Skip to main content
UKPMC Funders Author Manuscripts logoLink to UKPMC Funders Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2024 Sep 6.
Published in final edited form as: Cogn Sci. 2023 Feb 1;47(2):e13255. doi: 10.1111/cogs.13255

From Puzzle to Progress: How Engaging With Neurodiversity Can Improve Cognitive Science

Marie A R Manalili a,b,, Amy Pearson c,, Justin Sulik d,†,, Louise Creechan e,, Mahmoud Elsherif f,, Inika Murkumbi g,, Flavio Azevedo h,§, Kathryn L Bonnen i,§, Judy S Kim j,§, Konrad Kording k,§, Julie J Lee l,§, Manifold Obscura m,§, Steven K Kapp n, Jan P Röer o,, Talia Morstead o,
PMCID: PMC7616419  EMSID: EMS198019  PMID: 36807910

Abstract

In cognitive science, there is a tacit norm that phenomena such as cultural variation or synaesthesia are worthy examples of cognitive diversity that contribute to a better understanding of cognition, but that other forms of cognitive diversity (e.g., autism, attention deficit hyperactivity disorder/ADHD, and dyslexia) are primarily interesting only as examples of deficit, dysfunction, or impairment. This status quo is dehumanizing and holds back much-needed research. In contrast, the neurodiversity paradigm argues that such experiences are not necessarily deficits but rather are natural reflections of biodiversity. Here, we propose that neurodiversity is an important topic for future research in cognitive science. We discuss why cognitive science has thus far failed to engage with neurodiversity, why this gap presents both ethical and scientific challenges for the field, and, crucially, why cognitive science will produce better theories of human cognition if the field engages with neurodiversity in the same way that it values other forms of cognitive diversity. Doing so will not only empower marginalized researchers but will also present an opportunity for cognitive science to benefit from the unique contributions of neurodivergent researchers and communities.

Keywords: Cognitive diversity, Neurodiversity, Norms, Social cognition, Epistemic injustice, Scientific discovery


Cognitive science recognises the importance of diversity (Barrett, 2020; Bender, 2019; Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010; Prather et al., 2022; Puthillam et al., 2022; Whitaker & Guest, 2020). It is puzzling, then, that neurodiversity has been absent from the discussion. After describing potential causes of this exclusion, we discuss its ethical and scientific consequences and propose how cognitive science can break new ground by embracing neurodiversity.

1. What is neurodiversity?

Neurodiversity1* refers to variation in human cognitive functioning (Walker, 2012, 2021), including takiwātanga*/autism*, ADHD*, dyslexia*, dyspraxia*, stuttering*, and plurality*. The neurodiversity paradigm* extends this view by recasting these experiences as differences (neurodivergence*) from common (neurotypical*) forms of cognitive functioning rather than as pathologized disorders (Asasumasu, 2015; Chapman, 2021; Dwyer, 2022; Elsherif et al., 2022; Walker, 2021). It provides an inclusive view of cognitive diversity, consolidating neurobiological differences with evolving sociocultural contexts of human experiences (Manalili, 2021).

The neurodiversity movement* applies this paradigm to political goals (e.g., resisting ableism* or promoting bodily autonomy; Arnold, 2017; Campbell, Constantino, & Simpson, 2019; Constantino, 2018; Walker, 2021). Here, however, we treat neurodiversity as a theoretical framework that makes heterogeneity a fundamental feature of processes such as executive function, attention, social cognition, communication, decision making, and motor control. As these are core topics in cognitive science, it is surprising that cognitive science has a scant engagement with the neurodiversity paradigm.

2. Why has cognitive science had poor engagement with neurodiversity?

Historical approaches misconceptualized neurodivergence as inherently disordered while framing neurotypical functioning as normative rather than common (Bertilsdottir-Rosqvist et al., 2022). This treated neurodivergence as scientifically interesting only when compared to assumed norms (Bertilsdottir-Rosqvist et al., 2022; Karmiloff-Smith, 2009) and cognitive theories of neurodivergence highlighted mechanisms of ‘impairment’ rather than manifestations of natural variation.

