistic approach. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Claidière N, Scott-Phillips TC, Sperber D. 2014. How Darwinian is cultural evolution? Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 369, 20130368 ( 10.1098/rstb.2013.0368) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Claidière N, Sperber D. 2007. The role of attraction in cultural evolution. J. Cogn. Cult. 7, 89–111. ( 10.1163/156853707X171829) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Kuper H. 2018[1947] An African aristocracy: rank Among the swazi (reprint). London, UK: Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
- 5.Gluckman M. 1955. Rituals of rebellion in south-east Africa. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 6.Schank RC, Abelson RP. 1977. Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding: an inquiry into human knowledge structures. London, UK: Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
- 7.Chwe MS-Y. 2001. Rational ritual: culture, coordination, and common knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Camerer C. 2003. Behavioral game theory: experiments in strategic interaction. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 9.Bicchieri C. 2006. The grammar of society: the nature and dynamics of social norms. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 10.Rakoczy H, Schmidt MFH. 2013. The early ontogeny of social norms. Child Dev. Persp. 7, 17–21. ( 10.1111/cdep.12010) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Göckeritz S, Schmidt MFH, Tomasello M. 2014. Young children's creation and transmission of social norms. Cogn. Dev. 30, 81–95. ( 10.1016/j.cogdev.2014.01.003) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Rakoczy H, Warneken F, Tomasello M. 2008. The sources of normativity: young children's awareness of the normative structure of games. Dev. Psychol. 44, 875–881. ( 10.1037/0012-1649.44.3.875) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Turiel E. 1994. The development of social-conventional and moral concepts. In Fundamental research in moral development. Moral development: a compendium, vol. 2. (ed. Bill P.), pp. 255–292. New York, NY: Garland Publishing, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- 14.Olson A. 2019. Nike nixes flag design shoe after white supremacist questions. The people's World, retrieved 15 January, 2020. See https://www.peoplesworld.org/article/nike-nixes-flat-design-shoe-after-kaepernick-questions-white-supremacist-symbolism.
- 15.Poston L. 2005. Henry Wood, the ‘proms’, and national identity in music, 1895–1904. Vic. Stud. 47, 397–426. ( 10.1353/vic.2005.0104) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Elster J. 2005. Motivations and beliefs in suicide missions. In Making sense of suicide missions (ed. Gambetta D.), pp. 233–258. New York: NY: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 17.Watson-Jones RE, Legare CH. 2016. The social functions of group rituals. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 25, 42–46. ( 10.1177/0963721415618486) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Lienard P. 2004. Kuju/kwap, kide/too: La valence des coordonnées spatiales de la topographie Turkana. Civilisations. Revue internationale d'anthropologie et de sciences humaines 52, 81–113. ( 10.4000/civilisations.744) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Chwe MSY. 2013. Rational ritual: culture, coordination, and common knowledge, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 20.Whitehouse H, et al. 2014. The ties that bind us: ritual, fusion, and identification. Curr. Anthropol. 55, 674–695. ( 10.1086/678698) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Feldman R. 2014. Synchrony and the neurobiological basis of social affiliation. In Mechanisms of social connection: from brain to group (eds Mikulincer M, Shaver PR), pp. 145–166. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. [Google Scholar]
- 22.Reddish P, Tong EMW, Jong J, Lanman JA, Whitehouse H. 2016. Collective synchrony increases prosociality towards non-performers and outgroup members. Br. J. Soc. Psychol. 55, 722–738. ( 10.1111/bjso.12165) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Legare CH, Wen N. 2014. The effects of ritual on the development of social group cognition. Int. Soc. Study Behav. Dev. 2, 9–12. [Google Scholar]
- 24.Hornsey MJ. 2008. Social identity theory and self-categorization theory: a historical review. Soc. Personality Psychol. Compass 2, 204–222. ( 10.1111/j.1751-9004.2007.00066.x) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Yamagishi T, Mifune N. 2009. Social exchange and solidarity: in-group love or out-group hate? Evol. Hum. Behav. 30, 229–237. ( 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2009.02.004) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Kiyonari T, Tanida S, Yamagishi T. 2000. Social exchange and reciprocity: confusion or a heuristic? Evol. Hum. Behav. 21, 411–427. ( 10.1016/s1090-5138(00)00055-6) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Pietraszewski D. 2016. How the mind sees coalitional and group conflict: the evolutionary invariances of n-person conflict dynamics. Evol. Hum. Behav. 37, 470–480. ( 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2016.04.006) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Boyer P, Firat R, van Leeuwen F.. 2015. Safety, threat, and stress in intergroup relations: a coalitional index model. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 10, 434–450. ( 10.1177/1745691615583133) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Pietraszewski D. 2013. What is group psychology? Adaptations for mapping shared intentional stances. In Navigating the social world: what infants, children, and other species can teach us (eds Banaji MR, Gelman SA, Banaji MR, Gelman SA), pp. 253–257. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 30.van Vugt M, Cremer DD, Janssen DP.. 2007. Gender differences in cooperation and competition: the male-warrior hypothesis. Psychol. Sci. 18, 19–23. ( 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01842.x) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Campbell A. 2015. Women's competition and aggression. In The handbook of evolutionary psychology, 2nd edn (ed. Buss DM.), pp. 684–702. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons Inc. [Google Scholar]
- 32.Tooby J, Cosmides L. 2010. Groups in mind: the coalitional roots of war and morality. In Human morality & sociality: evolutionary & comparative perspectives (ed. Høgh-Olesen H.), pp. 191–234. New York: NY: Palgrave MacMillan. [Google Scholar]
- 33.Sosis R. 2006. Religious behaviors, badges, and bans: signaling theory and the evolution of religion. In Where God and science meet: how brain and evolutionary studies alter our understanding of religion (vol 1): evolution, genes, and the religious brain (ed. McNamara P.), pp. 77–102. Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers/Greenwood Publishing Group. [Google Scholar]
- 34.Legare CH, Souza AL. 2012. Evaluating ritual efficacy: evidence from the supernatural. Cognition 124, 1–15. ( 10.1016/j.cognition.2012.03.004) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Campbell JK. 1970. Honour, family, and patronage: a study of institutions and moral values in a Greek mountain community. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- 36.Tambiah SJ. 1990. Magic, science, religion, and the scope of rationality. New York: NY: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 37.Sperber D. 1996. Why are perfect animals, hybrids, and monsters food for symbolic thought? Meth. Theory Study Religion 8, 143–169. ( 10.1163/157006896X00170) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Johnson CN, Harris P. 1994. Magic: special but not excluded. Brit. J. Dev. Psychol. 12, 35–51. ( 10.1111/j.2044-835X.1994.tb00617.x) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Rosengren KS, Kalish CW, Hickling AK, Gelman SA. 1994. Exploring the relation between preschool children's magical beliefs and causal thinking. Special Issue: Magic. Brit. J. Dev. Psychol. 12, 69–82. ( 10.1111/j.2044-835X.1994.tb00619.x) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Sperber D. 1997. Intuitive and reflective beliefs. Mind Lang. 12, 17 ( 10.1111/1468-0017.00036) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Nemeroff C, Rozin P. 1994. The contagion concept in adult thinking in the United States: transmission of germs and of interpersonal influence. Ethos 22, 158–186. ( 10.1525/eth.1994.22.2.02a00020) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Kalish CW. 1999. What young children's understanding of contamination and contagion tells us about their concepts of illness. In Children's understanding of biology and health (eds Siegal M, Petersen CC), pp. 99–130. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 43.Lienard P, Boyer P. 2006. Whence collective rituals? A cultural selection model of ritualized behavior. Am. Anthropol. 108, 814–827. ( 10.1525/aa.2006.108.4.814) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Evans DW, et al. 1997. Ritual, habit, and perfectionism: the prevalence and development of compulsive-like behavior in normal young children. Child Dev. 68, 58–68. ( 10.2307/1131925) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Boyer P, Lienard P. 2006. Why ritualized behavior? Precaution systems and action parsing in developmental, pathological and cultural rituals. Behav. Brain Sci. 29, 595–613. ( 10.1017/S0140525X06009332) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Logan GD. 1988. Toward an instance theory of automatization. Psychol. Rev. 95, 492–527. ( 10.1037/0033-295x.95.4.492). [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Logan GD. 1989. Automaticity and cognitive control. Unintended Thought 1989, 52–74. [Google Scholar]
- 48.Boyer P, Lienard P. 2008. Ritual behavior in obsessive and normal individuals: moderating anxiety and reorganizing the flow of action. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. (Wiley-Blackwell) 17, 291–294. ( 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2008.00592.x) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Szechtman H, Woody E. 2004. Obsessive-compulsive disorder as a disturbance of security motivation. Psychol. Rev. 111, 111–127. ( 10.1037/0033-295X.111.1.111) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Boyer P, Bergstrom B. 2011. Threat-detection in child development: an evolutionary perspective. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 35, 1034–1041. ( 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2010.08.010) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Foa EB, et al. 1993. Information processing in obsessive-compulsive disorder. Cogn. Therapy Res. 17, 173–189. ( 10.1007/BF01172964) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Abed RT, de Pauw KW.. 1998. An evolutionary hypothesis for obsessive compulsive disorder: a psychological immune system? Behav. Neurol. 11, 245–250. ( 10.1155/1999/657382) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Zor R, Keren H, Hermesh H, Szechtman H, Mort J, Eilam D. 2009. Obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD): a disorder of pessimal (non-functional) behavior. Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 120, 288–298. ( 10.1111/j.1600-0447.2009.01370.x) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Dulaney S, Fiske AP. 1994. Cultural rituals and obsessive-compulsive disorder: is there a common psychological mechanism? Ethos 22, 243–283. ( 10.1525/eth.1994.22.3.02a00010) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Fiske AP, Haslam N. 1997. Is obsessive-compulsive disorder a pathology of the human disposition to perform socially meaningful rituals? Evidence of similar content. J. Nervous Mental Dis. 185, 211–222. ( 10.1097/00005053-199704000-00001) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Freud S. 1948. (1906) Zwangsbehandlungen und Religionsübungen. In Gesammelte werke von Sigmund Freud, chronologisch geordnet (ed. Freud AEA.), pp. 107–116. London, UK: Imago Publishing. [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Data Availability Statement
This article has no additional data.