Abstract
Entanglement is one of the strongest quantum correlation, and is a key ingredient in fundamental aspects of quantum mechanics and a resource for quantum technologies. While entanglement theory is well settled for distinguishable particles, there are five inequivalent approaches to entanglement of indistinguishable particles. We analyse the different definitions of indistinguishable particle entanglement in the light of the locality notion. This notion is specified by two steps: (i) the identification of subsystems by means of their local operators; (ii) the requirement that entanglement represent correlations between the above subsets of operators. We prove that three of the aforementioned five entanglement definitions are incompatible with any locality notion defined as above.
Subject terms: Information theory and computation, Quantum physics
Introduction
Entanglement is one of the strongest form of quantum correlations and is crucial for the undestanding of Bell’s inequalities1, quantum communications2, quantum metrology3,4, and quantum computation5,6. Fundamental aspects of quantum theory and the quantum information framework suggest that entanglement is a notion derived from the definition of subsystems that can be correlated or, in other words, from the notion of locality. For instance, any entangled pure state of two distinguishable particles violates a Bell’s inequality, and thus prove quantum non-locality7,8, and the resourcefulness of Bell non-locality is a special instance of entanglement theory9. On the other hand, several quantum technologies consist of parties independently manipulating subsystems, and entanglement among subsystems is a fundamental resource that allows to overcome the limitations of local operations on subsystems and classical communications between them10.
Entanglement theory is very well understood for distinguishable particles: two-particle separable, namely non-entangled, pure states are of the form , and each subsystem is implicitly assumed to be a particle. This definition can be reformulated by describing each subsystem with operators, termed local and acting non-trivially only on it, i.e. for the first particle and for the second one. Therefore, a pure state is separable if and only if its expectations do not show correlations between single-particle operators: for any A, B as above11.
The choice of the operators A and B naturally arises from the experimental ability to individually address particles. Nevertheless, correlations between operators of different form have been proven to correspond to entanglement between more general subsystems12–16, already in the framework of distinguishable particles.
Although distinguishable particles are a very useful paradigm in many physical systems, e.g. spin models where particles are localised at different positions, Nature is made of several kinds of indistinguishable particles, like electrons, atoms and photons. Particle indistinguishability requires that pure states and operators be invariant under particle permutations. In particular, the aforementioned single-particle operators are no longer allowed. These considerations challenge the notion of particle as a natural subsystem, whenever indistinguishability cannot be neglected, e.g. if particles are not spatially separated (see Fig. 1 for an illustration of particles that are progressively less separated and lose their distinguishability).
Figure 1.
Pictorial representation of two identical particles with an internal degree of freedom and a spatial degree of freedom, when the spatial wave function do not overlap (effectively distinguishable particles), partially overlap , and overlap almost completely .
In this context, five alternative definitions of entanglement in systems of indistinguishable particles have been proposed: see17 for a review. Nevertheless, the identification of subsystems and of local operators, whose correlations correspond to entanglement, is not always addressed. This identification indeed allows us to systematically describe the advantage that indistinguishable particle entanglement provides over local operations and classical communications in quantum technologies. Other resource theories can characterize resourceful states that overcome the limitations of operations defined by lifting the locality requirement. The characterisation of local operators also enables us to understand the overlap of a resource theory with entanglement theory, and the cost of resource conversion in terms of resourceful operations of both theories.
We say that a definition of entanglement is compatible with a notion of locality if entanglement corresponds to correlations between commuting subsets of operators and : for all and for pure separable states (see11,17 for the generalization to mixed states). These operator subsets formally and operationally define subsystems as they consist of observables individually measurable and transformations induvidually implementable without mutual disturbance due to their commutativity . A preliminary comparative analysis among the existing entanglement approaches shows that only one of them is fully consistent17. In particular, three of these approaches cannot be interpreted as entanglement of particles, because they are not consistent with the correlations between subsets made of permutationally invariant single-particle operators. The physical intuition is that truly indistinguishable particles cannot be individually addressed (see the sketch in Fig. 1). This issue does not apply to the other approaches, since one, the so-called superselection rule (SSR) entanglement, is resticted to physical situations of particles that can be effectively distinguished by means of certain degrees of freedom18–20, and the other accounts for more general correlations between modes in a second quantised description that also recovers particle correlations for effectively distinguishable particles21–30. The latter notion, i.e. mode-entanglement, is also routinely applied for entanglement detection, manipulations and measures17,31–33.