Some strands of cognitive science rest on similarly normative assumptions2: that research aims to discover rules or principles governing how the mind works, sometimes with the stronger assumption that these are optimal or rational. Such thinking may have evolutionary motivations, viewing biology as generating solutions to ecological problems that approximate optimal behavior (Körding, 2007; Ritter, Tehranchi, & Oury, 2019). Alternatively, it may derive from common frameworks, such as Bayesian modeling, which invoke rationality as a norm (Griffiths & Tenenbaum, 2006).

A normative frame commonly treats cognitive differences as variation on species-typical rules and principles due to culture or individual experience (Barrett, 2020) or as disordered breakdowns of those principles. However, neurodivergence is neither like cultural variation3 nor inherently disordered. Rather, it is a manifestation of biodiversity (Chapman, 2021).

When cognitive science frames neurodivergence as inherently disordered, it uses obsolete models of disability*. It would be unfortunate if this were the only frame of reference for areas of cognitive science less directly concerned with neurodiversity. Meanwhile, the humanities and social sciences have been applying the neurodiversity paradigm by rejecting oppressive medical models of disability in favor of social models*, which locate disability in the relationship between a person and their environment rather than being inherent to the person alone (Betts et al., in press; Chapman & Carel, 2022; Creechan, 2022; Kapp, 2013; Milton, 2012; Oliver, 1983, 2013; Stenning & Rosqvist, 2021).

3. Why is it wrong that cognitive science has not taken neurodiversity seriously?

It is unethical. Framing neurodivergence as “abnormal” is grounded in eugenics (Czech, 2018; Evans, 2014; Rutherford, 2022). Research maintaining this tradition dehumanizes neurodivergent people by treating them as objects—rather than agentive subjects—of research (Botha, 2021; Botha & Cage, 2022; Kapp, 2019). Theories built on deficit models are used to justify interventions that harm neurodivergent people (Yergeau, 2013), much like how conversion therapy harms gay and trans people by trying to “cure” them. Cognitive science should help prevent this by developing better theories of neurodivergence.

It is unjust. Conducting research about a marginalized group without their inclusion is epistemic injustice* (Byskov, 2021; Fricker, 2007). Neurodivergent people regularly face epistemic injustice (Catala, Faucher, & Poirier, 2021; Chapman & Carel, 2022). For example, even when tasks are modified to allow for cultural differences, similar calls for accommodation of neurodivergence are ignored (Hillary, 2020). Cognitive science should avoid injustice by empowering neurodivergent standpoints in research.

It is unscientific. For instance, although the theory of mind (ToM) is increasingly understood as comprising heterogeneous processes (Ahmed & Miller, 2011; Schaafsma, Pfaff, Spunt, & Adolphs, 2015; Warnell & Redcay, 2019), deficit-based accounts of neurodivergence talk in monolithic terms (e.g., describing autistic people as simply having a weaker ToM; Baron-Cohen, 2000). Claims about such “deficits” do not replicate reliably (Gernsbacher & Yergeau, 2019), further supporting the view that neurodiversity is more about differences than deficits (Astle & Fletcher-Watson, 2020). This view makes better sense of findings that communication failures are as much the fault of neurotypical people as they are of neurodivergent people (the double empathy problem*; Milton, 2012) as neurodivergent people understand each other even when neurotypicals do not (Crompton, Ropar, Evans-Williams, Flynn, & Fletcher-Watson, 2020). Cognitive science must develop more robust accounts of cognitive diversity that situate it in social contexts (e.g., second-person approaches; Schilbach et al., 2013).

