Skip to main content
Sage Choice logoLink to Sage Choice
. 2020 Nov 20;9(1):24–37. doi: 10.1177/2167702620951553

Derationalizing Delusions

Vaughan Bell 1,2,, Nichola Raihani 3, Sam Wilkinson 4
PMCID: PMC7820571  PMID: 33552704

Abstract

Because of the traditional conceptualization of delusion as “irrational belief,” cognitive models of delusions largely focus on impairments to domain-general reasoning. Nevertheless, current rationality-impairment models do not account for the fact that (a) equivalently irrational beliefs can be induced through adaptive social cognitive processes, reflecting social integration rather than impairment; (b) delusions are overwhelmingly socially themed; and (c) delusions show a reduced sensitivity to social context both in terms of how they are shaped and how they are communicated. Consequently, we argue that models of delusions need to include alteration to coalitional cognition—processes involved in affiliation, group perception, and the strategic management of relationships. This approach has the advantage of better accounting for both content (social themes) and form (fixity) of delusion. It is also supported by the established role of mesolimbic dopamine in both delusions and social organization and the ongoing reconceptualization of belief as serving a social organizational function.

Keywords: delusion, psychosis, schizophrenia, belief


Delusions are defined as wildly improbable beliefs that are strongly held despite incontrovertible and obvious counterevidence and despite what almost everyone else believes (American Psychiatric Association, 2013). Although the precise definition of delusions has been much debated (Bell et al., 2003; Coltheart et al., 2011; David, 1999), they are considered the archetypal characteristic of “madness” and a central component in the diagnosis of psychotic disorders such as schizophrenia, delusional disorder, and schizoaffective disorder; they are also thought to emerge after a range of neurological disorders and alterations to the central nervous system (Gilleen & David, 2005).

Dominant historical and contemporary approaches have conceptualized delusions as pathological beliefs that are characterized by their irrationality (Bayne, 2017; Berrios, 1991; Bortolotti, 2005; Sakakibara, 2016). Consequently, current cognitive theories have largely focused on describing impairments to general-purpose inferential reasoning as the sole or central part of the explanatory model of delusions (Bell et al., 2006; Broyd et al., 2017; Feeney et al., 2017). Existing cognitive models have variously attempted to explain this through multifactorial impairments to probabilistic reasoning, perception, and affect (Garety & Freeman, 1999); a two-stage impairment to perception and reasoning (Langdon & Coltheart, 2000); aberrations in the use of prediction error in hierarchical inference mechanisms (Corlett et al., 2010); impairments to various aspects of metacognitive representation and control (Bronstein et al., 2019; Frith et al., 2000; Moritz & Woodward, 2006); or a synthesis of several of these approaches (e.g., Broyd et al., 2017; Miyazono & McKay, 2019).

However, we argue here that this characterization—that privileges the explanation of irrationality at the expense of explaining the social form of delusions—has hindered researchers’ understanding. Specifically, these approaches have focused on finding problems with the components of domain-general rationality and have largely disregarded the potential role of socio-cognitive dysfunction. This approach has seemed viable only by failing to consider that healthy and adaptive social processes can form and maintain delusion-like beliefs by ignoring the most striking phenomenological characteristics of delusions—that they are overwhelmingly socially and relationally themed—and by disregarding the fact that delusions show a reduced sensitivity to social context both in terms of how they are shaped and how they are communicated.

In line with recent work on the social organizational function of belief (Boyer et al., 2015; Echterhoff et al., 2009; Gelpi et al., 2019; Jost et al., 2008; Mercier & Sperber, 2011; Williams, 2020), we suggest that causal models of delusions need to include dysfunction to coalitional cognition—that is, social cognitive processes involved in social influence, affiliation, interaction with groups, and the management of relationships. This approach has the advantage of better accounting for aspects of both the form and content of delusional beliefs as well as better reflecting the known function of the mesolimbic dopamine system—which is involved in the formation and maintenance of delusions and the management of social hierarchy, dominance, and cooperation.

The Missing Irrationality in Delusions

On face value, it might be reasonably assumed that someone who is distressed and disabled by the belief that they are dead (Sahoo & Josephs, 2017), or that a camera has been implanted in their tooth and is taking pictures of their mind (Tanenberg-Karant et al., 1995), or that they are being poisoned by the CIA because they are Jesus (Mitchell & Vierkant, 1991) has a problem with rationality.

Although some approaches have suggested that delusions are solely explained by a problem with perception (Maher, 1999) or language (Hinzen et al., 2016), the majority of cognitive accounts draw on the long-established historical idea that delusions reflect an impairment to rationality (Berrios, 1991), which now forms one of the central tenets of explanation for delusional beliefs (see reviews in Bortolotti, 2010; Gold & Hohwy, 2000; Leeser & O’Donohue, 1999; Radden, 1985). This approach suggests that the presence of marked epistemic irrationality (i.e., beliefs that wildly deviate from the conclusions generated by normative principles of reasoning given available information), usually in addition to marked procedural rationality (i.e., inconsistency with clearly relevant and available preexisting beliefs and mental states given the application of reliable forms of inference; Bermúdez, 2001), implies problems with the cognitive processes underlying the capacity to reason pragmatically (Gerrans, 2001). Note that the standard of comparison is normative because cognitive biases are considered to be an integral part of healthy, adaptive cognitive functioning (Bayne, 2017; Johnson et al., 2013). Consequently, this has motivated researchers to look for differences in performance on reasoning tasks that are assumed to reflect underlying impairments in domain-general rationality (Garety, 1991).

Initial assumptions that delusional beliefs reflect an impairment in syllogistic (i.e., deductive) reasoning (Von Domarus, 1944) were discredited because numerous studies failed to find any generalized difficulty in syllogistic reasoning associated with delusional beliefs when compared with IQ-matched control participants (Mujica-Parodi et al., 2000). Indeed, this is clearly apparent during conversation with someone with delusions. All things being equal, they can generate normative conclusions about matters not relating to their delusional beliefs and come to seemingly atypical conclusions only when reasoning relates to the specific focus of the delusions. Therefore, most people with delusions appear not to have a generalized problem with rationality but a circumscribed irrationality by which conclusions are irrational solely in relation to the delusional content (Gold & Hohwy, 2000).

It could be argued that one potential source of impairment to rationality might arise from general cognitive difficulties that are common in patients diagnosed with psychotic disorders (Bora et al., 2010). However, there is just a weak correlation between general cognitive performance and the presence of positive symptoms in patients—of which delusions are a central feature (Ventura et al., 2013). There is also a significant effect of referral bias in that community epidemiological studies show much smaller cognitive differences between people with and without psychosis than clinical studies (Mollon et al., 2016). Furthermore, cognitive impairment is neither necessary nor sufficient for the production of delusions because the vast majority of patients with even quite severe cognitive difficulties, for example after traumatic brain injury, do not develop delusions as a consequence and indeed do not show rates that markedly differ from the general population (Ponsford et al., 2018). Clearly, some delusions arise after brain injury, dementia, or alterations to the nervous system, for example, but there are no reliable instances of cognitive impairment independent of etiology that reliably raise the risk of developing delusions.

One potential explanation for this is that delusions involve a more subtle type of cognitive alteration that is detectable but must interact with other difficulties, such as perceptual dysfunction, emotional dysregulation, traumatic life events, and maladaptive coping, to form and maintain delusional belief (e.g. Garety et al., 2001; Langdon & Coltheart, 2000).

Consequently, various cognitive biases have been proposed as important in the development or maintenance of delusions. The most studied has been the “jumping to conclusions” probabilistic reasoning bias, most commonly tested using the beads task (Garety, 1991; Huq, Garety, & Hemsley, 1988). One recent large-scale study of people with first-episode psychosis reported that the jumping to conclusions bias was reliably associated with psychosis (Tripoli et al., 2020), although this was entirely accounted for by general cognitive difficulties and not the presence of psychotic symptoms per se. Recent meta-analyses (Dudley et al., 2016; So et al., 2016) reported that patients with current delusions drew fewer beads than patients without delusion, but this effect when quantified was 0.6 fewer beads, and 40% to 50% of patients showed no evidence of the bias whatsoever. Other cognitive biases associated with delusions show a similar pattern. A recent meta-analysis (McLean et al., 2017) of a range of cognitive biases in delusions, including jumping to conclusions bias, bias against disconfirmatory evidence, bias against confirmatory evidence, and liberal acceptance bias, showed small to moderate effect sizes when comparing patients with and without schizophrenia but did not include control participants for general cognitive function.