In this paper, we focus on the aforementioned entanglement definitions that do not correspond to particle correlations, and investigate if they rather represent correlations between subsystems identified by general subsets and . For each definition, we define the set of separable pure states, namely , and look for candidates for the subsets and .
Before sketching the general scheme of our analysis, it is crucial to notice that the linearity of quantum mechanics implies that the set of operators of a system, as well as subsystems, is an algebra34,35. An algebra is a linear space closed under a multiplication between its elements and under a conjugation operation (hermitian conjugation in our case). Therefore, the subsets and that comprise all operators acting on each subsystem are algebras, as happens in the standard case of distinguishable particles. Nevertheless, we have used neither the algebra structure nor commutativity in our main results which therefore hold also for more general subsets of operators, as those considered in36.
A necessary condition for operators and is that they do not generate entanglement, because subsystems cannot be correlated by local operators, like A, B, and AB. This requirement is formulated in full generality as and , or
1 |
relaxing the normalisation conditions, such that , , .
Operators in each subset, and , are chosen from the above ones, and those belonging to different subsets must commute with each other. Thus, we check the factorisation condition
2 |
for any subset, and , of operators that do not generate entanglement.
Results
We are now ready to go through the different entanglement definitions and to look for possible subsets, and , of local operators. We shall prove that it is impossible to find subsets whose correlations correspond to the following notions of entanglement. Specifically, we find that for any possible subset bipartition there are separable states that do not fulfil the factorisation of local expectations (2).
The first quantisation formalism is most familiar to the entanglement definitions analysed here. For completeness, we provide some definitions both in first and second quantisation, using the tilde to distinguish the second quantization formalism. However, our computations rely on matrix representations of the Hilbert space that are equivalent to matrix representations of Fock space sectors, after rewriting the basis states from first to second quantisation. Therefore, our conclusions remain valid in both formalisms, and we often consider the symbols without the tilde for simplifying the notation.
Moreover, we shall present our results in the form of lemmas and theorems in order to emphasise the key results in the statements.
Entanglement-I
For the sake of concreteness, let us focus on two bosonic two-level particles. Define a basis of the single particle Hilbert space , namely and , and that of the symmetrised two-particle Hilbert space where is the symmetrisation projector,
3 |
In second quantisation the above states read
4 |
where are creation operators of a single particle in the state or respectively, with , and is the vacuum.
In this case, the first entanglement definition is
Definition 1
(Entanglement-I37–40) The set of pure separable-I states is, in first and second quantization respectively,
5 |
6 |
All other pure states are entangled-I.
Practical realisations of the above single particle states and are, e.g. in cold atoms, spatial localisation in separated wells of a lattice, or hyperfine energy levels. Therefore, separable-I states are those with particles in the same superposition of localised or energy states.
In the following theorem, we characterise operators that do not generate entanglement-I.
Theorem 1
Operators that leave invariant are represented in first quantisation as on the enlarged Hilbert space with , and in second quantisation as
7 |
Proof
Any operator A that does not generate entanglement-I fulfils Eq. (1) which implies, from Definition 1,
8 |
where . Note that only the projection onto the symmetric space contribute to Eq. (9) since we considered bosonic states. Equalities (8) for imply
9 |
in the basis (3), or (4), with .
Conditions for x and y are found by requiring Eq. (1) for arbitrary . This requirement implies, after plugging into (8) the explicit form of in Eq. (5), that the coefficients of each monomial vanish. We obtain
10 |
11 |
12 |
The solutions of the above equations are
13 |
14 |
15 |
with either all plus signs or all minus signs.