4. Why will cognitive science be better if it seriously engages with neurodiversity?

Cognitive science can develop more accurate theories of cognitive diversity by working alongside neurodivergent communities, whereas sidelining of qualitative data from such communities has provided a false sense of objectivity. For instance, community-driven research on autism prioritizes different dimensions than research originating from neurotypical researchers. This has fed into newer quantitative studies and scale development (Garau et al., 2022; Wilson, 2022), though it is still in the minority. Going forward, such work should prioritize intersectionality (e.g., to combat Whiteness-centered stereotypes of autism; Botha, Dibb, & Frost, 2022). By analogy, trans healthcare has improved—not by doing more research into harmful conversion therapy or outdated conceptions of autogynephilia—but rather by doing different research that incorporates diverse trans perspectives (Serano, 2020).

Cognitive science can develop more general theories of cognitive diversity by broadening the range of diversity it considers worthy of attention. For instance, it recognizes the value of synaesthesia* in understanding cognitive diversity (Ward, 2019); neurodiversity should be no different. Kidd, Donnelly, and Christiansen (2018) highlight individual differences in language processing, yet limit their inquiry to neurotypicals. Future research should include non-deficit-framed language processing in neurodivergent people, including common interactions with attention or motor skills.

A weak way to include neurodiversity is in modeling previously unexplained variance (as might otherwise have been relegated to the random effects of a regression). This is weak because it is business as usual. It is like including autism status as a predictor to conclude that some people display worse ToM than others. It draws focus to how people vary along certain dimensions (such as ToM task scores) where neurotypicals are more central in the distribution and others more peripheral. This misconstrues neurotypicality as having an “average brain”4 and treats neurodivergence as defined by its deviation from that average. In any case, as many neurodivergent people do not have formal diagnoses, samples assumed to be neurotypical might not be.

There is a more radical way to embrace the message that neurodiversity is about difference, not deficit. It is analogous to the distinction in diversity metrics between “separation” (e.g., models of means and standard deviations) and “variety” (models of how different types are distributed in a group; Klein & Harrison, 2007). Whereas the weak strategy above treats diversity as separation, neurodiversity includes cognitive variety. This defocuses outcomes (e.g., variation in ToM performance) and instead highlights variety in cognitive mechanisms (e.g., heterogenous ways people tackle ToM tasks, whereby neurotypicality is “common” rather than “average”).5

In some areas, there is already a move in this direction. New research on brain-phenotype relations casts doubt on the validity of unitary cognitive models (Greene et al., 2022); in 3D perception, individuals vary in how they integrate different kinds of cues (Fulvio, Ji, & Rokers, 2021); a variety of mechanisms underlie ganglia circuit rhythms (Marder, Goeritz, & Otopalik, 2015); and some people engage linguistic processing when solving spatial problems, while others do not (Nedergaard, Wallentin, & Lupyan, 2022).

Converging on the point about “variety” from another angle: Even when there are evolutionary pressures on cognition and behavior, these are arguably pressures on the group rather than each individual. If there is no drive to optimize individual behavior, there is no single right way to learn, explore, manage attention, or make inferences. When intelligence is framed as a property of collectives (Falandays et al., 2022), true variety in cognitive processing and problem-solving—as endorsed by the neurodiversity paradigm—can contribute to group outcomes.

Neurodiversity thus presents an opportunity for cognitive science to build fundamentally new models of cognition. These could involve replacing single-agent reinforcement learning models with populations pursuing heterogenous strategies (related to neurodivergence by Dubois & Hauser, 2022; Yechiam, Arshavsky, Shamay-Tsoory, Yaniv, & Aharon, 2010). They could challenge the concept “theory of mind” (Williams, 2004), extending findings that ToM is not monolithic (Ahmed & Miller, 2011; Schaafsma et al., 2015; Warnell & Redcay, 2019) by showing how different neurotypes use different strategies in doing ToM tasks. Models relating group-level success to individual diversity could shift away from varying continuous parameters (Sulik, Bahrami, & Deroy, 2021a) toward studying distinct strategies (Devezer, Nardin, Baumgaertner, & Buzbas, 2019).

