Skip to main content
World Psychiatry logoLink to World Psychiatry
. 2020 Sep 15;19(3):381–388. doi: 10.1002/wps.20774

The evolution of Kraepelin's nosological principles

Stephan Heckers 1, Kenneth S Kendler 2
PMCID: PMC7491624  PMID: 32931122

Abstract

Emil Kraepelin developed a new psychiatric nosology in the eight editions of his textbook. Previous papers have explored his construction of particular diagnoses, including dementia praecox and manic‐depressive insanity. Here we are providing a close reading of his introductory textbook chapter, that presents his general principles of nosology. We identify three phases: 1) editions 1‐4, in which he describes nosological principles in search of data; 2) editions 5‐7, in which he declares the mature version of his nosological principles and develops new disease categories; 3) edition 8, in which he qualifies his nosological claims and allows for greater differentiation of psychiatric disorders. We propose that Kraepelin's nosology is grounded in three principles. First, psychiatry, like other sciences, deals with natural phenomena. Second, mental states cannot be reduced to neural states, but science will progress and will, ultimately, reveal how nature creates abnormal mental states and behavior. Third, there is a hierarchy of validators of psychiatric diagnoses, with the careful study of clinical features (signs, symptoms and course) being more important than neuropathologic and etiological studies. These three principles emerged over the course of the eight editions of Kraepelin's textbook and were informed by his own research and by available scientific methods. His scientific views are still relevant today: they have generated and, at the same time, constrained our current psychiatric nosology.

Keywords: Kraepelin, psychiatric nosology, psychiatry textbook, psychoses, clinical pictures, disease forms, scientific naturalism, natural kinds, validators


Emil Kraepelin (1856‐1926) proposed the diagnoses of dementia praecox and manic‐depressive insanity in an effort to advance the clinical management and scientific study of the psychoses. Previous papers have explored the history of these diagnostic concepts1, 2, 3, 4. Here we focus on Kraepelin's general principles of psychiatric nosology, which guided his classification of psychiatric disorders. The primary source texts are the eight editions of his textbook, published between 1883 and 19135, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16.

Textbooks served an important function when psychiatry emerged as an academic discipline in the second half of the 19th century17, 18, 19. In those early days of academic psychiatry, it was not clear how best to teach the subject and how to develop research programs17, 20. On a pragmatic level, textbooks provided a source of income and facilitated the teaching of psychiatry to medical students and assistant physicians. More importantly, textbooks allowed authors to articulate and disseminate their perspective of psychiatry in general, and psychiatric nosology in particular.

TEXTBOOKS BEFORE KRAEPELIN

Kraepelin referenced five textbooks that helped him write his own. Three are less relevant here: the fourth edition of Griesinger's textbook 21 , published posthumously in 1876; the textbook by Emminghaus 22 , published in 1878 when he was Kraepelin's medical school teacher, and a compendium by Weiss from 1881 23 . The other two are crucial for Kraepelin: the textbooks of Schüle (2nd edition in 1880) 24 and Krafft‐Ebing (2nd edition in 1883) 25 .

H. Schüle (1840‐1916) rose to prominence as asylum director (he turned down several offers to chair psychiatry departments) and as journal editor. He published three editions of his widely‐read textbook, known for rich, and sometimes convoluted, language 26 .

R.F. von Krafft‐Ebing (1840‐1902), trained with Schüle, subsequently chaired three psychiatry departments (Straßburg, Graz and Vienna), and was a prolific author of several books, including seven editions of his psychiatry textbook. The last edition was translated into English 27 .

Kraepelin acknowledged their influence when he introduced his own nosology of psychiatric disorders: “The sequence and delineation I have chosen … follows in its fundamental conception the systems constructed by Schüle and v. Krafft‐Ebing” 7 , p.239; 8, p.244.

All three authors – Schüle, Krafft‐Ebing and Kraepelin – included a chapter in their textbooks that summarized their general principles of psychiatric nosology.

Schüle proposed a complex and confusing psychiatric nosology 28 . He separated psychiatric disorders into psychic, organic and psychic‐organic types. He also distinguished cerebropsychoses (diffuse brain diseases that always affect the motor system) from psychoneuroses (diseases of the mind, not accompanied with brain changes). The resulting nosology was a hybrid of clinical description and etiological speculation, supported by neuropathological findings, if available.

Krafft‐Ebing was more practical. He acknowledged three types of nosologies (anatomical, etiological and clinical) and distinguished three major diagnostic groups: illnesses without pathological findings, illnesses with pathological findings, and neurodevelopmental disorders.

In the first three editions of his textbook, Kraepelin's introductory chapter The Classification of Psychoses followed the tradition of Schüle and Krafft‐Ebing. In the fourth edition, he broadened the title to The Nosology of Mental Disorders. We translated the eight editions of this chapter (which we will refer to as the “nosological chapter”), in order to study the evolution of his nosological principles (see Table 1 for details). In our view, Kraepelin developed his nosology in three phases: editions 1‐4, editions 5‐7, and edition 8.

Table 1.