The two cases, e.g. plus and minus signs, are equivalent as they result in the same operator by redefining and . Therefore, we found
16 |
In first quantisation, the above matrix is exactly the projection onto the symmetric subspace of the operator on the larger Hilbert space , with
17 |
in the basis . In second quantization, Eq. (16) is the matrix representation of Eq. (7). This concludes the proof.
The factorisation condition can be checked for arbitrary operators, and , that could form subsets of local operators. Note that the subsets are not necessarily commuting in the next theorem. We have therefore proven a more general result than what we need in entanglement analysis.
Theorem 2
Given two subsets and of operators that leave invariant, the factorisation condition (2) and Definition 1 imply that either or consists only of operators proportional to the identity.
Proof
Consider a separable-I state as in Definition 1, and two operators, and as in Theorem 1. The factorisation condition (2) reads
18 |
Both the left and the right hand sides of Eq. (18) are eight order polynomials in and . Nevertheless, there are monomials in the right-hand-side that do not appear in the left-hand-side. Since the factorisation condition must hold for any separable-I state, thus for any and , the monomials that appear only in the right-hand-side, i.e. with and , must by multiplied by vanishing coefficients, i.e. . This consideration implies that either O or Q are diagonal in the basis . The latter basis is arbitrary and the diagonality requirement must hold for any basis rotation. In conclusion, either O or Q must be proportional to the identity.
Therefore, entanglement-I is incompatible with any locality notions where each subsystem is characterised by subsets of local operators. We have not used the commutativity of subsets and in Theorem 2. In the Supplementary Information, we provide a characterisation of commuting subsets of operators that do not generate entanglement-I, a second proof of Theorem 2 using , and some examples of the proven properties.
Entanglement-II
Considering again two bosonic two-level particles, the second entanglement definition is
Definition 2
[Entanglement-II37–39,41–46] The set of pure separable-II states is, in first and second quantization respectively,
19 |
20 |
All other pure states are entangled-II.
Keeping in mind the same physical realisations mentioned after Definition 1, two particles are separable-II if they are either in the same or in orthogonal superpositions of spatial localisations or of hyperfine levels.
Theorem 3
Any operator that leaves invariant also leaves invariant.
Proof
Consider an operator A that does not generate entanglement-II, and therefore leaves invariant, and a state . Either or . A necessary and sufficient condition for is Eq. (8), namely
21 |
Instead, a necessary and sufficient condition for , in the case of two bosonic two-level particles, is47
22 |
where is the standard partial trace over the j-th particle Hilbert space. This partial trace does not have a straightforward connection with entanglement when indistinguishability cannot be neglected due to the symmetrisation postulate, as discussed here and in17. Nevertheless, it is a mathematical operation that still provides information on the structure of states.
is a forth order homogeneous polynomial in and but does not depend on their complex conjugates. The fundamental theorem of algebra states that, for any fixed , Eq. (21) either has at least one up to four distinct solutions, , or is a tautology.
is an eighth order polynomial that depends also on the complex conjugates , so that the fundamental theorem of algebra does not apply. Equation (22) can be a tautology, have at most eight solutions, say for fixed and , but can also have no solutions. If Eq. (22) were a tautology, all states in are transformed into states in . Nevertheless, Eq. (21) has at least a solution, and so at least one state in is transformed into a state in but also in . This result is impossible because of the linearity of A, unless for all that solve Eq. (21). The latter case implies , because the solutions of Eq. (21) span the full Hilbert space , as proven in the Lemma 1 in Methods. Thus, Eq. (22) has at most eight solutions for fixed and .
The above argument shows that, fixing and , there are at most a finite number of states (corresponding to coefficients ) that are sent to . If Eq. (21) has at most four solutions for fixed , there is also at most a finite number of states that are sent to . Remind, however, that we have relaxed the normalisation condition , and so can assume a continuity of values. Therefore, there are states that are sent out of , and this contradicts the hypothesis of Theorem 3.
In conclusion, the only possibility is that Eq. (21) is a tautology and Eq. (22) has no solutions. This is equivalent to the statement of Theorem 3.
The impossibility to define subsets of local operators, whose correlations correspond to entanglement-II, follows from Theorem 3 and from the analogous result for entanglement-I.