Finally, there are benefits for cognitive science qua science. The above points about ethics, justice, and science converge in the larger question—from Indigenous and feminist philosophy of science (Harding & Hintikka, 2003; Pownall et al., 2021; Smith, 2021)—of who gets to contribute to knowledge. A marginalized standpoint allows individuals to see what those in positions of privilege cannot, yielding unique epistemic advantages (Friesen & Goldstein, in press). Diversity is especially important for scientific discovery: identifying questions, framing problems, or uncovering insights (Sulik, Bahrami, & Deroy, 2021b). Neurodivergent people explore in different ways than neurotypicals (Dubois & Hauser, 2022; Yechiam et al., 2010), and exploration is part of discovery (Devezer et al., 2019). A variety of strategies—incorporating research led by both neurodivergent and neurotypical people—could lead to better long-term advances. Increased promotion of Open Science/Scholarship aims may also improve inclusion of neurodivergent researchers (Azevedo et al., 2022; Elsherif et al., 2022).

Without neurodiversity, cognitive science offers an impoverished account of cognitive diversity. It dehumanizes neurodivergent communities, and it is missing out on the invaluable contributions of neurodivergent researchers.

5. Recommendations

For cognitive science as an institution:

  1. Explicitly include neurodiversity in institutional diversity statements.

  2. Reject models or theories that frame neurodivergence as inherently disordered.

For research comparing neurodivergent and neurotypical populations:

  1. Critically test assumptions that neurodivergence necessarily involves deficits.

  2. Promote neurodivergent-led research and community involvement.

  3. Evaluate whether common tasks are fair measures of heterogeneous cognitive processes.

For research on topics commonly implicated in neurodivergence (e.g., executive function, ToM, decision making):

  1. Do not assume that samples are (or should be) neurotypical.

  2. Explore whether human cognition offers a variety of ways to approach superficially similar tasks.

Positionality statement

The meaning of neurodiversity may differ among authors of this article due to our various lived experiences, neurodivergence, ethnicity, gender, epistemological, ontological, and/or methodological perspectives. However, we are united in combating ableism and in believing that cognitive science cannot be truly representative until it empowers and engages with neurodivergent populations and in emphasizing the intersectional nature of neurodiversity. Social and institutional barriers—such as higher rates of misdiagnosis/misidentification of neurodivergence—disproportionately impact disabled people, people of color, and women (Davis, Solomon, & Belcher, 2022; Diemer, Gerstein, & Regester, 2022; Jack, 2011; Malone et al., 2022; Zener, 2019). Neurodivergence also intersects with queerness and variant gender identity (Walker, 2021). Some forms of neurodivergence are more stigmatized than others (Manalili, 2021).

Notes

1

Terms marked * are explained in the accompanying glossary (https://osf.io/hujzq). When the terms are multi-word phrases, they are marked in italics.

2

Cognitive science is not monolithic in its assumptions, though it is all the more puzzling that other strands of research—falling under the broad umbrella of cognitive science but not motivated by such normative assumptions—have ignored neurodiversity.

3

Though degrees and forms of acceptance of neurodiversity vary across cultures

4

Whatever that may mean.

5

Richters (2021) makes the stronger claim that an outcome-variable oriented (in our terms, “separation”) approach to individual differences assumes homogeneity of underlying psychological structures and processes. For a recent account of philosophical characterizations of cognitive diversity and how they map onto statistical models, see Ward (2022).