The nosological chapter in Kraepelin's textbook

Kraepelin's place of work Leipzig Dorpat Heidelberg Munich
Year of publication 1883 1887 1889 1893 1896 1899 1904 1910
Edition (volume) 1 2 3 4 5 6 (2) 7 (2) 8 (2)
Die Klassifikation der Psychosen (pages) 187‐189 209‐212 235‐240
Die Einteilung der Seelenstörungen (pages) 239‐245 311‐320 1‐9 1‐12 1‐19

Second and third edition used the spelling “Classification” instead of “Klassifikation”. Fourth, fifth and sixth edition used the spelling “Eintheilung” instead of “Einteilung”.

PHASE 1: EDITIONS 1‐4

First edition

Kraepelin published the first edition of his textbook in 1883, at age 26. He had completed medical school in 1878 and psychiatric training with the anatomist‐psychiatrist B. von Gudden (1824‐1886) in 1882. In February 1883, he accepted his first psychiatric position, as first assistant to the department chairman P. Flechsig (1847‐1929) in Leipzig. After less than four months, Flechsig dismissed Kraepelin 29 .

In his Memoirs, Kraepelin wrote: “My situation in Leipzig was very uncertain. I tried to help myself out of my difficulties by accepting the offer to write a compendium of psychiatry” 30 , p.25.

The first edition of Kraepelin's textbook was indeed a Compendium, a concise compilation, primarily for students. The next three editions were a Short Textbook and the final four editions became the Textbook. Kraepelin dryly stated: “Nothing new is to be expected in a compendium, however, as far as my own experiences sufficed, I have strived for a degree of independence in the presentation” 5 , p. VIII.

The nosological chapter of the Compendium was brief. In three pages, Kraepelin reviewed anatomical, etiological and clinical‐symptomatic approaches to psychiatric classification. He considered pathological anatomy and etiology to be of limited value, and concluded that clinical presentations had to provide the basis of a preliminary classification. His assessment was in line with Krafft‐Ebing's one: “What it offers us are not illnesses, but merely symptom complexes” 5 , p.189.

The Compendium included the chapter The supporting sci‐ences and methods of psychiatric research, which was not contin‐ued in the subsequent editions of the textbook. Here Kraepelin described, in general terms, how neuroanatomy and experimen‐tal psychology can support the pathological study and clinical characterization of mental disorders. The influence of his two mentors – the anatomist B. von Gudden and the experimental psychologist W. Wundt (1832‐1920) – is unmistakable. Three years later, Kraepelin used much of this chapter for his inaugural lecture as the new psychiatry chair at Dorpat University30, 31.

Second and third edition

The next two editions of Kraepelin's textbook appeared during his chairmanship in Dorpat (now Tartu), Estonia (1886‐1890). He wrote in his Memoirs: “I was forced to publish a second edition of my little text‐book, which was completed in 1887; a third edition followed in 1889. The unfavorable circumstances of my clinical activity meant that I had to stay on the tracks already taken, without making any particular progress” 30 , p.43.

But this is not the full story. In fact, the nosological chapter in the second edition advanced a new vision for psychiatry: “Were we to be in possession of a thorough and exhaustive knowledge of all details in one of the three fields, namely pathological anatomy, etiology or symptomatology of insanity, not only would each of them allow a uniform and thorough division of the psychoses, but each of these three groups would also – this requirement is the cornerstone of all scientific research – coincide substantially with the other two 6 , p.211 (italics added).

This single final sentence captured the essence of Kraepelin's philosophy of science and remained largely unchanged in all subsequent editions. In the third edition, he elaborated on the “three fields of knowledge” and added a fourth set: “The cases of illness which occurred due to the same causes would in each case have to display the same phenomena and the same post‐mortem findings. It follows from this fundamental view that the clinical classification of mental disturbances has to be based on all three of the classification aids, to which one must add the experience gained from course, outcome and treatment” 7 , p.238.

This text in the second and third edition of the textbook anticipated a core concept of current nosology: any classification is preliminary but, in the end, validators will converge and psychiatric disorders will be defined at the level of the brain. It is remarkable that the text appears so early in Kraepelin's career, considering his own assessment of the limited opportunity for clinical research available to him in Dorpat 32 . Only after his move to Heidelberg in 1891 was he able to collect enough clinical material to develop and then support his new nosology.

Despite a lack of available data, Kraepelin made two important claims. First, psychiatric disorders in general, and psychoses in particular, are what philosophers call natural kinds: they reflect the structure of the natural world, being discovered rather than invented33, 34. He asserted that progress in psychiatric research is possible only if validators converge on natural kinds. This is in contrast to the view that psychiatry should be limited to studying the mind35, 36.

Second, the various methods of psychiatric research complement each other. Researchers might start from very different vantage points, but their results will converge.

These conjectures became a focus of criticism for a number of his detractors 37 . Kraepelin already anticipated such criticism of his strong naturalism in the third edition of the textbook: “The more the forms which have been gained from the different views correspond, the greater the certainty that the latter really represent particular disorders” 7 , p.238.

Kraepelin recognized that psychiatric disorders are not all the same. Some will likely have higher convergent validity than others. This allowed for a hierarchy within psychiatric nosology, with high convergent validity being the closest to the ideal of a natural kind. It also meant that his classification of psychoses may include diagnoses with only modest convergent validity.