We note here that research motivated by the search for evidence of problems in domain-general rationality has had some success, although the effects are relatively small in light of the striking deviations from normative conclusions about reality represented by the presence of delusions, suggesting an ongoing “validity gap” in the rationality-impairment approach.

Delusion-Like Beliefs Arise From Unimpaired, Adaptive Social Processes

In rationality-impairment approaches, the irrationality of beliefs is typically evaluated in terms of normative conclusions about the natural world (i.e., in terms of epistemic irrationality) and not in terms of the role the belief plays in the social environment. For example, it may be “irrational,” given the natural world, for people to believe their thoughts control the weather, but it may be socially beneficial given that, if this belief is strongly held by their social group, rejecting it may lead to hostility and ostracism with potentially far greater negative consequences (Edis & Boudry, 2019; Rauwolf et al., 2015), which suggests the belief may be “functionally rational” (Bayne, 2017).

Indeed, there are many examples of how strongly held, affectively loaded, epistemically irrational beliefs can be reliably formed through social influence—demonstrating that adaptive social processes, rather than individual impairments in rationality, are sufficient to form delusion-like beliefs in cognitively intact people. We document several examples below.

The sudden spread of intense delusion-like ideas through the population are well documented and frequently occur over time and across cultures and have variously been called “mass delusion” and “social delusion” and have been studied alongside “mass hysteria” (Bartholomew, 2001). Episodes of socially transmitted delusion-like belief outbreaks have included beliefs in a “phantom anaesthetist” who was believed to be prowling the community and “gassing” members of the public (Bartholomew & Victor, 2004), a “windshield pitting epidemic” attributed to nonexistent “H-bomb tests” (Medalia & Larsen, 1958), frequent waves of beliefs about malicious penis-stealing episodes (Dan et al., 2017), the kidnapping of children to use their decapitated heads in the foundations of new buildings (Barnes, 1993), and an invasion of foreign airships before capable technology was available (Holman, 2016), to name but a few. Note that these are distinct from conspiracy theories in that rather than being “explanations for important events that involve secret plots by powerful and malevolent groups” (Douglas et al., 2017, p. 58), they typically involve new and idiosyncratic phenomena that reflect a direct and personal risk to the individual believer. These episodes of mass social delusion typically include thousands of people and motivate urgent behavior designed to protect the individual and community, but they resolve quickly, usually within weeks, as the community interest wanes (Bartholomew, 2001).

Intense delusion-like beliefs that greatly deviate from both consensual reality and orthodoxy have been reported in members of small, isolated religious groups. These groups can be cults, which can involve coercive control (Rodríguez-Carballeira et al., 2015), but also more benign groups in which membership is through enthusiastic and voluntary participation (Dawson, 1996). However, common to both is intense within-group contact and the reduction of extragroup social ties (Coates, 2012). Examples of firmly and intensely held, improbable, behavior-shaping beliefs in members of noncoercive isolated religious groups include that mass suicide (eventually carried out) would allow group members to meet an alien space ship accompanying the Hale-Bopp comet, which would cause them to ascend to “The Evolutionary Level Above Human” (Robinson, 1997); that a forthcoming nuclear war would wipe out a third of the world’s population and the group members would be subsequently gifted miraculous powers of healing to save humanity (Melton, 1985); that God would appear on a specific cable TV channel to announce his presence to the world (Prather, 1999); and that group members were under attack from electromagnetic wave warfare designed to disrupt their spiritual work, which could be deflected by wrapping themselves in white cloth (Murguia, 2011).

The transfer of delusional beliefs from one person to others has been variously classified as folie à deux, induced delusional disorder, and shared psychotic disorder (Shimizu et al., 2007). This can take several forms, but the type most relevant here is one in which a secondary person who is not otherwise experiencing psychosis takes on the delusional beliefs of the first person who has psychosis. It is now recognized that many secondary subjects of induced delusional disorder may have risk factors for psychotic disorder—genetic risk factors because relatedness is essential (Arnone et al., 2006). However, there are also clear cases of induced delusional disorder in secondaries who do not share relevant risk factors, including taking on the delusion of a primary with dementia that the house was being continually burgled by neighbors who would replace the items shortly after stealing them (Brooks, 1987); a husband, two sons, sister-in-law, and nephew taking on a delusion that the neighbors were using technology to persecute them through the ceiling (Dippel et al., 1991); and parents taking on the delusion resulting from amphetamine psychosis of the son that he was being persecuted, his walls were bugged, and he could detect which bricks had listening devices in them because of “their different look” (Hill et al., 2001). Relevant nonbiological risk factors for induced delusions include social isolation (José & Mary, 1995), the length and closeness of the relationship (Arnone et al., 2006), and enmeshed and dependent relationship style (Mentjox et al., 1993).

Experimentally, delusional beliefs have been modeled, albeit transiently, in the lab using hypnosis that involves a combination of suggestion and active engagement of highly suggestible individuals (Cox & Barnier, 2010). More prosaically, although orthodox religious beliefs are complex and include dogma relating to social organization as well as reality, they have a poor historical track record of reflecting accurate models of the natural world but have been successfully transmitted to large numbers of people (Edgell, 2012).

These examples demonstrate that healthy and adaptive social processes have a powerful role in belief formation—to the point that social influence can form and maintain beliefs that are as epistemically irrational, affectively loaded, and strongly held as delusional beliefs. However, that these beliefs wane or modify as the social context changes and reflect successful social integration in context of the community or microcommunity in which they originate rather than social disability suggests they reflect adaptive rather than impaired functioning. Therefore, these examples also demonstrate that privileging irrationality is unlikely to be an effective explanatory strategy for models of delusional belief because it will not successfully account for their maladaptive nature.

The Majority of Delusions Have Social Themes

Delusions have a relatively select number of themes, with social themes being overwhelmingly the most common presentation. Despite this clear social phenomenology, the majority of cognitive models of delusions do not consider it a focus for, or a constraint on, explanation.

Common delusional themes include persecution, reference, guilt or sin, grandiosity, erotomania, jealousy, somatic changes, religion, mind reading, external control, thought broadcast, insertion, and withdrawal (Gutiérrez-Lobos et al., 2001; Paolini et al., 2016; Peralta & Cuesta, 2016). Delusions of persecution, reference, jealousy, and erotomania are social because, by definition, they implicate social actors. Other delusion types are not by definition socially themed but commonly present as social. Grandiose delusions often involve beliefs about having an elevated social position, important social role, or link to important people (Suhail & Cochrane, 2002). Delusions of guilt or sin typically involve concerns about contravening the expectations of others, including spiritual beings (Stompe et al., 1999). Religious delusions often involve a spiritual identity determining relationships with others or a closeness or relationship with spiritual figures (Rieben et al., 2013). Delusions of external control, thought insertion, broadcast, and withdrawal typically involve concerns about the social permeability of the private mental experience (Schimansky et al., 2012) and being controlled by others (Hirjak et al., 2013). Delusions as a whole also commonly include beliefs about illusory social agents that seem present across themes (Bell et al., 2017).

Epidemiologically, persecutory delusions are by far the most common presentation in nonaffective psychosis (de Portugal et al., 2013; Ellersgaard et al., 2014), psychosis in Parkinson’s disease (Warren et al., 2018), and drug-induced psychoses (Voce et al., 2019). In the affective psychoses, grandiose delusions or delusions of guilt or shame may be more common depending on mood state (Picardi et al., 2018). Indeed, one of the notable attributes of delusions as a whole is that the majority involve key themes likely to reflect adaptive social processes shaped by evolution—for example, danger from others, social position, social stigma, and social affiliation (Bortolotti, 2015; McKay & Dennett, 2009).

Despite this, the majority of cognitive models do not attempt to address why delusions are typically socially themed rather than not socially themed. Several cognitive models exclude specific alterations to social cognition and do not address the social theming of delusions (Bronstein et al., 2019; Broyd et al., 2017; Feeney et al., 2017; Frith et al., 2000); several suggest that content, including social content, is determined by anomalous experience of which only specific examples are given (e.g., reduced autonomic responding to familiar people in Capgras delusion), which cannot account for the prevalence of social themes in delusions more generally (Langdon & Coltheart, 2000; McKay, 2012); whereas others restrict themselves to a specific social theme, typically persecutory delusions (Bentall et al., 2001; Freeman, 2016), and so cannot explain why delusions per se have social rather than nonsocial themes.