References

  1. Ahmed FS, Stephen Miller L. Executive function mechanisms of theory of mind. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders. 2011;41(5):667–678. doi: 10.1007/s10803-010-1087-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  2. Arnold L. A brief history of “Neurodiversity” as a concept and perhaps a movement. Autonomy, the Critical Journal of Interdisciplinary Autism Studies. 2017;1(5) [Google Scholar]
  3. Asasumasu K. [@sherlocksflataffect] PSA from the actual coiner of “neurodivergent.” Tumbler. 2015. Retrieved February 12 2023, from https://sherlocksflataffect.tumblr.com/post/121295972384/psa-from-the-actual-coiner-of-neurodivergent.
  4. Astle DE, Fletcher-Watson S. Beyond the core-deficit hypothesis in developmental disorders. Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2020;29(5):431–437. doi: 10.1177/0963721420925518. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Azevedo F, Middleton S, Phan JM, Kapp S, Gourdon-Kanhukamwe A, Iley B, Elsherif M, Shaw JJ. Navigating academia as neurodivergent researchers: Promoting Neurodiversity Within Open Scholarship. APS Observer. 2022;35 [Google Scholar]
  6. Baron-Cohen S. Theory of mind and autism: A review. International Review of Research in Mental Retardation. 2000;23:169–184. doi: 10.1016/S0074-7750(00)80010-5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  7. Barrett HC. Towards a cognitive science of the human: Cross-cultural approaches and their urgency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 2020;24(8):620–638. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2020.05.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  8. Bender A. The value of diversity in cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science. 2019;11(4):853–863. doi: 10.1111/tops.12464. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Bertilsdottir-Rosqvist H, Botha M, Hens K, O’Donoghue S, Pearson A, Stenning A. Being, knowing and doing: Importing theoretical toolboxes for Autism studies. Autism in adulthood. 2022 doi: 10.1089/aut.2022.0021. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Betts K, Creechan L, Cawkwell R, Finn-Kelcey I, Griffin CJ, Hagopian A, Hartley D, Manalili MAR, Murkumbi I, O’Donoghue S, Shanahan C, et al. The narratives of neurodiversity network: Exploring intimacy and expressive freedom in the time of COVID-19. Social Inclusion. doi: 10.17645/si.v11i1.5737. in press. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Botha M. Academic, activist, or advocate? Angry, entangled, and emerging: A critical reflection on autism knowledge production. Frontiers in Psychology. 2021;12:727542. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.727542. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  12. Botha M, Cage E. “Autism Research is in Crisis”: A mixed method study of researcher’s constructions of autistic people and autism research. 2022 July 14; doi: 10.31219/osf.io/w4389. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Botha M, Dibb B, Frost D. “Autism is me”: An investigation of how autistic individuals make sense of autism and stigma. Disability & Society. 2022;37(3):427–453. doi: 10.1080/09687599.2020.1822782. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  14. Byskov MF. What makes epistemic injustice an “injustice”? Journal of Social Philosophy. 2021;52(1):114–131. doi: 10.1111/josp.12348. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  15. Campbell P, Constantino C, Simpson S. Stammering pride and prejudice. Havant: J & R Press Limited; 2019. [Google Scholar]
  16. Catala A, Faucher L, Poirier P. Autism, epistemic injustice, and epistemic disablement: A relational account of epistemic agency. Synthese. 2021;199(3):9013–9039. doi: 10.1007/s11229-021-03192-7. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  17. Chapman R. Neurodiversity and the SOCIAL ECOLOGY OF MENTAL FUNCTIONS. Perspectives on Psychological Science. 2021;16(6):1360–1372. doi: 10.1177/1745691620959833. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Chapman R, Carel H. Neurodiversity, epistemic injustice, and the good human life. Journal of Social Philosophy. 2022;53(4):614–631. doi: 10.1111/josp.12456. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  19. Constantino CD. What can stutterers learn from the neurodiversity movement? Seminars in Speech and Language. 2018;39(4):382–396. doi: 10.1055/s-0038-1667166. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Creechan L. Killing the letter: Alternate literacies and orthographic distortions in Jude the Obscure. Journal of Victorian Culture. 