Despite his strong philosophical claims, Kraepelin was a pragmatist when designing his classification scheme: “I have not constructed an actual classification and have contented myself with simply placing a number of empirically gained clinical pictures alongside each other” 6 , p.211.

There is considerable tension between Kraepelin's bold vision for a new psychiatric nosology and his traditional classification. The first sign that this tension will lead to a rupture is seen in his fourth edition.

Fourth edition

In 1891, Kraepelin left Dorpat to become chair of psychiatry in Heidelberg. The fourth edition of his textbook, published in 1893, represented a transition towards the more mature form of his psychiatric nosology, which he achieved during this chairmanship in Heidelberg (1891‐1903).

Much of the nosological chapter in the fourth edition is unchanged from the two previous ones. But Kraepelin added: “There simply exist no pathognomonic symptoms in the field of insanity; instead only the comprehensive picture of a case of illness, in its development from the beginning to the end, justifies inclusion with other similar observations” 8 , p.242.

And he advocated for a new method of painstaking, longitudinal studies: “Every psychiatrist knows that we sometimes encounter cases which in every respect, in the manner of emergence, all details of the symptoms, and further course, present a downright baffling similarity to each other. Such observations will form the natural starting point for our classification endeavors” 8 , p.243.

Here he anticipated the significant changes of the fifth edition: for the discovery of natural kinds in psychiatry, clinical observation needs to take the lead.

PHASE 2: EDITIONS 5‐7

Fifth edition

The Foreword of the fifth edition of the textbook, published in 1896, announced a significant change in Kraepelin's nosology: “In the development of this book, the current edition means the last decisive step from a symptomatic to a clinical perspective of insanity. All pure ‘clinical pictures' (Zustandsbilder) have thus disappeared from the nosology” 9 , p. V.

The change to a clinical perspective is a paradigm shift 38 in Kraepelin's nosology: the symptom complexes of the Compendium have been replaced by the concept of unitary diseases39, 40, 41.

Kraepelin elaborated on the clinical perspective in the Introduction. First, course and outcome have become primary validators: “As soon as we are able to predict, based on the current condition of a patient, the most likely further development of his affliction with a degree of certainty, then the first important step towards a scientific and practical command of the clinical picture has occurred” 9 , p.3.

Second, he asserted a causal structure for psychiatric disorders and the special role of clinical observation: “In the course of mental illness, the same causes also have to have the same effects everywhere. If we encounter, as we so often do, seeming deviations from this law, then, without a doubt, either the causes or the effects have not really been the same. Once we have managed to process clinical knowledge to such an extent that we can construct clinical groups with particular causes, symptoms and courses, it will become our task to penetrate the essence of individual pathological processes” 9 , pp.4‐5.

Finally, a new paragraph in the nosological chapter summarized his mature nosology: “The first task of the doctor at the sickbed is to form a judgment about the further course of the case of illness. The value of each diagnosis for the practical task of the psychiatrist is therefore essentially determined by how far in the future certain forecasts can be made. The same cause of illness will generally also determine the same course of the affliction, and from the clinical symptoms we have to be able to read the further fate of our patients in broad strokes” 9 , p.315.

Kraepelin used his new nosological framework to make significant changes to the classification of Schüle and Krafft‐Ebing. In fact, with this edition of the textbook and going forward, he no longer referred to them. Kraepelin even added a new subtitle to pages 317 and 319: Eigene Eintheilung (Own Division). He made three major changes.

First, he introduced an etiological dichotomy: acquired mental disorders versus mental disorders due to a pathological predisposition. The former are disorders of a previously normal brain, often with acute onset, and caused by exogenous poisons, brain injury or metabolic disorders; the latter are conditions that arise insidiously in an already abnormal brain.

Second, metabolic disorders are caused by an endogenous poison, a process he called autointoxication, and include endocrine disorders, general paresis and dementing processes. Kraepelin acknowledged that an endogenous poison is only “certain” for the first group, but considered such etiology “most likely” for the other two. The dementing processes are a prequel version of dementia praecox and already include three subtypes: dementia praecox (later termed hebephrenia), catatonia and dementia paranoides.

Third, while dementia paranoides was part of the dementing processes within the metabolic disorders (i.e., an acquired disorder), paranoia (Verrücktheit) was classified as a constitutional mental disturbance (i.e., due to a pathological predisposition).

These were remarkable changes in the classification of psychiatric disorders. Kraepelin made bold claims about distinct disease mechanisms and etiology, especially his speculation about autointoxication and the separation of dementia praecox from paranoia. He now needed to find more evidence from clinical studies to support his new nosologic vision.

Sixth edition

Kraepelin published the sixth edition in 1899, just three years after the previous one. The textbook had grown in size and was now published in two volumes. The nosological chapter was largely unchanged. But Kraepelin revised his classification scheme.

First, he abandoned the etiological dichotomy of acquired and predisposed disorders from the fifth edition. Second, metabolic disorders were split into thyroid conditions and his mature concept of dementia praecox, which now included hebephrenic, catatonic and paranoid subtypes. With this split, he acknowledged more clearly the different forms of autointoxication.