It is therefore clear that current cognitive models of delusional belief do not attempt to, or cannot, account for the most common thematic content of delusional beliefs.

Delusions as Dysfunction in Coalitional Cognition

Given (a) the modest findings from studies searching for domain-general impairments to rationality, (b) the demonstrable role of adaptive social processes in the formation of delusion-like irrational beliefs in healthy individuals, (c) the social themes of the vast majority of delusions, and (d) the reduced sensitivity of delusions to social context, we suggest that social cognitive processes are an important candidate for inclusion in any adequate cognitive model of delusions. This raises the question of how to conceptualize the role of social cognition in such models.

One potential objection to the inclusion of social cognitive mechanisms in models of delusions is that traditional measures of social cognition barely predict the presence of reality distortion symptoms of psychosis, tending to predict negative symptoms more strongly (Ventura et al., 2013). However, we agree with previous authors that the most widely used measures of social cognition do not capture the full range of relevant cognitive processes needed to explain disturbed social experience in psychopathology (Gallagher & Varga, 2015; Schilbach, 2016; Yager & Ehmann, 2006). Indeed, traditional measures tend to require individual testing of participants while exposing them to short instances of static social information that largely quantify individualized mechanisms of social information processing (M. F. Green et al., 2015) rather than the management of dynamic, evolving, multiagent social situations (Bell et al., 2017; Schilbach, 2016).

Instead, we suggest that processes involved in social influence, affiliation, and strategic social behavior are likely to be key in understanding delusions. Cognitive processes focused on garnering support from other individuals, organizing and maintaining alliances, and perceiving social status in groups have been described as “coalitional psychology”—something that is highly likely to be part of evolved cognitive system adapted to life in complex social groups (Boyer et al., 2015; Tooby & Cosmides, 2010). Evidence for the evolutionary basis of this system stems from the fact that life in complex social groups favors the evolution of specialized and sophisticated socio-cognitive abilities (Dunbar & Shultz, 2017) and that the ability to form and maintain coalitional alliances is present in multiple species and throughout hominid evolutionary history (Kappeler & van Schaik, 2002).

We cite coalitional cognition as important in delusions for several reasons. First, beliefs are now increasingly recognized as strongly or primarily social in function, which implies that delusions need to be understood in terms of the same social mechanisms. Recent work in social cognition has suggested that conscious access to metacognitive judgments such as beliefs exists largely, if not primarily, to facilitate social interaction and group coordination (Tomasello, 2009). Frith (2012b) described how complex social coordination requires explicit communication of metacognitive judgments that allows for group refinement of knowledge and joint action. Likewise, Mercier and Sperber (2011) argued that the primary function of reasoning is not for the refinement of personal knowledge, given the extensive evidence for how ineffective it is for this purpose, but for argumentation, social communication, and persuasion. Here, beliefs, reasons, and knowledge primarily are generated to communicate what are usually intuitive inferences for group refinement and social coordination. Cushman (2019) argued that the post hoc generation of reasons may not be efficient in itself for solving problems, but it allows people to apply the same reflective process to themselves and to others, again facilitating social coordination for problem-solving. Williams (2020) suggested that understanding the social function of belief better accounts for both its function and phenomenology but also better explains phenomena such as confabulation, positive illusions, and identity-protective cognition.

Second, the social themes of delusions are also primarily coalitional in nature and involve concerns about persecution by others, social status, social affiliation, or social transgressions (e.g., McKay & Dennett, 2009; Raihani & Bell, 2019). In addition, delusions frequently involve belief in the existence and actions of illusory social agents that impinge on the life of the believer (Bell et al., 2017). Indeed, we note that delusions are frequently delusional precisely because they cite the actions of coalitions that do not exist or cannot perform the actions believed of them. Moreover, observational studies have reported that delusions typically involve coalitional characteristics that go often beyond the simple theme of the delusion itself. Individuals with persecutory delusions rank their perceived persecutors as having higher social rank than them (C. Green et al., 2006; Paget & Ellett, 2014) and frequently involve a perception of being targeted by a specific group (Raihani & Bell, 2019). Erotomanic delusions frequently involve the belief that a person of higher social status is in love with the believer (Brüne, 2001), whereas delusions of jealousy typically relate to perceived infidelity and the resultant humiliation (Seeman, 2016). Grandiose delusions involve a belief that the individual has risen in social status and has a special mission or message for the world (Knowles et al., 2011). Experimental studies of psychosis and the psychosis spectrum that have examined coalitional perception and behavior have reported alterations in the social perception of groups as paranoia increases (Greenburgh et al., 2019), an impact of in-group/out-group status on attribution of harmful intent in paranoia (Saalfeld et al., 2018), alterations to the social representation of others (Raihani & Bell, 2017), and a range of alterations to cooperative behavior and emotional reactions to differences in cooperative behavior in others accompanying delusions (Ellett et al., 2013; Fett et al., 2012, 2016; Gromann et al., 2013; Savulich et al., 2018).

Third, by definition, delusions are both irrational and show reduced sensitivity to social context. This latter characteristic suggests they may involve a dysfunction in the ability to have beliefs moderated and refined through social interaction and reflect problems with the strategic presentation of beliefs given social context. The criterion that delusions are not beliefs “ordinarily accepted by other members of the person’s culture or subculture” has been maligned as a pragmatic decision to avoid the uncomfortable situation of diagnosing religious or spiritual beliefs as delusional given that many such beliefs would otherwise fulfill the irrationality criteria (Pierre, 2001; Ross & McKay, 2017). But although religious beliefs may be epistemically irrational when judged against how well they explain the natural world, they may still be highly socially beneficial. In contrast, delusions are typically epistemically irrational beliefs that, in addition, are socially maladaptive, indicated by the fact they form outside of a shared community of belief and are resistant to social context, which leads to high levels of social disability and ostracism. Social context effects are not only about the influence of the social milieu on the content and conviction in the belief but also include being able to strategically communicate the belief given the social environment (Fransen et al., 2015). For example, one potential solution to having a belief that leads to social sanction is to keep it to oneself, deny it, or reveal it only to people who are unlikely to sanction the believer (Edis & Boudry, 2019). Although not well studied, this is an ability people with delusions seem to progressively lose as delusions becomes more intense, as suggested by greater difficulties in using social context for pragmatic communication with increasing severity (Colle et al., 2013).

Finally, a coalitional approach to delusions is consistent with the known role of the mesolimbic dopamine system, which has been strongly implicated in both delusions (Howes & Kapur, 2009) and coalitional cognition (O’Connell & Hofmann, 2011; Salamone & Correa, 2012; Trainor, 2011). Increased dopamine turnover in the mesolimbic dopamine system is present in in patients with delusions (Winton-Brown et al., 2014) whereas increasing dopamine turnover by the use of stimulant drugs causes delusions after chronic use (Voce et al., 2019). These same drugs also increase social motivation and sensitivity to emotional expression in nonpsychotic individuals (Wardle & de Wit, 2012; Wardle et al., 2012). Conversely, antagonism of D2 dopamine receptors in the mesolimbic pathway by antipsychotic medication reduces the intensity of delusional beliefs (Kaar et al., 2019), reduces social engagement, and induces indifference (Gerlach & Larsen, 1999; Moritz et al., 2013). Furthermore, a wealth of evidence from human and animal studies suggests that the mesolimbic dopamine system mediates various aspects of coalitional cognition, including perception and response to social hierarchy, social defeat, and social dominance (Báez-Mendoza & Schultz, 2013; Ghosal et al., 2019; Krach et al., 2010; O’Connell & Hofmann, 2011). Conversely, there is now increasing evidence that the risk of psychosis is raised by coalitional stress given that social disadvantage and poor social integration (Jongsma et al., 2020) lead to long-term changes in the mesolimbic dopamine pathway (Howes & Murray, 2014; Selten et al., 2013), which suggests a causal pathway that includes coalitional components across levels.

Thus, converging evidence from multiple sources, including observational and experimental studies of delusion, models of normal belief, the social responsiveness of delusional beliefs, and the functions of mesolimbic dopamine, suggests that coalitional cognition is likely an important but currently overlooked component of explanatory models of delusional belief.

Hypotheses Regarding the Role of Coalitional Cognition in Delusion Formation

In this article, we hypothesize two roles for coalitional cognition in belief formation: (a) underpinning the social processes of belief formation and (b) contributing to the coalitional content of belief. Consequently, we hypothesize that dysfunction to coalitional cognition contributes to two aspects of delusions: first, by affecting the form of delusions—for example, their resistance to social influence—and second, by affecting the content of delusions—resulting in their frequent social themes.

Note that we are hypothesizing that dysfunction to coalitional cognition may play a role in delusions regardless of their theme, not solely socially themed ones, because social belief formation processes apply widely and not solely to socially themed beliefs. However, because coalitional cognition impairment would typically also lead to a misperception of the social environment, socially themed delusions would be the most common type—in line with the results from epidemiological studies.

Consequently, we describe some specific hypotheses regarding dysfunction to coalitional processes that we suggest are candidates for inclusion in delusion-formation mechanisms.

As described above, one common feature of delusions is a reduced ability to strategically communicate (or strategically hide) the belief in social situations. Collective decision-making is common in social species and involves the ability to judge other group members’ information, integrate social markers of reliability and influence (e.g., status), and communicate one’s own decision and confidence given the social context (Bang & Frith, 2017). For humans, one important consideration may be the strategic balancing of personal and group goals, particularly when they are in conflict (Bazazi et al., 2019). We hypothesize that people with delusions will show selective difficulties with the strategic communication of beliefs during group decision-making when the focus relates to delusion content even when it is in their interest to do so. Recently developed paradigms to test these processes seem well suited to this hypothesis, and we suggest that people with psychosis will show delusion-related difficulties communicating beliefs and belief conviction for group decision-making (Bang et al., 2017) and in strategic communication in which differences between felt confidence and communicated confidence are key to task completion (Bang et al., 2020).

With regard to delusion content, cognitive models of persecutory delusions frequently conceptualize the core pathology as overactive social threat perception with no strong distinction made between the processes involved in the perception of individuals and the perception of groups (e.g., Diaconescu et al., 2019; Freeman, 2016; Freeman & Garety, 2014). However, persecutory delusions frequently include not only a belief about increased threat of harm but also a belief in a conspiracy behind the intent to harm, often involving the selective identification of a (seemingly arbitrary) group of persecutors (Raihani & Bell, 2019). As noted above, these sorts of social group misperceptions appear widely in delusions and appear in several delusion subtypes. Cognitively, the mechanisms underlying group perception seem to be distinct from individually focused social cognitive process such as theory of mind (Dunham, 2018), are present across species (Bissonnette et al., 2015), and emerge early in human infancy (Rhodes & Baron, 2019). Consequently, we hypothesize that people with delusions that involve the misperception of social alliances will show difficulties with the accurate perception of group boundaries and the judgment of joint intent, particularly as the task becomes more related to the topic of their delusional concern.

That delusions commonly involve a belief of having a radically altered social status (e.g., C. Green et al., 2006; Isham et al., 2019) and that, independently, social exclusion and social distance are risk factors for psychosis (Jongsma et al., 2020) suggest that cognitive mechanisms involved in the perception and processing of social status may be an important site of pathology. Processes involved in perceiving and managing social status are common across a range of social species, including humans; have an evolutionarily important social function (Chiao, 2010); and do not seem to be explainable solely in terms of mentalization (Rushworth et al., 2013). Social-rank perception has already been identified as important in mediating beliefs about and distress resulting from hallucinated voices (Larøi et al., 2019), and we hypothesize that perceived social-rank differences will have an effect on promoting delusional ideation in the relevant direction (e.g. Saalfeld et al., 2018) and that people with delusions involving marked changes in perception of social status will perform more poorly on tasks that measure of accurate perception of social status within a group.

Conclusions and Future Directions

We have argued that dysfunction to coalitional cognition is likely to be an important component in any adequate cognitive model of delusions. This approach has several benefits: (a) It suggests how a model that includes dysfunction to social processes that moderate belief formation could better explain aspects of the form (fixity and reduced sensitivity to social context) and content (social themes) of delusions, (b) it distinguishes delusional from nondelusional epistemically irrational beliefs, and (c) it is supported by the role of the mesolimbic dopamine system in both delusions and coalitional cognition.

However, we note several outstanding issues. The first is the relationship between dysfunction to coalitional cognition and dysfunction to other cognitive systems. We suggest that dysfunction to coalitional cognition may be sufficient, in itself, to account for some delusions. Given that well-functioning and adaptive social processes can form delusion-like beliefs, dysfunction to this system may lead to misconstrual of the social environment causing delusions to form without the need for impairment to other cognitive systems. The exact content of the belief (“Madonna is in love with me”) may well be a post hoc rationalization of a less specific social inference that, for example, a high-status person has a romantic connection to a person, with the same dysfunction making it difficult to moderate or socially test the specific belief after it has formed.

Alternatively, there may be an interaction between an impairment in coalitional cognition and impairment to other cognitive systems. Perhaps most convincing in this regard are delusions of alien control that are frequently socially themed but evidence suggests may also depend on dysfunction to mechanisms of action monitoring and execution (Blakemore, Wolpert, & Frith, 2002; Frith, 2012a). Likewise, perceptual dysfunction and hallucination may provide additional content for the delusional belief. However, it is worth noting here that hallucinated voices, the most common hallucinations that accompany delusions, have clear social content in the majority of cases (Bell, 2013; Bell et al., 2017; Woods et al., 2015). Likewise, visual hallucinations, also common in psychosis, are most commonly social in content (Collerton et al., 2016; van Ommen et al., 2019). We do not assume all perceptual disturbances related to delusions will have clear social content, but we note the strong thematic similarity, suggesting altered coalitional cognition may also affect perceptual experience.

Furthermore, although most delusions have a clear social theme, a minority do not. Delusional parasitosis, the delusional belief you are infested with parasites, can include delusions about other people as agents of infection, but most cases in the literature simply report a belief about infestation accompanied with perceptual disturbance in the form of formication, a sensation of crawling under the skin (Campbell et al., 2019). Avoidance of infection and contamination have been cited as basic mechanisms underlying social stigma and disgust, and this has been cited as a factor in delusional parasitosis (Kupfer & Fessler, 2018), but it is certainly the case that delusional parasitosis does not seem to be a prima facie example of a socially themed delusion. Likewise, somatic and apocalyptic delusions are not by definition social, although the extent to which these are best understood as reflecting coalitional themes requires further investigation.

In terms of scope, it is clear that future research needs to orient toward the coalitional features of delusions and should deploy methods that better capture coalitional processes effectively. Note that most cognitive models of delusions have either been “generalist,” aiming to explain the formation and maintenance of all delusions without particular reference to their theme, or have restricted themselves to specific themes (e.g., paranoid, external control) in a way that precludes the need to explain why delusions in general have a social theme. Research that takes a comparative approach to delusional themes is still lacking, and we note that some important and common delusional themes (e.g., grandiose delusions) have received remarkably little research attention (Knowles et al., 2011).

Furthermore, additional focus needs to be paid to the coalitional phenomenology of delusions. For example, we have noted that explanations of paranoid delusions mostly characterize them as “delusional fears about harm to self” despite the fact that they frequently include concerns about being persecuted by specific groups (Raihani & Bell, 2019). Delusions, and indeed hallucinated voices, seem to frequently involve illusory social agents, but this social aspect of the experience has been, until recently, markedly underresearched (Bell et al., 2017).

Likewise, many current paradigms in social cognition research are poorly able to capture coalitional processes such as evaluating relationships and alliances or tracking agent identity and status. Social cognition research in psychosis and schizophrenia has broadly coalesced on studying processes related to perception of individual others in ways that largely stem from methods that test individuals by exposing them to social information or involving them in simulated social situations (M. F. Green et al., 2015). Paradigms that involve experimental studies of interaction between individuals (e.g., “second person neuroscience”; Schilbach, 2016; Schilbach et al., 2013) or that examine interaction with groups (e.g., Greenburgh et al., 2019) are likely to be key in capturing the mechanisms of social influence and alliance.

In summary, we argue for a move away from attempts to explain delusions rooted primarily in terms of individual irrationality and instead toward models that include dysfunction to coalitional cognition as an essential component, which we argue are urgently needed to better capture the known form, content, and mechanisms of delusional beliefs.

Footnotes

Transparency

Action Editor: Michael F. Pogue-Geile

Editor: Scott O. Lilienfeld

Author Contributions

V. Bell drafted the manuscript, and N. Raihani and S. Wilkinson provided critical revisions. All of the authors approved the final manuscript for submission.

Declaration of Conflicting Interests: The author(s) declared that there were no conflicts of interest with respect to the authorship or the publication of this article.

Funding: This work was supported by Wellcome Trust Grant 200589/Z/16/Z and a Royal Society University Research Fellowship award.

References

  1. American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Author. [Google Scholar]
  2. Arnone D., Patel A., Tan G. M.-Y. (2006). The nosological significance of Folie à Deux: A review of the literature. Annals of General Psychiatry, 5, 11 10.1186/1744-859X-5-11 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Báez-Mendoza R., Schultz W. (2013). The role of the striatum in social behavior. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 7, Article 233. 10.3389/fnins.2013.00233 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  4. Bang D., Aitchison L., Moran R., Castanon S. H., Rafiee B., Mahmoodi A., Lau J. Y. F., Latham P. E., Bahrami B., Summerfield C. (2017). Confidence matching in group decision-making. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(6), 1–7. 10.1038/s41562-017-0117 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  5. Bang D., Ershadmanesh S., Nili H., Fleming S. M. (2020). Private-public mappings in human prefrontal cortex. BioRxiv. 10.1101/2020.02.21.954305 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  6. Bang D., Frith C. D. (2017). Making better decisions in groups. Royal Society Open Science, 4(8), 170193 10.1098/rsos.170193 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Barnes R. H. (1993). Construction sacrifice, kidnapping and head-hunting rumors on Flores and elsewhere in Indonesia. Oceania, 64(2), 146–158. 10.1002/j.1834-4461.1993.tb02459.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  8. Bartholomew R. E. (2001). Little green men, meowing nuns and head-hunting panics: A study of mass psychogenic illness and social delusion. McFarland. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bartholomew R. E., Victor J. S. (2004). A social-psychological theory of collective anxiety attacks: The “Mad Gasser” reexamined. The Sociological Quarterly, 45(2), 229–248. [Google Scholar]
  10. Bayne T. (2017). Delusion and the norms of rationality. In Hung T.-W., Lane T. J. (Eds.), Rationality (pp. 77–94). Academic Press; 10.1016/B978-0-12-804600-5.00005-2 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  11. Bazazi S., von Zimmermann J., Bahrami B., Richardson D. (2019). Self-serving incentives impair collective decisions by increasing conformity. PLOS ONE, 14(11), Article e0224725. 10.1371/journal.pone.0224725 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  12. Bell V. (2013). A community of one: Social cognition and auditory verbal hallucinations. PLOS Biol, 11(12), Article e1001723. 10.1371/journal.pbio.1001723 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Bell V., Halligan P. W., Ellis H. (2003). Beliefs about delusions. The Psychologist, 16(8), 418–423. [Google Scholar]
  14. Bell V., Halligan P. W., Ellis H. D. (2006). Explaining delusions: A cognitive perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(5), 219–226. 10.1016/j.tics.2006.03.004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Bell V., Mills K. L., Modinos G., Wilkinson S. (2017). Rethinking social cognition in light of psychosis: Reciprocal implications for cognition and psychopathology. Clinical Psychological Science, 5(3), 537–550. 10.1177/2167702616677079 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  16. Bentall R. P., Corcoran R., Howard R., Blackwood N., Kinderman P. (2001). Persecutory delusions: A review and theoretical integration. Clinical Psychology Review, 21(8), 1143–1192. 10.1016/S0272-7358(01)00106-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Bermúdez J. L. (2001). Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders. Mind & Language, 16(5), 493–457. 10.1111/1468-0017.00179 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  18. Berrios G. E. (1991). Delusions as “wrong beliefs”: A conceptual history. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 159(S14), 6–13. 10.1192/S0007125000296414 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Bissonnette A., Perry S., Barrett L., Mitani J. C., Flinn M., Gavrilets S., Waal F. B. M. de. (2015). Coalitions in theory and reality: A review of pertinent variables and processes. Behaviour, 152(1), 1–56. 10.1163/1568539X-00003241 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  20. Blakemore S.-J., Wolpert D. M., Frith C. D. (2002). Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(6), 237–242. 10.1016/S1364-6613(02)01907-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  21. Bora E., Yücel M., Pantelis C. (2010). Cognitive impairment in schizophrenia and affective psychoses: Implications for DSM-V criteria and beyond. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 36(1), 36–42. 10.1093/schbul/sbp094 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Bortolotti L. (2005). Delusions and the background of rationality. Mind & Language, 20(2), 189–208. 10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00282.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  23. Bortolotti L. (2010). Delusions and other irrational beliefs. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  24. Bortolotti L. (2015). The epistemic innocence of motivated delusions. Consciousness and Cognition, 33, 490–499. 10.1016/j.concog.2014.10.005 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Boyer P., Firat R., van Leeuwen F. (2015). Safety, threat, and stress in intergroup relations: A coalitional index model. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(4), 434–450. 10.1177/1745691615583133 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Bronstein M. V., Pennycook G., Joormann J., Corlett P. R., Cannon T. D. (2019). Dual-process theory, conflict processing, and delusional belief. Clinical Psychology Review, 72, 101748 10.1016/j.cpr.2019.101748 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Brooks S. A. (1987). Folie à deux in the aged: Variations in psychopathology. The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 32(1), 61–63. 10.1177/070674378703200112 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  28. Broyd A., Balzan R. P., Woodward T. S., Allen P. (2017). Dopamine, cognitive biases and assessment of certainty: A neurocognitive model of delusions. Clinical Psychology Review, 54(Suppl. C), 96–106. 10.1016/j.cpr.2017.04.006 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  29. Brüne M. (2001). De Clérambault’s syndrome (erotomania) in an evolutionary perspective. Evolution and Human Behavior, 22(6), 409–415. 10.1016/S1090-5138(01)00077-0 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  30. Campbell E. H., Elston D. M., Hawthorne J. D., Beckert D. R. (2019). Diagnosis and management of delusional parasitosis. Journal of the American Academy of Dermatology, 80(5), 1428–1434. 10.1016/j.jaad.2018.12.012 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  31. Chiao J. Y. (2010). Neural basis of social status hierarchy across species. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 20(6), 803–809. 10.1016/j.conb.2010.08.006 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Coates D. D. (2012). “Cult commitment” from the perspective of former members: Direct rewards of membership versus dependency inducing practices. Deviant Behavior, 33(3), 168–184. 10.1080/01639625.2010.548302 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  33. Colle L., Angeleri R., Vallana M., Sacco K., Bara B. G., Bosco F. M. (2013). Understanding the communicative impairments in schizophrenia: A preliminary study. Journal of Communication Disorders, 46(3), 294–308. 10.1016/j.jcomdis.2013.01.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Collerton D., Tayor J.-P., Tsuda I., Fujii H., Nara S., Aihara K., Katori Y. (2016). How can we see things that are not there? Current insights into complex visual hallucinations. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(7–8), 195–227. [Google Scholar]
  35. Coltheart M., Langdon R., McKay R. (2011). Delusional belief. Annual Review of Psychology, 62(1), 271–298. 10.1146/annurev.psych.121208.131622 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Corlett P. R., Taylor J. R., Wang X.-J., Fletcher P. C., Krystal J. H. (2010). Toward a neurobiology of delusions. Progress in Neurobiology, 92(3), 345–369. 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2010.06.007 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Cox R. E., Barnier A. J. (2010). Hypnotic illusions and clinical delusions: Hypnosis as a research method. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 15(1–3), 202–232. 10.1080/13546800903319884 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Cushman F. (2019). Rationalization is rational. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 43, Article e28. 10.1017/S0140525X19001730 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  39. Dan A., Mondal T., Chakraborty K., Chaudhuri A., Biswas A. (2017). Clinical course and treatment outcome of Koro: A follow up study from a Koro epidemic reported from West Bengal, India. Asian Journal of Psychiatry, 26, 14–20. 10.1016/j.ajp.2016.12.016 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. David A. S. (1999). On the impossibility of defining delusions. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 6(1), 17–20. [Google Scholar]
  41. Dawson L. L. (1996). Who joins new religious movements and why: Twenty years of research and what have we learned? Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses, 25(2), 141–161. 10.1177/000842989602500202 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  42. de Portugal E., González N., del Amo V., Haro J. M., Díaz-Caneja C. M., de Dios Luna del Castillo J., Cervilla J. A. (2013). Empirical redefinition of delusional disorder and its phenomenology: The DELIREMP study. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 54(3), 243–255. 10.1016/j.comppsych.2012.08.002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  43. Diaconescu A. O., Hauke D. J., Borgwardt S. (2019). Models of persecutory delusions: A mechanistic insight into the early stages of psychosis. Molecular Psychiatry, 24, 1258–1267. 10.1038/s41380-019-0427-z [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Dippel B., Kemper J., Berger M. (1991). Folie à six: A case report on induced psychotic disorder. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 83(2), 137–141. 10.1111/j.1600-0447.1991.tb07379.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Douglas K. M., Sutton R. M., Cichocka A. (2017). The psychology of conspiracy theories. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 26(6), 538–542. 10.1177/0963721417718261 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  46. Dudley R., Taylor P., Wickham S., Hutton P. (2016). Psychosis, delusions and the “jumping to conclusions” reasoning bias: A systematic review and meta-analysis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 42(3), 652–665. 10.1093/schbul/sbv150 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  47. Dunbar R. I. M., Shultz S. (2017). Why are there so many explanations for primate brain evolution? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 372(1727), 20160244 10.1098/rstb.2016.0244 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  48. Dunham Y. (2018). Mere membership. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22(9), 780–793. 10.1016/j.tics.2018.06.004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Echterhoff G., Higgins E. T., Levine J. M. (2009). Shared reality: Experiencing commonality with others’ inner states about the world. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 4(5), 496–521. 10.1111/j.1745-6924.2009.01161.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  50. Edgell P. (2012). A cultural sociology of religion: New directions. Annual Review of Sociology, 38(1), 247–265. 10.1146/annurev-soc-071811-145424 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  51. Edis T., Boudry M. (2019). Truth and consequences: When is it rational to accept falsehoods? Journal of Cognition and Culture, 19(1–2), 147–169. 10.1163/15685373-12340052 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  52. Ellersgaard D., Mors O., Thorup A., Jørgensen P., Jeppesen P., Nordentoft M. (2014). Prospective study of the course of delusional themes in first-episode non-affective psychosis. Early Intervention in Psychiatry, 8(4), 340–347. 10.1111/eip.12059 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  53. Ellett L., Allen-Crooks R., Stevens A., Wildschut T., Chadwick P. (2013). A paradigm for the study of paranoia in the general population: The prisoner’s dilemma game. Cognition and Emotion, 27(1), 53–62. 10.1080/02699931.2012.689757 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  54. Feeney E. J., Groman S. M., Taylor J. R., Corlett P. R. (2017). Explaining delusions: Reducing uncertainty through basic and computational neuroscience. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 43(2), 263–272. 10.1093/schbul/sbw194 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Fett A-K. J., Shergill S. S., Joyce D. W., Riedl A., Strobel M., Gromann P. M., Krabbendam L. (2012). To trust or not to trust: The dynamics of social interaction in psychosis. Brain, 135(3), 976–984. 10.1093/brain/awr359 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Fett A.-K. J., Shergill S. S., Korver-Nieberg N., Yakub F., Gromann P. M., Krabbendam L. (2016). Learning to trust: Trust and attachment in early psychosis. Psychological Medicine, 46(7), 1437–1447. 10.1017/S0033291716000015 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Fransen M. L., Smit E. G., Verlegh P. W. J. (2015). Strategies and motives for resistance to persuasion: An integrative framework. Frontiers in Psychology, 6 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01201 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Freeman D. (2016). Persecutory delusions: A cognitive perspective on understanding and treatment. The Lancet Psychiatry, 3(7), 685–692. 10.1016/S2215-0366(16)00066-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  59. Freeman D., Garety P. (2014). Advances in understanding and treating persecutory delusions: A review. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 49(8), 1179–1189. 10.1007/s00127-014-0928-7 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Frith C. D. (2012. a). Explaining delusions of control: The comparator model 20 years on. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(1), 52–54. 10.1016/j.concog.2011.06.010 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  61. Frith C. D. (2012. b). The role of metacognition in human social interactions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367, 2213–2223. 10.1098/rstb.2012.0123 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  62. Frith C. D., Blakemore S.-J., Wolpert D. M. (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Reviews, 31, 357–363. doi: 10.1016/S0165-0173(99)00052-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  63. Gallagher S., Varga S. (2015). Social cognition and psychopathology: A critical overview. World Psychiatry, 14(1), 5–14. 10.1002/wps.20173 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  64. Garety P. (1991). Reasoning and delusions. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 159(S14), 14–18. 10.1192/S0007125000296426 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  65. Garety P. A., Freeman D. (1999). Cognitive approaches to delusions: A critical review of theories and evidence. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 38, 113–154. doi: 10.1348/014466599162700 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  66. Garety P. A., Kuipers E., Fowler D., Freeman D., Bebbington P. E. (2001). A cognitive model of the positive symptoms of psychosis. Psychological Medicine, 31(2), 189–195. 10.1017/S0033291701003312 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  67. Gelpi R., Cunningham W. A., Buchsbaum D. (2019). Belief as a non-epistemic adaptive benefit. PsyArXiv. 10.31234/osf.io/6ythf [DOI] [PubMed]
  68. Gerlach J., Larsen E. B. (1999). Subjective experience and mental side-effects of antipsychotic treatment. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 99(s395), 113–117. 10.1111/j.1600-0447.1999.tb05990.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  69. Gerrans P. (2001). Delusions as performance failures. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 6(3), 161–173. 10.1080/1354680004200016 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  70. Ghosal S., Sandi C., van der Kooij M. A. (2019). Neuropharmacology of the mesolimbic system and associated circuits on social hierarchies. Neuropharmacology, 159, Article 107498. 10.1016/j.neuropharm.2019.01.013 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Gilleen J., David A. S. (2005). The cognitive neuropsychiatry of delusions: From psychopathology to neuropsychology and back again. Psychological Medicine, 35(1), 5–12. 10.1017/S0033291704003976 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Gold I., Hohwy J. (2000). Rationality and schizophrenic delusion. Mind & Language, 15(1), 146–167. 10.1111/1468-0017.00127 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  73. Green C., Garety P. A., Freeman D., Fowler D., Bebbington P., Dunn G., Kuipers E. (2006). Content and affect in persecutory delusions. British Journal of Clinical Psychology, 45(4), 561–577. 10.1348/014466506X98768 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  74. Green M. F., Horan W. P., Lee J. (2015). Social cognition in schizophrenia. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16(10), 620–631. 10.1038/nrn4005 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Greenburgh A., Bell V., Raihani N. (2019). Paranoia and conspiracy: Group cohesion increases harmful intent attribution in the Trust Game. PeerJ, 7, Article e7403. 10.7717/peerj.7403 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  76. Gromann P. M., Heslenfeld D. J., Fett A.-K., Joyce D. W., Shergill S. S., Krabbendam L. (2013). Trust versus paranoia: Abnormal response to social reward in psychotic illness. Brain, 36(Pt. 6), 1968–1975. 10.1093/brain/awt076 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  77. Gutiérrez-Lobos K., Schmid-Siegel B., Bankier B., Walter H. (2001). Delusions in first-admitted patients: Gender, themes and diagnoses. Psychopathology, 34(1), 1–7. 10.1159/000049273 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  78. Hill B., Kevin P., Patkar M., Ashwin A. (2001). Folie a famille associated with amphetamine use. Jefferson Journal of Psychiatry, 16(1), Article 5. 10.29046/JJP.016.1.004 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  79. Hinzen W., Rosselló J., McKenna P. (2016). Can delusions be understood linguistically? Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 21(4), 281–299. 10.1080/13546805.2016.1190703 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  80. Hirjak D., Breyer T., Thomann P. A., Fuchs T. (2013). Disturbance of intentionality: A phenomenological study of body-affecting first-rank symptoms in schizophrenia. PLOS ONE, 8(9), Article e73662. 10.1371/journal.pone.0073662 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  81. Holman B. (2016). The phantom airship panic of 1913: Imagining aerial warfare in Britain before the Great War. Journal of British Studies, 55(1), 99–119. 10.1017/jbr.2015.173 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  82. Howes O. D., Kapur S. (2009). The dopamine hypothesis of schizophrenia: Version III—The final common pathway. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 35(3), 549–562. 10.1093/schbul/sbp006 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  83. Howes O. D., Murray R. M. (2014). Schizophrenia: An integrated sociodevelopmental-cognitive model. The Lancet, 383(9929), 1677–1687. 10.1016/S0140-6736(13)62036-X [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  84. Huq S. F., Garety P. A., Hemsley D. R. (1988). Probabilistic judgements in deluded and non-deluded subjects. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A, 40(4), 801–812. 10.1080/14640748808402300 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  85. Isham L., Griffith L., Boylan A.-M., Hicks A., Wilson N., Byrne R., . . . Freeman D. (2019). Understanding, treating, and renaming grandiose delusions: A qualitative study. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice. Advance online publication. 10.1111/papt.12260 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  86. Johnson D. D. P., Blumstein D. T., Fowler J. H., Haselton M. G. (2013). The evolution of error: Error management, cognitive constraints, and adaptive decision-making biases. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 28(8), 474–481. 10.1016/j.tree.2013.05.014 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. Jongsma H. E., Gayer-Anderson C., Tarricone I., Velthorst E., Ven E., van der Quattrone D., di Forti M. EU-GEI WP2 Group, Menezes P. R., Del-Ben C. M., Arango C., Lasalvia A., Berardi D., Cascia C. L., Bobes J., Bernardo M., Sanjuán J., Santos J. L., Arrojo M., . . . Kirkbride J. B. (2020). Social disadvantage, linguistic distance, ethnic minority status and first-episode psychosis: Results from the EU-GEI case–control study. Psychological Medicine. Advance online publication. 10.1017/S003329172000029X [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  88. José M. S., Mary V. S. (1995). Shared psychotic disorder: A critical review of the literature. The Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 40(7), 389–395. 10.1177/070674379504000705 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  89. Jost J. T., Ledgerwood A., Hardin C. D. (2008). Shared reality, system justification, and the relational basis of ideological beliefs. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 2(1), 171–186. 10.1111/j.1751-9004.2007.00056.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  90. Kaar S. J., Natesan S., McCutcheon R., Howes O. D. (2019). Antipsychotics: Mechanisms underlying clinical response and side-effects and novel treatment approaches based on pathophysiology. Neuropharmacology, 107704 10.1016/j.neuropharm.2019.107704 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  91. Kappeler P. M., van Schaik C. P. (2002). Evolution of primate social systems. International Journal of Primatology, 23(4), 707–740. 10.1023/A:1015520830318 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  92. Knowles R., McCarthy-Jones S., Rowse G. (2011). Grandiose delusions: A review and theoretical integration of cognitive and affective perspectives. Clinical Psychology Review, 31(4), 684–696. 10.1016/j.cpr.2011.02.009 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  93. Krach S., Paulus F. M., Bodden M., Kircher Ti. (2010). The rewarding nature of social interactions. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 4, Article 22. 10.3389/fnbeh.2010.00022 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  94. Kupfer T. R., Fessler D. M. T. (2018). Ectoparasite defence in humans: Relationships to pathogen avoidance and clinical implications. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 373(1751). 10.1098/rstb.2017.0207 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  95. Langdon R., Coltheart M. (2000). The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions. Mind & Language, 15(1), 184–218. 10.1111/1468-0017.00129 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  96. Larøi F., Thomas N., Aleman A., Fernyhough C., Wilkinson S., Deamer F., McCarthy-Jones S. (2019). The ice in voices: Understanding negative content in auditory-verbal hallucinations. Clinical Psychology Review, 67, 1–10. 10.1016/j.cpr.2018.11.001 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  97. Leeser J., O’Donohue W. (1999). What is a delusion? Epistemological dimensions. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 108(4), 687–694. 10.1037/0021-843X.108.4.687 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  98. Maher B. A. (1999). Anomalous experience in everyday life: Its significance for psychopathology. The Monist, 82(4), 547–570. [Google Scholar]
  99. McKay R. (2012). Delusional inference. Mind & Language, 27(3), 330–355. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2012.01447.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  100. McKay R. T., Dennett D. C. (2009). The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(06), 493–510. 10.1017/S0140525X09990975 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  101. McLean B. F., Mattiske J. K., Balzan R. P. (2017). Association of the jumping to conclusions and evidence integration biases with delusions in psychosis: A detailed meta-analysis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 43(2), 344–354. 10.1093/schbul/sbw056 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  102. Medalia N. Z., Larsen O. N. (1958). Diffusion and belief in a collective delusion: The Seattle windshield pitting epidemic. American Sociological Review, 23(2), 180–186. JSTOR. 10.2307/2089002 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  103. Melton J. G. (1985). Spiritualization and reaffirmation: What really happens when prophecy fails. American Studies, 26(2), 17–29. [Google Scholar]
  104. Mentjox R., van Houten C. A. G., Kooiman C. G. (1993). Induced psychotic disorder: Clinical aspects, theoretical considerations, and some guidelines for treatment. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 34(2), 120–126. 10.1016/0010-440X(93)90056-A [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  105. Mercier H., Sperber D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(2), 57–74. 10.1017/S0140525X10000968 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  106. Mitchell J., Vierkant A. D. (1991). Delusions and hallucinations of cocaine abusers and paranoid schizophrenics: A comparative study. The Journal of Psychology, 125(3), 301–310. 10.1080/00223980.1991.10543294 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  107. Miyazono K., McKay R. (2019). Explaining delusional beliefs: A hybrid model. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 24(5), 335–346. 10.1080/13546805.2019.1664443 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  108. Mollon J., David A. S., Morgan C., Frissa S., Glahn D., Pilecka I., Hatch S. L., Hotopf M., Reichenberg A. (2016). Psychotic experiences and neuropsychological functioning in a population-based sample. JAMA Psychiatry, 73(2), 129–138. 10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2015.2551 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  109. Moritz S., Andreou C., Klingberg S., Thoering T., Peters M. J. V. (2013). Assessment of subjective cognitive and emotional effects of antipsychotic drugs. Effect by defect? Neuropharmacology, 72, 179–186. 10.1016/j.neuropharm.2013.04.039 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  110. Moritz S., Woodward T. S. (2006). Metacognitive control over false memories: A key determinant of delusional thinking. Current Psychiatry Reports, 8(3), 184–190. 10.1007/s11920-006-0022-2 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  111. Mujica-Parodi L. R., Malaspina D., Sackeim H. A. (2000). Logical processing, affect, and delusional thought in schizophrenia. Harvard Review of Psychiatry, 8(2), 73–83. 10.1080/hrp_8.2.73 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  112. Murguia S. J. (2011). When prophets fail to fail: A case study of Yuko Chino, Chino Shoho, and the Pana-Wave laboratory. In Tumminia D. G., Swatos W. H., Jr. (Eds.), How prophecy lives (pp. 99–114). Brill. [Google Scholar]
  113. O’Connell L. A., Hofmann H. A. (2011). The vertebrate mesolimbic reward system and social behavior network: A comparative synthesis. Journal of Comparative Neurology, 519(18), 3599–3639. 10.1002/cne.22735 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  114. Paget A., Ellett L. (2014). Relationships among self, others, and persecutors in individuals with persecutory delusions: A repertory grid analysis. Behavior Therapy, 45(2), 273–282. 10.1016/j.beth.2013.12.001 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  115. Paolini E., Moretti P., Compton M. T. (2016). Delusions in first-episode psychosis: Principal component analysis of twelve types of delusions and demographic and clinical correlates of resulting domains. Psychiatry Research, 243, 5–13. 10.1016/j.psychres.2016.06.002 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  116. Peralta V., Cuesta M. J. (2016). Delusional disorder and schizophrenia: A comparative study across multiple domains. Psychological Medicine, 46(13), 2829–2839. 10.1017/S0033291716001501 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  117. Picardi A., Fonzi L., Pallagrosi M., Gigantesco A., Biondi M. (2018). Delusional themes across affective and non-affective psychoses. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 9, Article 132. 10.3389/fpsyt.2018.00132 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  118. Pierre J. (2001). Faith or delusion? At the crossroads of religion and psychosis. Journal of Psychiatric Practice, 7(3), 163–172. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  119. Ponsford J., Alway Y., Gould K. R. (2018). Epidemiology and natural history of psychiatric disorders after TBI. The Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 30(4), 262–270. 10.1176/appi.neuropsych.18040093 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  120. Prather C. H. (1999). God’s Salvation Church: Past, present and future. Marburg Journal of Religion, 4(1). 10.17192/mjr.1999.4.3761 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  121. Radden J. (1985). Madness and reason. Unwin Hyman. [Google Scholar]
  122. Raihani N. J., Bell V. (2017). Paranoia and the social representation of others: A large-scale game theory approach. Scientific Reports, 7(1), 1–9. 10.1038/s41598-017-04805-3 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  123. Raihani N. J., Bell V. (2019). An evolutionary perspective on paranoia. Nature Human Behaviour, 3(2), 114–121. 10.1038/s41562-018-0495-0 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  124. Rauwolf P., Mitchell D., Bryson J. J. (2015). Value homophily benefits cooperation but motivates employing incorrect social information. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 367, 246–261. 10.1016/j.jtbi.2014.11.023 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  125. Rhodes M., Baron A. (2019). The development of social categorization. Annual Review of Developmental Psychology, 1(1), 359–386. 10.1146/annurev-devpsych-121318-084824 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  126. Rieben I., Mohr S., Borras L., Gillieron C., Brandt P.-Y., Perroud N., Huguelet P. (2013). A thematic analysis of delusion with religious contents in schizophrenia: Open, closed, and mixed dynamics. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 201(8), 665–673. 10.1097/NMD.0b013e31829c5073 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  127. Robinson W. G. (1997). Heaven’s Gate: The end. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication, 3(3). 10.1111/j.1083-6101.1997.tb00077.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  128. Rodríguez-Carballeira Á., Saldaña O., Almendros C., Martín-Peña J., Escartín J., Porrúa-García C. (2015). Group psychological abuse: Taxonomy and severity of its components. The European Journal of Psychology Applied to Legal Context, 7(1), 31–39. 10.1016/j.ejpal.2014.11.001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  129. Ross R. M., McKay R. (2017). Why is belief in God not a delusion? Religion, Brain & Behavior, 7(4), 316–319. 10.1080/2153599X.2016.1249917 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  130. Rushworth M. F., Mars R. B., Sallet J. (2013). Are there specialized circuits for social cognition and are they unique to humans? Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 23(3), 436–442. 10.1016/j.conb.2012.11.013 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  131. Saalfeld V., Ramadan Z., Bell V., Raihani N. J. (2018). Experimentally induced social threat increases paranoid thinking. Royal Society Open Science, 5(8), Article 180569. 10.1098/rsos.180569 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  132. Sahoo A., Josephs K. A. (2017). A neuropsychiatric analysis of the Cotard delusion. The Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 30, 58–65. 10.1176/appi.neuropsych.17010018 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  133. Sakakibara E. (2016). Irrationality and pathology of beliefs. Neuroethics, 9(2), 147–157. 10.1007/s12152-016-9256-9 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  134. Salamone J. D., Correa M. (2012). The mysterious motivational functions of mesolimbic dopamine. Neuron, 76(3), 470–485. 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.10.021 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  135. Savulich G., Jeanes H., Rossides N., Kaur S., Zacharia A., Robbins T. W., Sahakian B. J. (2018). Moral emotions and social economic games in paranoia. Frontiers in Psychiatry, 9, Article 615. 10.3389/fpsyt.2018.00615 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  136. Schilbach L. (2016). Towards a second-person neuropsychiatry. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 371(1686), Article 20150081. 10.1098/rstb.2015.0081 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  137. Schilbach L., Timmermans B., Reddy V., Costall A., Bente G., Schlicht T., Vogeley K. (2013). Toward a second-person neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(4), 393–414. 10.1017/S0140525X12000660 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  138. Schimansky J., Rössler W., Haker H. (2012). The influence of social cognition on ego disturbances in patients with schizophrenia. Psychopathology, 45(2), 117–125. 10.1159/000330264 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  139. Seeman M. V. (2016). Pathological jealousy: An interactive condition. Psychiatry, 79(4), 379–388. 10.1080/00332747.2016.1175838 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  140. Selten J.-P., van der Ven E., Rutten B. P. F., Cantor-Graae E. (2013). The social defeat hypothesis of schizophrenia: An update. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 39(6), 1180–1186. 10.1093/schbul/sbt134 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  141. Shimizu M., Kubota Y., Toichi M., Baba H. (2007). Folie à deux and shared psychotic disorder. Current Psychiatry Reports, 9(3), 200–205. 10.1007/s11920-007-0019-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. So S. H., Siu N. Y., Wong H., Chan W., Garety P. A. (2016). ‘Jumping to conclusions’ data-gathering bias in psychosis and other psychiatric disorders—Two meta-analyses of comparisons between patients and healthy individuals. Clinical Psychology Review, 46, 151–167. 10.1016/j.cpr.2016.05.001 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  143. Stompe T., Friedman A., Ortwein G., Strobl R., Chaudhry H. R., Najam N., Chaudhry M. R. (1999). Comparison of delusions among schizophrenics in Austria and in Pakistan. Psychopathology, 32(5), 225–234. 10.1159/000029094 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  144. Suhail K., Cochrane R. (2002). Effect of culture and environment on the phenomenology of delusions and hallucinations. International Journal of Social Psychiatry, 48(2), 126–138. 10.1177/002076402128783181 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  145. Tanenberg-Karant M., Fennig S., Ram R., Krishna J., Jandorf L., Bromet E. J. (1995). Bizarre delusions and first-rank symptoms in a first-admission sample: A preliminary analysis of prevalence and correlates. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 36(6), 428–434. 10.1016/S0010-440X(95)90250-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  146. Tomasello M. (2009). Why we cooperate. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  147. Tooby J., Cosmides L. (2010). Groups in mind: The coalitional roots of war and morality. In Høgh-Olesen H. (Ed.), Human morality and sociality: Evolutionary and comparative perspectives (pp. 191–234). Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  148. Trainor B. C. (2011). Stress responses and the mesolimbic dopamine system: Social contexts and sex differences. Hormones and Behavior, 60(5), 457–469. 10.1016/j.yhbeh.2011.08.013 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  149. Tripoli G., Quattrone D., Ferraro L., Gayer-Anderson C., Rodriguez V., Cascia C. L., Barbera D. L., Sartorio C., Seminerio F., Tarricone I., Berardi D., Szöke A., Arango C., Tortelli A., Llorca P.-M., de Haan L., Velthorst E., Bobes J., Bernardo M., . . .di Forti M. (2020). Jumping to conclusions, general intelligence, and psychosis liability: Findings from the multi-centre EU-GEI case-control study. Psychological Medicine. Advance online publication. 10.1017/S003329171900357X [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  150. van Ommen M. M., van Laar T., Cornelissen F. W., Bruggeman R. (2019). Visual hallucinations in psychosis. Psychiatry Research, 280, Article 112517. 10.1016/j.psychres.2019.112517 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  151. Ventura J., Wood R. C., Hellemann G. S. (2013). Symptom domains and neurocognitive functioning can help differentiate social cognitive processes in schizophrenia: A meta-analysis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 39(1), 102–111. 10.1093/schbul/sbr067 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  152. Voce A., Calabria B., Burns R., Castle D., McKetin R. (2019). A systematic review of the symptom profile and course of methamphetamine-associated psychosis. Substance Use & Misuse, 54(4), 549–559. 10.1080/10826084.2018.1521430 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  153. Von Domarus E. (1944). The specific laws of logic in schizophrenia. In Kasanin J. S., Lewis N. D. C. (Eds.), Language and thought in schizophrenia (pp. 104–113). University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
  154. Wardle M. C., de Wit H. (2012). Effects of amphetamine on reactivity to emotional stimuli. Psychopharmacology, 220(1), 143–153. 10.1007/s00213-011-2498-7 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  155. Wardle M. C., Garner M. J., Munafò M. R., de Wit H. (2012). Amphetamine as a social drug: Effects of d-amphetamine on social processing and behavior. Psychopharmacology, 223(2), 199–210. 10.1007/s00213-012-2708-y [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  156. Warren N., O’Gorman C., Hume Z., Kisely S., Siskind D. (2018). Delusions in Parkinson’s disease: A systematic review of published cases. Neuropsychology Review, 28(3), 310–316. 10.1007/s11065-018-9379-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  157. Williams D. (2020). Socially adaptive belief. Mind & Language. Advance online publication. 10.1111/mila.12294 [DOI]
  158. Winton-Brown T. T., Fusar-Poli P., Ungless M. A., Howes O. D. (2014). Dopaminergic basis of salience dysregulation in psychosis. Trends in Neurosciences, 37(2), 85–94. 10.1016/j.tins.2013.11.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  159. Woods A., Jones N., Alderson-Day B., Callard F., Fernyhough C. (2015). Experiences of hearing voices: Analysis of a novel phenomenological survey. The Lancet Psychiatry, 2(4), 323–331. 10.1016/S2215-0366(15)00006-1 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  160. Yager J. A., Ehmann T. S. (2006). Untangling social function and social cognition: A review of concepts and measurement. Psychiatry: Interpersonal and Biological Processes, 69(1), 47–68. 10.1521/psyc.2006.69.1.47 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Clinical Psychological Science are provided here courtesy of SAGE Publications

RESOURCES