2022;27(3):493–506. doi: 10.1093/jvcult/vcac034. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  21. Crompton CJ, Ropar D, Evans-Williams CV, Flynn EG, Fletcher-Watson S. Autistic peer-to-peer information transfer is highly effective. Autism. 2020;24(7):1704–1712. doi: 10.1177/1362361320919286. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Czech H. Hans Asperger, national socialism, and “race hygiene” in Nazi-era Vienna. Molecular Autism. 2018;9(29) doi: 10.1186/s13229-018-0208-6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  23. Davis A, Solomon M, Belcher H. Examination of race and autism intersectionality among African American/Black young adults. Autism in Adulthood. 2022;4(4):306–314. doi: 10.1089/aut.2021.0091. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Devezer B, Nardin LG, Baumgaertner B, Buzbas EO. Scientific discovery in a model-centric framework: Reproducibility, innovation, and epistemic diversity. PLoS One. 2019;14(5):e0216125. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0216125. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Diemer MC, Gerstein ED, Regester A. Autism presentation in female and Black populations: Examining the roles of identity, theory, and systemic inequalities. Autism. 2022;26(8):1931–1946. doi: 10.1177/13623613221113501. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Dubois M, Hauser TU. Value-free random exploration is linked to impulsivity. Nature Communications. 2022;13:4542. doi: 10.1038/s41467-022-31918-9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Dwyer P. The neurodiversity approach(es): What are they and what do they mean for researchers? Human Development. 2022;66(2):73–92. doi: 10.1159/000523723. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  28. Elsherif M, Middleton S, Phan JM, Azevedo F, Iley B, Grose-Hodge M, Tyler SL, Kapp SK, Gourdon-Kanhukamwe A, Grafton-Clarke D, Yeng SK, et al. Bridging neurodiversity and open scholarship: How shared values can guide best practices for research integrity, social justice, and principled education. MetaArXiv. 2022 June 20; doi: 10.31222/osf.io/k7a9p. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  29. Evans B. The Foundations of Autism: The Law Concerning Psychotic, Schizophrenic, and Autistic Children in 1950s and 1960s Britain. Bulletin of the History of Medicine. 2014;88(2):253. doi: 10.1353/bhm.2014.0033. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Falandays JB, Kaaronen RO, Moser CJ, Rorot W, Tan J, Varma V, William T, Youngblood M. All intelligence is collective intelligence. 2022 December 2; doi: 10.31234/osf.io/jhrp6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  31. Fricker M. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press; 2007. [Google Scholar]
  32. Friesen P, Goldstein J. Standpoint theory and the psy sciences: Can marginalization and critical engagement lead to an epistemic advantage? Hypatia. (in press) [Google Scholar]
  33. Fulvio JM, Ji M, Rokers B. Variations in visual sensitivity predict motion sickness in virtual reality. Entertainment Computing. 2021;38:100423. doi: 10.1016/j.entcom.2021.100423. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  34. Garau V, Fletcher-Watson S, Woods R. Development and Validation of a Self-Report Measure of Monotropism in Autism [Poster presentation]; Autistica Research Festival; 2022. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  35. Gernsbacher MA, Yergeau M. Empirical failures of the claim that autistic people lack a theory of mind. Archives of Scientific Psychology. 2019;7(1):102–118. doi: 10.1037/arc0000067. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Greene AS, Shen X, Noble S, Horien C, Hahn CA, Arora J, Tokoglu F, Spann MN, Carrión CI, Barron DS, Sanacora G, et al. Brain–phenotype models fail for individuals who defy sample stereotypes. Nature. 2022;609:109–118. doi: 10.1038/s41586-022-05118-w. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Griffiths TL, Tenenbaum JB. Optimal predictions in everyday cognition. Psychological Science. 2006;17(9):767–773. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01780.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Harding S, Hintikka MB. Discovering reality: Feminist perspectives on epistemology, metaphysics, methodology, and philosophy of science. New York: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 2003. [Google Scholar]