Theorem 4
Given two subsets and of operators that leave invariant, the factorisation condition (2) and Definition 2imply that either or consists only of operators proportional to the identity.
Proof
Theorem 3 implies that operators that generate subsets and are special cases of those considered in Theorem 1 and in Theorem 2. The statements in Theorem 1 and in Theorem 2 therefore holds also for the operators considered here. Moreover, separable-I states are also separable-II, so that Theorem 2 proves the inconsistency also between separability-II and locality.
Note that also the proof of Theorem 4 does not require the commutativity of the operator subsets. In the Supplementary Information, we prove a complete characterisation of operators that do not generate entanglement-II, and prove that their subsets do not form an algebra. This provides an alternative proof of Theorem 4 if the operator subsets and are algebras. We also show some examples in the Supplementary Information.
Entanglement-III
The last definition of entanglement is more elaborated than the previous ones. The simplest physical system, where entanglement-III exists, is made of two bosons with a spatial degree of freedom, , and an internal one, . This definition is relative to the projection onto a subspace of the single particle Hilbert space. We assume that such subspace is , as often assumed within this approach48. The general definition, shown in the Supplementary Information, leads in our case to the following.
Definition 3
(Entanglement-III48) The set of pure separable-III states is, in first and second quantization respectively,
23 |
24 |
All other pure states are entangled-III.
Let us introduce the following projectors in first quantisation
25 |
or in second quantisation
26 |
with , and , and define for any operator A. The support of is isomorphic to , and separable-III states in , namely , are in one-to-one correspondence with separable-I states in Eq. (5). In particular, all the results for entanglement-I hold for entanglement-III constrained to the support of . The support of is isomorphic to 17,41,49–52; therefore, separable-III states in , i.e. , are in one-to-one correspondence with two distinguishable two-level particles, . Finally, is the whole support of and isomorphic to .
The search for subsets of local operators requires a detailed analysis of contributions to the factorisation condition from each sector identified by the projectors (25). Nevertheless, the identification of operators that leave is not needed to prove the following Theorem.
Theorem 5
Given two subsets of operators, and , the factorisation condition (2) and Definition 3imply that either or consists only of operators proportional to the identity.
Proof
Consider separable-III states , with , , and . The factorisation condition (2) reads
27 |
Since and in Eq. (27) are arbitrary, the coefficient of each monomial must vanish whenever and , or and . Thus,
28 |
Apply now Lemma 2 in Methods where the functions therein are and , and the variables are the coefficients used to parametrise states and (see the discussion after Definition 3). Lemma 2 in Methods entails that at least one factor in Eq. (28) vanish for all separable-III states, i.e. either or for all and . Because and span the support of and respectively, then either or .
Assume that , as the other case is analogous. Comparing the coefficients of the monomial in the right and the left hand sides of Eq. (27), we obtain
for both and . The difference between the two cases ( and ) of the above equation is
29 |
Lemma 2 in Methods implies that at least one of the factors in Eq. (29) must be identically zero. If the term in brackets vanishes then and due to the arbitrariness of the separable-III states and (see Lemma 3 in Methods). Therefore, from the arbitrariness of , and we have proven Theorem 5. The case implies , because separable-III states and span the support of and respectively. At this point, we have proven that for any .
Choose separable-III states that form an orthonormal basis of the support of . Equation (28) implies
30 |
Using Eq. (30) in the comparison between the coefficients of the monomial in the left and right hand side of Eq. (27), we obtain for any
31 |
After plugging the above equation in the factorisation (27), and matching the coefficients of , we get
32 |
As above, Lemma 2 in Methods proves that at least one of the factors must identically vanish. According to Lemma 3 in Methods, the arbitrariness of separable-III states and further implies that either or for any . This conclusion, together with the property for proved above, entails Theorem 5.
Therefore, also entanglement-III is incompatible with any locality notion as sketched in the Introduction: expectations of products of local operators pertaining to different subsystems must factorise for all non-entangled state. We stress that commutativity between the operator subsets and have not been used in Theorem 5. This makes Theorem 5 a stronger result than analogous theorems for entanglement-I and entanglement-II. We show some examples in the Supplementary Information.