Third, Kraepelin introduced manic‐depressive insanity. Together with paranoia (Verrücktheit), he defined the new disorder as “an insanity where, in its formation, more and more, a pathological predisposition comes to the fore” 11 , p.7.

The sixth edition is of crucial importance for our understanding of the diagnoses of dementia praecox and manic‐depressive insanity, but it did not introduce any new general principles to his nosology.

Seventh edition

Kraepelin wrote the Foreword to the seventh edition while still in Heidelberg. However, when the two volumes were published, in 1903 and 1904, he was already the new chair of psychiatry in Munich.

The nosological chapter grew from 9 to 12 pages, but did not change substantially. The added new text included an important clarification: “In the course of the same disease process, it was obvious that completely divergent phenomena followed each other, even seeming to indicate the complete opposite. From this arose the clearly recognized necessity, especially by Kahlbaum, to distinguish between temporary clinical pictures and disease forms. A scientific diagnosis can never be content with the determination of a clinical picture, but instead has to shed light on the disease process belonging to a picture” 13 , p.4.

Kraepelin inherited the concept of disease form (Krankheitsform) from K. Kahlbaum (1828‐1899) and E. Hecker (1843‐1909), the latter of whom wrote in 1871: “There is an urgent need in psychiatry for a new nomenclature, which allows differentiation between the manifestations and the true clinical disease forms” 42 .

What Kraepelin started in the fifth edition had now matured into such a new psychiatric nosology. With his longitudinal observations of large patient samples, he was convinced that he had established true disease forms. The psychiatric researcher could now go beyond a purely descriptive classification and establish a framework for the scientific exploration of psychiatric disorders. Kraepelin built on this in the last edition of his textbook, and used the momentum to build the first research institute devoted to psychiatric disorders.

PHASE 3: EDITION 8

Eighth edition

The eighth and final full edition of the textbook was published in four volumes, between 1909 and 1915. Kraepelin finished writing the last volume in October 1914, three months into World War I 30 .

This edition included a wealth of new data (tables, figures, microphotographs of histological specimens) and extensive citations of other researchers. As a result, the nosology was more complex. For example, dementia praecox grew from three to eleven subtypes, as a result of which the dementia praecox chapter grew from 107 to 354 pages. Furthermore, a late‐onset subtype was carved out as a novel diagnostic category and given a new name: paraphrenia.

Similarly, the nosological chapter grew from 12 to 19 pages. The ambitious paragraph from the second edition was largely unchanged, but now covered all psychiatric disorders: “If we achieve the goal we have in mind, the recognition of the actual disease processes by means of our clinical descriptions, then the different delineation efforts, whether they occur from a pathological‐anatomical, etiological or a purely clinical standpoint, have to finally coincide with each other. I view this requirement as the keystone for the scientific research of mental disturbances” 15 , p.14.

It was this unbridled enthusiasm for scientific progress that allowed him to raise considerable funds, in the throes of World War I, for the German Psychiatric Research Institute, which open‐ed in April 1918 and later became the Max Planck Institute of Psychiatry43, 44, 45.

We view the eighth edition as the start of a third, humbler phase of Kraepelin's nosology. As he was approaching retirement in the early 1920s, he published a thoughtful critique of his own classification scheme, questioning the dichotomy of dementia praecox and manic‐depressive insanity 46 . But he never changed his mind about the task of psychiatric nosology and the way to make progress in psychiatric research 47 .

PRINCIPLES OF KRAEPELIN'S NOSOLOGY

We propose that Kraepelin's nosology evolved over thirty years, from the first (1883) to the eighth (1915) edition of his textbook.

His nosology began with the thesis that psychiatry, like other sciences, deals with natural phenomena. Scientific naturalism is the first principle of his nosology.

At the same time, Kraepelin did not believe that mental states can be reduced to neural states. But he was confident that the proper scientific methods will, in the end, reveal how nature creates abnormal mental states and behaviors. His strong belief in scientific progress is the second principle of his nosology.

Kraepelin was initially undecided about the best approach to make progress in psychiatry. But, after years of longitudinal studies, he concluded that clinical course and outcome were the most important validators in our search for the yet unknown natural disease units. His hierarchy of validators is the third principle of his nosology.

In Table 2 we provide a synopsis of his mature nosology (taken from the eighth edition of his textbook). Table 3 contains a glossary of his main nosological terms. Below we briefly review his three nosological principles.

Table 2.