  39. Henrich J, Heine SJ, Norenzayan A. The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2010;33(2-3):61–83. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X0999152X. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. Hillary A. In: Neurodiversity studies: A new critical paradigm. Rosqvist H, Chown N, Stenning A, editors. NMew York: Routledge; 2020. Neurodiversity and cross-cultural communication; pp. 91–107. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  41. Jack J. “The extreme male brain?” Incrementum and the rhetorical gendering of autism. Disability Studies Quarterly. 2011;31(3):3. doi: 10.18061/dsq.v31i3.1672. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  42. Kapp SK. How social deficit models exacerbate the medical model: Autism as case in point. Autism Policy & Practice. 2019;2(1):3–28. [Google Scholar]
  43. Kapp SK. In: Empowering leadership: A systems change guide for autistic college students and those with other disabilities. Ashkenazy E, Latimer M, editors. Washington, DC: Autistic Self Advocacy Network; 2013. Interactions between theoretical models and practical stakeholders: The basis for an integrative, collaborative approach to disabilities; pp. 104–113. [Google Scholar]
  44. Karmiloff-Smith A. Nativism versus neuroconstructivism: Rethinking the study of developmental disorders. Developmental Psychology. 2009;45(1):56–63. doi: 10.1037/a0014506. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Kidd E, Donnelly S, Christiansen MH. Individual differences in language acquisition and processing. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 2018;22(2):154–169. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2017.11.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  46. Klein KJ, Harrison DA. On the diversity of diversity: Tidy logic, messier realities. Academy of Management Perspectives. 2007;21(4):26–33. doi: 10.5465/amp.2007.27895337. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  47. Kording K. Decision theory: What “should” the nervous system do? Science. 2007;318(5850):606–610. doi: 10.1126/science.1142998. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  48. Malone KM, Pearson JN, Palazzo KN, Manns LD, Rivera AQ, Mason Martin DL. The scholarly neglect of Black autistic adults in autism research. Autism in Adulthood. 2022;4(4):271–280. doi: 10.1089/aut.2021.0086. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Manalili MAR. Ableist ideologies stifle neurodiversity and hinder inclusive education. Ought: The Journal of Autistic Culture. 2021;3(1):6. [Google Scholar]
  50. Marder E, Goeritz ML, Otopalik AG. Robust circuit rhythms in small circuits arise from variable circuit components and mechanisms. Current Opinion in Neurobiology. 2015;31:156–163. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2014.10.012. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  51. Milton DEM. On the ontological status of autism: The ‘double empathy problem’. Disability & Society. 2012;27(6):883–887. doi: 10.1080/09687599.2012.710008. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  52. Nedergaard JSK, Wallentin M, Lupyan G. Verbal interference paradigms: A systematic review investigating the role of language in cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 2022 doi: 10.3758/s13423-022-02144-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  53. Oliver M. Social work with disabled people. Basingstoke: Macmillan; 1983. [Google Scholar]
  54. Oliver M. The social model of disability: Thirty years on. Disability & Society. 2013;28(7):1024–1026. doi: 10.1080/09687599.2013.818773. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  55. Pownall M, Talbot CV, Henschel A, Lautarescu A, Lloyd KE, Hartmann H, Darda KM, Tang KTY, Carmichael-Murphy P, Siegel JA. Navigating open science as early career feminist researchers. Psychology of Women Quarterly. 2021;45(4):526–539. doi: 10.1177/03616843211029255. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  56. Prather RW, Benitez VL, Brooks LK, Dancy CL, Dilworth-Bart J, Dutra NB, Faison OM, Figueroa M, Holden LR, Johnson C, Medrano J, et al. What can cognitive science do for people? Cognitive Science. 2022;46(6):e13167. doi: 10.1111/cogs.13167. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Puthillam A, Montilla Doble LJ, Delos Santos JI, Elsherif MM, Steltenpohl CN, Moreau D, Pownall M, Kapoor H. Guidelines to improve internationalization in psychological science. 2022 August 1; doi: 10.31234/osf.io/2u4h5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  58. Richters JE. Incredible utility: The lost causes and causal debris of psychological science. Basic and Applied Social Psychology. 2021;43(6):366–405. doi: 10.1080/01973533.2021.1979003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  59. Ritter FE, Tehranchi F, Oury JD. ACT-R: A cognitive architecture for modeling cognition. WIREs Cognitive Science. 2019;10(3):e1488. doi: 10.1002/wcs.1488. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Rutherford A. Control: The dark history and troubling present of eugenics. London: Hachette UK; 2022. [Google Scholar]