Discussion
For completeness, we report the other entanglement definitions that correspond to correlations between suitably defined subsystem operators17, generalising thus the Werner’s formulation to indistinguishable particles. These definitions are called mode-entanglement and SSR-entanglement. Mode-entanglement for N bosonic two-level particles is defined by the following.
Definition 4
(Mode-entanglement21–24) The set of pure mode-separable states is, in first and second quantization respectively,
33 |
34 |
All other pure states are mode-entangled.
This definition can be generalised to fermions substituting the symmetrization projector with the antisymmetrization projector or considering anticommuting creation operators: see17,28,53,54 for a complete discussion of the fermionic case. If , Definition 4 reduces to . Mode-entanglement depends on the choice of the mode basis as it accounts for quantum correlations between modes in the second quantization formalism, and is ubiquitous in quantum optics and quantum field theories, and also applied in several atomic and condensed matter systems (see references in the review17). The factorisation condition (2) is fulfilled if and only if the state therein is mode-separable17 when consists of all functions of and and of all functions of and . Indeed, operators , and AB do not generate mode-entanglement and are the local operators of this theory.
Non-vanishing SSR-entanglement requires that the single particle Hilbert space has at least four dimentions, and so we focus on the same system described for entanglement-III.
Definition 5
(SSR-entanglement18–20) The set of pure SSR-separable states is, in first and second quantization respectively,
35 |
36 |
All other pure states are SSR-entangled.
SSR-entanglement depends on the choice of the spatial basis , as entanglement-III does, and, recalling Eqs. (25) and (26), . Moreover, SSR-separable states in are isomorphic to and indeed represent states of particles effectively distinguished by their spatial localisations. The name superselection rule entanglement is due to the fact that Definition 5 is derived within the supports of the projectors , , (and their many-particle generalisations) and ignoring their superpositions17–20. The physical meaning of this superselection rule is that SSR-entanglement recovers standard entanglement when groups of particles can be effectively distinguished. SSR-entanglement is a constrained version of mode-entanglement since if and only if , with . Specializing the general argument in Ref.17 to the two-particle system described here, the compatibility with locality can be verified when is made of all functions of and and of all functions of and , as for mode-entanglement but with the further constraints for all , . Operators , and AB do not generate SSR-entanglement and are the local operators of this theory.
We analysed different definitions of entanglement for indistinguishable particles in the light of locality. In particular, entanglement is a form of quantum correlations between subsystems, and therefore entanglement is fully specified only after identifying subsystems. In many of the existing approaches, subsystems are vaguely considered to be particles. We have looked for operators whose correlations correspond to each notion of entanglement. These operators, that define the subsystems by identifying their measurable quantities, form commuting subalgebras, where commutativity entails independence of the subsystems. Nevertheless, we stress that we used neither the commutativity nor the algebra structure in our main proofs. Therefore, our results are more general than what we need for the analysis of entanglement.
The results of our investigation is that three of the five existing entanglement definitions are incompatible with any locality notion formalised as above, because they do not correspond to correlations either between particles or between more general and abstract subsystems. Indeed, for any couple of non-trivial operators there are non-entangled pure states that show correlations. Therefore, these definitions do not generalise the Werner’s formulation of entanglement11, i.e. the requirement (2) for pure separable states, to the domain of indistinguishable particles for any partitioning of the system. Their practical usefulness may be shown in the framework of different resource theories40 that do not share some of their properties with entanglement theory. Thus, our results open the way to a deeper investigation of connections between indistinguishable particles entanglement and other resource theories.
Our results are relevant when particle indistinguishability cannot be neglected (see Fig. 1). When, on the other hand, particles can be distinguished by means of unambiguos properties, i.e. orthogonal states of certain degrees of freedom like different position eigenstates41,49–52, then the standard theory of entanglement applies. Since entanglement of distisguishable particles is a resource for quantum technologies, our analysis shed light into the possibility to identify individually addressable subsystems when particle distinguishability cannot be implemented, as in miniaturised quantum devices with all degrees of freedom employed in the device functioning.
Methods
Lemma 1
The states that solve Eq. (21) span the whole symmetrised Hilbert space .
Proof
If Eq. (21) is a tautology, its solutions correspond to all states which form an overcomplete basis of the symmetrised Hilbert space . Therefore the statement is proved.
If Eq. (21) is not a tautology, it has at least one and at most four solutions for each fixed and fixed A, from the fundamental theorem of algebra. Denote by the state corresponding to one of these solutions with . Consider the rescaling , and assume that the new state is proportional to . Therefore and . We implicitly assumed that and are the same function, which is always possible because the polynomial depends only on the matrix A that is not changed.
Equations say that the function is homogeneous of degree one and therefore linear. This linear behaviour implies that , because is homogeneous in and . Therefore implies , but by construction. Therefore, and are linearly independent. We can iterate this argument with a second rescaling to find a third state linearly independent from the previous two. This proves the Theorem, since the symmetrised Hilbert space is three-dimensional.
Note that the linear span of solutions of Eq. (21) is not the space of solutions, because is not linear in .
Lemma 2
Given two rational functions f(x) and g(x) of several variables such that for all x in the domain of the two functions, then either or for all x.
Proof
Fix so that the two functions and either are identically zero or have a finite number of zeros . If both and have a finite number of zeros, after fixing , then there are infinitely many n-tuples x such that , contradicting the hypothesis of the Lemma.
Lemma 3
Given an operator A, if for any separable-III states and
37 |
then and .
Proof
Equation (37) implies that
38 |
with some independent of the supports of both and . Without loss of generality, we now focus on the first of equations (38), and consider the three cases with states represented as discussed before Theorem 5.
If , separable-III states can be represented as in Eq. (5). Since the state norm is , and from the arbitrariness of the coefficients , all monomials that appear only on the left-hand-side of Eq. (38), e.g. , must be multiplied by a vanishing coefficient. Moreover, the coefficients of the remaining monomials must match between the left and the right hand sides of Eq. (38). These requirements imply .
The case is similar, with the difference that separable-III states can be represented as and . Now, we must compare coefficients of monomials in , , and their complex conjugates. The result is .
The case is straightforward because all states are separable-III. Therefore, Eq. (38) must be fulfilled for all bases of the support of that is possible only if .
Supplementary Information
Acknowledgements
U. M. is financially supported by the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under the Marie Skłodowska-Curie grant agreement No. 754496 - FELLINI. T. J. F. J. and U. M. acknowledges the DAAD RISE Worldwide programme reference code HR-PH-4248.
Author contributions
U.M. conceived and supervised the project. T.J.F.J. and U.M. performed the analytic work, discussed the results, and wrote the paper.
Competing interests
The authors declare no competing interests.
Footnotes
Publisher's note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Supplementary Information
The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1038/s41598-021-94991-y.
References
- 1.Bell M, Gao S, editors. Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 Years of Bell’s Theorem. Cambridge University Press; 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Buhrman H, Cleve R, Massar S, de Wolf R. Nonlocality and communication complexity. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2010;82:665. doi: 10.1103/RevModPhys.82.665. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Braun D, et al. Quantum-enhanced measurements without entanglement. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2018;90:035006. doi: 10.1103/RevModPhys.90.035006. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Moreau P-A, Toninelli E, Gregory T, Padgett MJ. Imaging with quantum states of light. Nat. Rev. Phys. 2019;1:367. doi: 10.1038/s42254-019-0056-0. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Lund A. P, Bremner M. J, Ralph T. C. Quantum sampling problems, BosonSampling and quantum supremacy. npj Quantum Inf. 2017;3:15. doi: 10.1038/s41534-017-0018-2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Harrow AW, Montanaro A. Quantum computational supremacy. Nature. 2017;549:203. doi: 10.1038/nature23458. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Gisin N. Bell’s inequality holds for all non-product states. Phys. Lett. A. 1991;154:201. doi: 10.1016/0375-9601(91)90805-I. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Gisin N, Peres A. Bell’s inequality holds for all non-product states. Phys. Lett. A. 1992;162:15. doi: 10.1016/0375-9601(92)90949-M. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Sengupta, K., Zibakhsh, R., Chitambar, E. & Gour, G. Quantum Bell Nonlocality is Entanglement (2020). Preprint arXiv:2012.06918.
- 10.Chitambar E, Leung D, Mancinska L, Ozols M, Winter A. Everything you always wanted to know about LOCC (but were afraid to ask) Commun. Math. Phys. 2014;328:303. doi: 10.1007/s00220-014-1953-9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Werner RF. Quantum states with Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen correlations admitting a hidden-variable model. Phys. Rev. A. 1989;40:4277. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.40.4277. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Zanardi P. Virtual quantum subsystems. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2001;87:077901. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.87.077901. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Zanardi P, Lidar DA, Lloyd S. Quantum tensor product structures are observable induced. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2004;92:060402. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.92.060402. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Barnum H, Knill E, Ortiz G, Somma R, Viola L. A subsystem-independent generalization of entanglement. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2004;92:107902. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.92.107902. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Harshman NL, Ranade KS. Observables can be tailored to change the entanglement of any pure state. Phys. Rev. A. 2011;84:012303. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.84.012303. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Thirring W, Bertlmann RA, Köhler P, Narnhofer H. Entanglement or separability: The choice of how to factorize the algebra of a density matrix. Eur. Phys. J. D. 2011;64:181. doi: 10.1140/epjd/e2011-20452-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Benatti F, Floreanini R, Franchini F, Marzolino U. Entanglement in indistinguishable particle systems. Phys. Rep. 2020;878:1. doi: 10.1016/j.physrep.2020.07.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Wiseman HM, Vaccaro JA. Entanglement of indistinguishable particles shared between two parties. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2003;91:097902. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.91.097902. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Ichikawa T, Sasaki T, Tsutsui I. Separability of N-particle fermionic states for arbitrary partitions. J. Math. Phys. 2010;51:062202. doi: 10.1063/1.3399807. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Sasaki T, Ichikawa T, Tsutsui I. Entanglement of indistinguishable particles. Phys. Rev. A. 2011;83:012113. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.83.012113. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Zanardi P. Quantum entanglement in fermionic lattices. Phys. Rev. A. 2002;65:042101. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.65.042101. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Shi Y. Quantum entanglement of identical particles. Phys. Rev. A. 2003;67:024301. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.67.024301. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Schuch N, Verstraete F, Cirac JI. Quantum entanglement theory in the presence of superselection rules. Phys. Rev. A. 2004;70:042310. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.70.042310. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Benatti F, Floreanini R, Marzolino U. Sub-shot-noise quantum metrology with entangled identical particles. Ann. Phys. 2010;325:924. doi: 10.1016/j.aop.2010.01.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Benatti F, Floreanini R, Marzolino U. Bipartite entanglement in systems of identical particles: The partial transposition criterion. Ann. Phys. 2012;327:1304. doi: 10.1016/j.aop.2012.02.002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Benatti F, Floreanini R, Marzolino U. Entanglement robustness and geometry in systems of identical particles. Phys. Rev. A. 2012;85:042329. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.85.042329. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Marzolino U. Entanglement in dissipative dynamics of identical particles. EPL. 2013;104:40004. doi: 10.1209/0295-5075/104/40004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Benatti F, Floreanini R, Marzolino U. Entanglement in fermion systems and quantum metrology. Phys. Rev. A. 2014;89:032326. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.89.032326. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Balachandran AP, Govindarajan TR, de Queiroz AR, Reyes-Lega AF. Algebraic approach to entanglement and entropy. Phys. Rev. A. 2013;88:022301. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.88.022301. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Benatti F, Floreanini R. Entanglement in algebraic quantum mechanics: Majorana fermion systems. J. Phys. A. 2016;49:305303. doi: 10.1088/1751-8113/49/30/305303. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Cramer M, et al. Spatial entanglement of bosons in optical lattices. Nat. Commun. 2013;4:2161. doi: 10.1038/ncomms3161. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Killoran N, Cramer M, Plenio MB. Extracting entanglement from identical particles. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2014;112:150501. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.112.150501. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Ding L, Schilling C. Correlation paradox of the dissociation limit: A quantum information perspective. J. Chem. Theory Comput. 2020;16:7. doi: 10.1021/acs.jctc.9b00648. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Bratteli O, Robinson D. Operator Algebras and Quantum Statistical Mechanics. Springer; 1987. [Google Scholar]
- 35.Strocchi F. An Introduction to the Mathematical Structure of Quantum Mechanics. 2. World Scientific; 2008. [Google Scholar]
- 36.Kabernik O, Pollack J, Singh A. Quantum state reduction: Generalized bipartitions from algebras of observables. Phys. Rev. A. 2020;101:032303. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.101.032303. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Paskauskas R, You L. Quantum correlations in two-boson wave functions. Phys. Rev. A. 2001;64:042310. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.64.042310. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Eckert K, Schliemann J, Bruß D, Lewenstein M. Quantum correlations in systems of indistinguishable particles. Ann. Phys. 2002;299:88. doi: 10.1006/aphy.2002.6268. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Grabowski, J., Marek Ku, M. & Marmo, G. Entanglement for multipartite systems of indistinguishable particles. J. Phys. A44, 175302 (2011).
- 40.Morris B, et al. Entanglement between identical particles is a useful and consistent resource. Phys. Rev. X. 2020;10:041012. [Google Scholar]
- 41.Herbut F. How to distinguish identical particles. Am. J. Phys. 2001;69:207. doi: 10.1119/1.1288130. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Schliemann J, Cirac JI, Kuś M, Lewenstein M, Loss D. Quantum correlations in two-fermion systems. Phys. Rev. A. 2001;64:022303. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.64.022303. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Plastino AR, Manzano D, Dehesa JS. Separability criteria and entanglement measures for pure states of N identical fermions. EPL. 2009;86:20005. doi: 10.1209/0295-5075/86/20005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Li YS, Zeng B, Liu XS, Long GL. Entanglement in a two-identical-particle system. Phys. Rev. A. 2001;64:054302. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.64.054302. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Ghirardi G, Marinatto L, Weber T. Entanglement and properties of composite quantum systems: A conceptual and mathematical analysis. J. Stat. Phys. 2002;108:49. doi: 10.1023/A:1015439502289. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Iemini F, Vianna RO. Computable measures for the entanglement of indistinguishable particles. Phys. Rev. A. 2013;87:022327. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.87.022327. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Ghirardi G, Marinatto L. General criterion for the entanglement of two indistinguishable particles. Phys. Rev. A. 2004;70:012109. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.70.012109. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Lo Franco R, Compagno G. Quantum entanglement of identical particles by standard information-theoretic notions. Sci. Rep. 2016;6:20603. doi: 10.1038/srep20603. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.De Muynck WM. Distinguishable- and indistinguishable-particle descriptions of systems of identical particles. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 1975;14:327. doi: 10.1007/BF01807861. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Herbut, F. How to Distinguish Identical Particles. The General Case. Preprint arXiv:quant-ph/0611049 (2006).
- 51.Tichy MC, de Melo F, Kuś M, Mintert F, Buchleitner A. Entanglement of identical particles and the detection process. Fortschr. Phys. 2013;61:225. doi: 10.1002/prop.201200079. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Cunden FD, Di Martino S, Facchi P, Florio G. Spatial separation and entanglement of identical particles. Int. J. Quantum Inform. 2014;12:1461001. doi: 10.1142/S0219749914610012. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Bañuls M-C, Cirac JI, Wolf MM. Entanglement in fermionic systems. Phys. Rev. A. 2007;76:022311. doi: 10.1103/PhysRevA.76.022311. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Szalay S, et al. Fermionic systems for quantum information people. J. Phys. A. 2021 doi: 10.1088/1751-8121/ac0646. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.