Synopsis of Kraepelin's nosology (quotes from the 8th edition of his textbook)

“The task of psychiatric nosology is the delineation of individual disorders (Krankheitsformen) and their grouping according to unified viewpoints. The completion of the first task occurred previously almost exclusively according to the most prominent illness phenomena.” 15 , p.1

“Only the purposeful distinction between clinical pictures (Zustandsbilder) and disorders has made an adequate nosology possible. A diagnosis currently means the recognition of the underlying disease process (Krankheitsvorgang) of a particular type in the given clinical picture.” 15 , p.1

“We can only view a disease concept (Krankheitsbegriff) as final and clearly delineated once we are precisely informed about the causes, the phenomena, the course and outcome of the affliction, finally, also about the peculiar anatomical changes.” 15 , p.2

“The careful splitting of the forms into their smallest and seemingly insignificant variations… is thus the indispensable precursor for the obtainment of truly uniform disease pictures which correspond to nature (der Natur entsprechende Krankheitsbilder). Analysis is followed by synthesis… Only observation of the further course will clarify which of the numerous small deviations in the illness phenomena have a close relationship to the nature of the disease process, and based on this permit a recognition of its peculiarity.” 15 , p.11

“The method of conducting experiments – in the border region between two illnesses – with diagnostic features, until predictions have achieved the greatest possible degree of reliability, delivers practically useful disease concepts, of which we can assume that they are as close as possible to natural disease processes (natürliche Krankheitsvorgänge).” 15 , p.13

Table 3.

Glossary of Kraepelin's main nosological terms

Nominalist terms

Disorder (Krankheitsform): The basic unit of psychiatric nosology.

Clinical picture (Zustandsbild): The cross‐sectional description of psychopathology.

Disease concept (Krankheitsbegriff): Initially a nominalist definition of a psychiatric disorder. When final, it links causes with all clinical phenomena and explains course and outcome.

Disease process (Krankheitsvorgang): The evolution of clinical pictures over time. Only longitudinal observations can reveal this active process.

Realist terms

Disease picture which corresponds to nature (der Natur entsprechendes Krankheitsbild): A nosological entity that represents nature.

Natural disease process (natürlicher Krankheitsvorgang): A process occurring in nature, giving rise to clinical phenomena.

Kraepelin blends nominalist with realist views. The nominalist terms are descriptive and preliminary: they allow us to assign a diagnostic label. The realist terms capture what nature has revealed to us. For Kraepelin, psychiatric nosology progresses, through conjecture and refutation, from constructivism to realism. Kraepelin was not always consistent in the use of his terms 48 .

Scientific naturalism

Psychiatric disorders are natural kinds. They can be validated with the methods of natural science. In the end, all validators will converge on natural disease units. This principle – the first and most important one ‐ attracted many critics37, 48.

A. Hoche (1865‐1943), Kraepelin's main academic adversary in the early 20th century, rejected natural disease units and argued that there are only symptom complexes: “We are barking up the wrong tree with this unremitting search for definitive, pure syndromes of a physical kind” 49 , p.341.

A. Meyer (1866‐1950), who communicated many of Kraepelin's ideas to his American colleagues, remained critical: “Kraepe‐lin bends the facts of psychiatric observation to the concept of disease processes” 50 , p.274.

More recently, Weber and Engstrom examined Kraepelin's Zählkarten (diagnostic cards) and criticized his “positivist clinical research agenda”: “Condensing patient reports was already an interpretative process – a cognitive discrimination and scientific assessment impossible without preconceived categories which Kraepelin had acquired outside, before, or perhaps despite his clinical observations” 51 , p.379.

Many contemporary critics of Kraepelin have focused on scientific naturalism as an indefensible philosophical position35, 40, 52. In contrast, the psychiatrist‐turned‐philosopher K. Jaspers (1883‐1969) viewed Kraepelin's principle more favorably53, 54: “The idea of the disease‐entity is in truth an idea in Kant's sense of the word: the concept of an objective which one cannot reach since it is unending; but all the same it indicates the path for fruitful research and supplies a valid point of orientation for particular empirical investigations” 54 (italics added).

The view that natural disease units have heuristic value is relevant for Kraepelin's next nosological principle, his unshakeable trust that psychiatry will make progress.

Scientific progress

Kraepelin finished the introduction to the fifth edition of his textbook on an optimistic note: “Psychiatry is a young, still developing science, that must, against sharp opposition, gradually achieve the position it deserves according to its scientific and practical importance. There is no doubt that it will achieve this position – for it has at its disposal the same weapons which have served the other branches of medicine so well: clinical observation, the microscope and experimentation” 9 , pp.10‐11.

He kept the paragraph in all subsequent editions. Where did Kraepelin see the “sharp opposition” against psychiatry? In his 1918 monograph One Hundred Years of Psychiatry 55 , he describ‐ed how empirical research had overcome unscientific views of the human mind.

But Kraepelin was acutely aware that the scientific understanding of psychiatric conditions was uneven. For some clinical presentations there was a clear cause, e.g., an exogenous agent. For many other clinical syndromes, however, disease mechanism and etiology were unknown. Kraepelin viewed advances in scientific methods as the primary drivers of progress. For example, he cited the histological stains by Nissl and Weigert 55 , p.86 and the serological test by Wasserman 55 , p.90 for their impact on revealing new disease mechanisms.

His pragmatic approach to classification included the recognition that mental states cannot be reduced to neural states. In fact, Kraepelin embraced the psychophysical parallelism of his mentor W. Wundt 56 in the Compendium: “Only with the close connection of brain pathology and ‘psycho‐pathology', it is possible to discern the laws of the interrelationship between physical and mental disturbances and thus advance to a true, deeper understanding of the phenomena of insanity” 5 , p.3.

The juxtaposition of scientific naturalism and psychophysical parallelism in Kraepelin's nosology has puzzled many, including W. de Boor in his 1954 review of psychiatric nosologies: “It is astonishing to see how Kraepelin put the need for a dualistic methodology with regard to the somatological and psychopathological side of psychiatry programmatically at the beginning of his work, in order to largely neglect this principle in its nosology” 57 , p.20.

As Kraepelin developed his nosology, he recognized that psychiatric disorders are not created equal. As a consequence, he had to determine the method best suited to reveal the etiology and disease mechanism of each psychiatric disorder.

Hierarchy of validators

During Kraepelin's time, some psychiatric disorders had already been validated with biological measures. The neuropsychiatric syndrome in the end stage of syphilis, known as dementia paralytica or general paresis, may serve as the most compelling example 58 .

But, for the majority of psychiatric disorders, biological validation was not available to Kraepelin – and is still lacking today 59 . Kraepelin disagreed with T. Meynert (1833‐1892), the prominent anatomist and inaugural chair of psychiatry in Vienna, and his student C. Wernicke (1848‐1905), that neuroanatomy is the premier method in psychiatry: “The statement by Wernicke that all mental disorders with anatomical findings have approximately the same underlying disease process, can be refuted due to the advances of science” 15 , p.3.

Following Kahlbaum 60 , Kraepelin established disease course and outcome as the primary validators for psychiatric disorders. But it was not until the fifth edition of his textbook, after he and his assistants had collected longitudinal data in Heidelberg, that Kraepelin declared his hierarchy of validators. Once he had established it, he embraced prediction (of course and outcome) as the most important task of the psychiatrist. This hierarchy of validators might be Kraepelin's most impactful contribution to psychiatric nosology61, 62.

CONCLUSIONS

The principles of Kraepelin's nosology are still relevant today 39 . But we have not been able to hold them together in the way Krae‐pelin did.

On the one hand, current diagnostic systems (such as the DSM 63 and ICD 64 ) have implemented a simpler, nominalist view of mental illness 65 . In such nosologies we diagnose disorder, rather than disease, which suffices for clinical and forensic practice 66 . Disorder avoids premature assumptions about etiology and, by doing so, may reduce stigma and bias 67 . Psychiatric diagnoses also serve many functions in society, only some of which are scientific68, 69.

On the other hand, psychiatric research favors a realist view: causal models of disease allow for stronger hypothesis testing 70 . Accordingly, research communities have established hierarchies of validators that fit their research methods and inference testing62, 71.

The DSM‐5 Scientific Review Committee embraced a hierarchy of validators to guide the revision process 72 . But psychiatric clinicians and researchers assess validators differently and often speak a different language73, 74. As a result, the training of psychiatrists has lost its footing 75 . This is different from the start of the 20th century, when Kraepelin's nosology promised progress in the education of both clinicians and researchers76, 77. We are still searching for the best avenue to make progress in the nosology of psychiatric disorders 71 .

ACKNOWLEDGEMENT

Translations from the German were performed by A. Klee and reviewed by the authors.

REFERENCES

  • 1. Kendler KS. The development of Kraepelin's mature diagnostic concept of hebephrenia: a close reading of relevant texts of Hecker, Daraszkiewicz, and Kraepelin. Mol Psychiatry 2020;25:180‐93. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2. Kendler KS. The development of Kraepelin's mature diagnostic concept of catatonic dementia praecox: a close reading of relevant texts. Schizophr Bull 2020;46:471‐83. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3. Kendler KS. The development of Kraepelin's mature diagnostic concepts of paranoia (Die Verrücktheit) and paranoid dementia praecox (Dementia Paranoides): a close reading of his textbooks from 1887 to 1899. JAMA Psychiatry 2018;75:1280‐8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4. Trede K, Salvatore P, Baethge C et al. Manic‐depressive illness: evolution in Kraepelin's Textbook, 1883‐1926. Harv Rev Psychiatry 2005;13:155‐78. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5. Kraepelin E. Compendium der Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Abel, 1883. [Google Scholar]
  • 6. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein kurzes Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Zweite, gänzlich umgearbeitete Auflage. Leipzig: Abel, 1887. [Google Scholar]
  • 7. Psychiatrie Kraepelin E.. Ein kurzes Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Dritte, vielfach umgearbeitete Auflage. Leipzig: Abel, 1889. [Google Scholar]
  • 8. Psychiatrie Kraepelin E.. Ein kurzes Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Vierte, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. Leipzig: Abel, 1893. [Google Scholar]
  • 9. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Fünfte, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. Leipzig: Barth, 1896. [Google Scholar]
  • 10. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Sechste, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. I. Band. Allgemeine Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Barth, 1899. [Google Scholar]
  • 11. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte. Sechste, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. II. Band. Klinische Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Barth, 1899. [Google Scholar]
  • 12. Psychiatrie Kraepelin E.. Ein Lehrbuch für Studierende und Ärzte. Siebente, vielfach umgearbeitete Auflage. I. Band. Allgemeine Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Barth, 1903. [Google Scholar]
  • 13. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studierende und Ärzte. Siebente, vielfach umgearbeitete Auflage. II. Band. Klinische Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Barth, 1904. [Google Scholar]
  • 14. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studierende und Ärzte. Achte, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. I. Band. Allgemeine Psychiatrie. Leipzig: Barth, 1909. [Google Scholar]
  • 15. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studierende und Ärzte. Achte, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. II. Band. Klinische Psychiatrie. I. Teil. Leipzig: Barth, 1910. [Google Scholar]
  • 16. Kraepelin E. Psychiatrie. Ein Lehrbuch für Studierende und Ärzte. Achte, vollständig umgearbeitete Auflage. III. Band. Klinische Psychiatrie. II. Teil. Leipzig: Barth, 1913. [Google Scholar]
  • 17. Engstrom EJ. Clinical psychiatry in imperial Germany: a history of psychiatric practice. Ithaka: Cornell University Press, 2004. [Google Scholar]
  • 18. Wübben Y. Verrückte Sprache. Psychiater und Dichter in der Anstalt des 19. Jahrhunderts. Konstanz: Konstanz University Press, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  • 19. Wübben Y. Mikrotom der Klinik. Der Aufstieg des Lehrbuchs in der Psychiatrie (um 1890) In: Wübben Y, Zelle C. (eds). Krankheit schreiben. Aufzeichnungsverfahren in Medizin und Literatur. Göttingen: Wallstein, 2013:107‐133. [Google Scholar]
  • 20. Schmitt W. Das Modell der Naturwissenschaft in der Psychiatrie im Übergang vom 19. zum 20. Jahrhundert. Berichte der Wissenschaftsgeschichte 1983;8:89‐101. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 21. Griesinger W. Die Pathologie und Therapie der psychischen Krankheiten. 4. Auflage. Stuttgart: Krabbe, 1876. [Google Scholar]
  • 22. Emminghaus H. Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Zur Einführung in das Studium der Geistesstörungen. Leipzig: Vogel, 1878. [Google Scholar]
  • 23. Weiss J. Compendium der Psychiatrie. Für Praktische Ärzte und Studierende. Wien: Bermann & Altmann, 1881. [Google Scholar]
  • 24. Schüle H. Handbuch der Geisteskrankheiten. Zweite umgeänderte Auflage. Leipzig: Vogel, 1880. [Google Scholar]
  • 25. von Krafft‐Ebing R. Lehrbuch der Psychiatrie. Auf klinischer Krundlage für praktische Ärzte und Studierende. Zweite, theilweise umgearbeitete Auflage. Stuttgart: Enke, 1883. [Google Scholar]
  • 26. Jaspers K. Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Berlin: Springer, 1913. [Google Scholar]
  • 27. von Krafft‐Ebing R. Text‐book of insanity based on clinical observations for practitioners and students of medicine. Philadelphia: Davis, 1905. [Google Scholar]
  • 28. Beer MD. Psychosis: from mental disorder to disease concept. Hist Psychiatry 1995;6:177‐200. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 29. Steinberg H. Kraepelin in Leipzig. Bonn: Edition Das Narrenschiff im Psychiatrie‐Verlag, 2001. [Google Scholar]
  • 30. Kraepelin E. Memoirs. Berlin: Springer, 1987. [Google Scholar]
  • 31. Engstrom EJ, Weber MM. The directions of psychiatric research by Emil Kraepelin. 1887. Hist Psychiatry 2005;16:345‐64. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32. Steinberg H, Angermeyer MC. Emil Kraepelin's years at Dorpat as professor of psychiatry in nineteenth‐century Russia. Hist Psychiatry 2001;12:297‐327. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 33. Kincaid H, Sullivan JA. (eds). Classifying psychopathology: mental kinds and natural kinds. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2014. [Google Scholar]
  • 34. Tsou JY. Natural kinds, psychiatric classification and the history of the DSM. Hist Psychiatry 2016;27:406‐24. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35. Haslam N. Natural kinds in psychiatry: conceptually implausible, empirically questionable, and stigmatizing In: Kincaid H, Sullivan JA. (eds). Classifying psychopathology: mental kinds and natural kinds. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2014:11‐28. [Google Scholar]
  • 36. Zachar P. Psychiatric disorders are not natural kinds. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 2000;7:167‐82. [Google Scholar]
  • 37. Kendler KS, Engstrom EJ. Criticisms of Kraepelin's psychiatric nosology: 1896‐1927. Am J Psychiatry 2018;175:316‐26. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38. Kuhn TS. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962. [Google Scholar]
  • 39. Berrios GE, Hauser R. The early development of Kraepelin's ideas on classification: a conceptual history. Psychol Med 1988;18:813‐21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40. Hoff P. The Kraepelinian tradition. Dialogues Clin Neurosci 2015;17:31‐41. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41. Heckers S. Making progress in schizophrenia research. Schizophr Bull 2008;34:591‐4. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 42. Kraam A. On the origin of the clinical standpoint in psychiatry, Dr Ewald Hecker in Gorlitz. Hist Psychiatry 2004;15:345‐60. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 43. Hippius H, Möller H‐J, Müller G et al. The University Department of Psychiatry in Munich. From Kraepelin and his predecessors to molecular psychiatry. Heidelberg: Springer, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  • 44. Engstrom EJ, Burgmair W, Weber MM. Psychiatric governance, völkisch corporatism, and the German Research Institute of Psychiatry in Munich (1912‐26). Part 1. Hist Psychiatry 2016;27:38‐50. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45. Engstrom EJ, Burgmair W, Weber MM. Psychiatric governance, völkisch corporatism, and the German Research Institute of Psychiatry in Munich (1912‐26). Part 2. Hist Psychiatry 2016;27:137‐52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 46. Kraepelin E. Die Erscheinungsformen des Irreseins. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie 1920;62:1‐29. [Google Scholar]
  • 47. Kraepelin E. Die Erforschung psychischer Krankheitsformen. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie 1920;51:224‐46. [Google Scholar]
  • 48. Hoff P. Emil Kraepelin und die Psychiatrie als klinische Wissenschaft Ein Beitrag zum Selbstverständnis psychiatrischer Forschung. Berlin: Springer, 1994. [Google Scholar]
  • 49. Hoche A, Dening RG, Dening TR et al. The significance of symptom complexes in psychiatry. Hist Psychiatry 1991;2:329‐43. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50. Meyer A. The nature and conception of dementia praecox. J Abnorm Psychol 1910;5:274‐85. [Google Scholar]
  • 51. Weber MM, Engstrom EJ. Kraepelin's ‘diagnostic cards': the confluence of clinical research and preconceived categories. Hist Psychiatry 1997;8:375‐85. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52. Bentall RP. Madness explained. Psychosis and human nature. London: Penguin, 2005. [Google Scholar]
  • 53. Ghaemi SN. Nosologomania: DSM & Karl Jaspers' critique of Kraepelin. Philos Ethics Humanit Med 2009;4:10. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54. Walker C. Karl Jaspers on the disease entity: Kantian ideas and Weberian ideal types. Hist Psychiatry 2014;25:317‐34. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55. Kraepelin E. Hundert Jahre Psychiatrie. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte menschlicher Gesittung. Berlin: Springer, 1918. [Google Scholar]
  • 56. Engstrom EJ. On attitudes toward philosophy and psychology in German psychiatry, 1867‐1917 In: Kendler KS, Parnas J. (eds). Philosophical issues in psychiatry III: The nature and sources of historical change. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014:148‐164. [Google Scholar]
  • 57. de Boor W. Psychiatrische Systematik. Berlin: Springer, 1954. [Google Scholar]
  • 58. Ropper AH. Neurosyphilis. N Engl J Med 2019;381:1358‐63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59. Hyman SE. Neuroscience, genetics, and the future of psychiatric diagnosis. Psychopathology 2002;35:139‐44. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 60. Kahlbaum K. The clinico‐pathological perspective in psychopathology. 1878. Hist Psychiatry 2007;18:233‐45. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61. Robins E, Guze SB. Establishment of diagnostic validity in psychiatric illness: its application to schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry 1970;126:983‐7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 62. Kendler KS. Toward a scientific psychiatric nosology. Strengths and limitations. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1990;47:969‐73. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 63. American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 5th ed Arlington: American Psychiatric Association, 2013. [Google Scholar]
  • 64. World Health Organization . International classification of diseases, 11th revision. https://icd.who.int/en.
  • 65. Scadding JG. Essentialism and nominalism in medicine: logic of diagnosis in disease terminology. Lancet 1996;348:594‐6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 66. Jokstad A. The disorder of disorders in current nosology. Clin Exp Dent Res 2017;3:123‐5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 67. Sartorius N, Chiu H, Heok KE et al. Name change for schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull 2014;40:255‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 68. Kendell RE. The role of diagnosis in psychiatry. Oxford: Blackwell, 1975. [Google Scholar]
  • 69. Rosenberg CE. Contested boundaries: psychiatry, disease, and diagnosis. Perspect Biol Med 2006;49:407‐24. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 70. Kendler KS, Campbell J. Interventionist causal models in psychiatry: repositioning the mind‐body problem. Psychol Med 2009;39:881‐7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 71. Jablensky A. Psychiatric classifications: validity and utility. World Psychiatry 2016;15:26‐31. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 72. Kendler KS. A history of the DSM‐5 Scientific Review Committee. Psychol Med 2013;43:1793‐800. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 73. Lilienfeld SO, Treadway MT. Clashing diagnostic approaches: DSM‐ICD versus RDoC. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2016;12:435‐63. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 74. Luhrmann TM. Of two minds: the growing disorder in American psychiatry. New York: Knopf, 2001. [Google Scholar]
  • 75. de Leon J. Is psychiatry scientific? A letter to a 21st century psychiatry resident. Psychiatry Investig 2013;10:205‐17. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 76. Nissl F. Über die Entwicklung der Psychiatrie in den letzten 50 Jahren. Verhandlungen des Naturhistorisch‐Medizinischen Vereins zu Heidelberg 1904;8:510‐24. [Google Scholar]
  • 77. Burgmair W, Engstrom EJ, Weber MM. (eds). Kraepelin edition (9 vols). Munich: Belleville, 2000. ‐2019. [Google Scholar]

Articles from World Psychiatry are provided here courtesy of The World Psychiatric Association

RESOURCES