  61. Schaafsma SM, Pfaff DW, Spunt RP, Adolphs R. Deconstructing and reconstructing theory of mind. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 2015;19(2):65–72. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.11.007. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  62. Schilbach L, Timmermans B, Reddy V, Costall A, Bente G, Schlicht T, Vogeley K. Toward a second-person neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2013;36(4):393–414. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12000660. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  63. Serano J. Autogynephilia: A scientific review, feminist analysis, and alternative ‘embodiment fantasies’ model. The Sociological Review. 2020;68(4):763–778. doi: 10.1177/0038026120934690. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  64. Smith LT. Decolonizing methodologies: Research and indigenous peoples. London: Bloomsbury Publishing; 2021. [Google Scholar]
  65. Stenning A, Rosqvist HB. Neurodiversity studies: Mapping out possibilities of a new critical paradigm. Disability & Society. 2021;36(9):1532–1537. doi: 10.1080/09687599.2021.1919503. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  66. Sulik J, Bahrami B, Deroy O. Tolerance for failure unleashes the benefits of cognitive diversity in collective problem solving. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society. 2021a;43:826–832. https://escholarship.org/uc/item/2jv0w6kf . [Google Scholar]
  67. Sulik J, Bahrami B, Deroy O. The diversity gap: When diversity matters for knowledge. Perspectives on Psychological Science. 2021b;17(3) doi: 10.1177/17456916211006070. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  68. Walker N. In: Loud hands: Autistic people, speaking. Bascom J, editor. Washington, DC: The Autistic Press; 2012. Throw away the master’s tools: Liberating ourselves from the pathology paradigm; pp. 225–237. [Google Scholar]
  69. Walker N. Neuroqueer heresies: Notes on the neurodiversity paradigm, autistic empowerment, and postnormal possibilities. Ff e "fereeference " de the page raort Worth, TX: Autonomous Press; 2021. [Google Scholar]
  70. Ward J. Synaesthesia: A distinct entity that is an emergent feature of adaptive neurocognitive differences. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. 2019;374(1787):20180351. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2018.0351. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Ward ZB. Cognitive variation: The philosophical landscape. Philosophy Compass. 2022;17:e12882. doi: 10.1111/phc3.12882. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  72. Warnell KR, Redcay E. Minimal coherence among varied theory of mind measures in childhood and adulthood. Cognition. 2019;191:103997. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2019.06.009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  73. Whitaker K, Guest O. #bropenscience is broken science. The Psychologist. 2020;33:34–37. doi: 10.5281/zenodo.4099011. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  74. Williams E. Who really needs a ‘theory’ of mind? An interpretative phenomenological analysis of the autobiographical writings of ten high-functioning individuals with an autism spectrum disorder. Theory & Psychology. 2004;14(5):704–724. doi: 10.1177/0959354304046180. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  75. Wilson AC. Development and validation of the conversation questionnaire: A psychometric measure of communication challenges generated from the self-reports of autistic people. Autism & Developmental Language Impairments. 2022 doi: 10.1177/2396941522112328. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  76. Yechiam E, Arshavsky O, Shamay-Tsoory SG, Yaniv S, Aharon J. Adapted to explore: Reinforcement learning in autistic spectrum conditions. Brain and Cognition. 2010;72(2):317–324. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2009.10.005. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  77. Yergeau M. Clinically significant disturbance: On theorists who theorize theory of mind. Disability Studies Quarterly. 2013;33(4) [Google Scholar]
  78. Zener D. Journey to diagnosis for women with autism. Advances in Autism. 2019;5(1):2–13. doi: 10.1108/AIA-10-2018-0041. [DOI] [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES