Abstract
A central question in neuroscience concerns the relationship between consciousness and its physical substrate. Here, we argue that a richer characterization of consciousness can be obtained by viewing it as constituted of distinct information-theoretic elements. In other words, we propose a shift from quantification of consciousness—viewed as integrated information—to its decomposition. Through this approach, termed Integrated Information Decomposition (ΦID), we lay out a formal argument that whether the consciousness of a given system is an emergent phenomenon depends on its information-theoretic composition—providing a principled answer to the long-standing dispute on the relationship between consciousness and emergence. Furthermore, we show that two organisms may attain the same amount of integrated information, yet differ in their information-theoretic composition. Building on ΦID’s revised understanding of integrated information, termed ΦR, we also introduce the notion of ΦR-ing ratio to quantify how efficiently an entity uses information for conscious processing. A combination of ΦR and ΦR-ing ratio may provide an important way to compare the neural basis of different aspects of consciousness. Decomposition of consciousness enables us to identify qualitatively different ‘modes of consciousness’, establishing a common space for mapping the phenomenology of different conscious states. We outline both theoretical and empirical avenues to carry out such mapping between phenomenology and information-theoretic modes, starting from a central feature of everyday consciousness: selfhood. Overall, ΦID yields rich new ways to explore the relationship between information, consciousness, and its emergence from neural dynamics.
Keywords: consciousness, information decomposition, integrated information theory, selfhood, phenomenology
Introduction
A central aim in both neuroscience and philosophy of mind is understanding the relationship between consciousness and its physical substrate. The past two decades have seen a proliferation of theoretical, experimental, and philosophical work on this topic (Crick and Koch 2003; Friston 2012; Tononi and Koch 2015; Koch et.al. 2016; Tononi et al. 2016; Parr and Friston 2019; Kleiner 2020). Additionally, an important and related question to how consciousness arises from matter concerns a mathematically precise and conceptually clear account of what constitutes ‘emergence’ (Tononi et al. 1998; Friston et al. 2014; Hoel et al. 2016; De Caro and Grasso 2017; Palacios et al. 2017, 2019; Hesp et al. 2019; Cea 2020). The present work is situated at the convergence of these two fundamental research avenues: i.e. in this paper we seek to contribute to the formalization of the relationship between consciousness and its underlying physical substrate and elucidate to what extent this relationship can be rigorously understood in terms of emergence. To this end, we demonstrate the value of leveraging novel information-theoretic approaches to shed light on the nature of consciousness.
Here, we understand consciousness to be that which is lost during dreamless sleep and deep anaesthesia and recovered upon awakening (Schwitzgebel 2016). Following William James’s celebrated notion of the stream of consciousness, we take the stance that subjective experiences dynamically unfold over time. For this reason, when seeking to understand the aspects of the physical world that correspond to subjective experiences, and give rise to them, we direct our attention to neural dynamics. Indeed, neural dynamics have recently been proposed as a ‘common currency’ between brain and mind (Northoff et al. 2020), and a growing body of empirical work has demonstrated—through a variety of neuroimaging modalities and analytic approaches—that considering neural dynamics can provide powerful insights into consciousness and its alterations (Barttfeld et al. 2015; Atasoy et al. 2017, 2018; Uhrig et al. 2018; Deco et al. 2019; Demertzi et al. 2019; Lee. et al. 2019; Lord et al. 2019; Luppi et al. 2019, 2020b, 2020c, 2021b; Vlisides et al. 2019; Dinesh et al. 2020; Huang et al. 2020; Standage et al. 2020; Varley et al. 2020a, 2020b; Cavanna et al. 2018; Cao et al. 2019; Cai et al. 2020; Eagleman et al. 2019; Hahn et al. 2021; Hutchinson et al. 2014).
Thus, both theoretical and empirical reasons lead us to adopt a process-theoretic framework to the study of consciousness. Shannon’s information theory is particularly well-suited to address process-theoretic approaches such as the one adopted here, because it enables the study of dynamical processes in a way that is not committed to any specific physical instantiation. This is not to say that the physicality of the system does not matter for the instantiation of consciousness: some material substrates may be more or less suitable (e.g. in terms of degrees of freedom) to sustain the dynamics on which consciousness depends (see esp. Barrett 2014). Rather, information theory enables us to focus on the dynamics and their properties, abstracted from considerations about physical instantiation or neuroimaging modality.
From quantification of consciousness to its decomposition
The close relationship between consciousness and information is a key aspect of the well-known Integrated Information Theory of consciousness (hereafter, IIT) (Tononi et al. 1994; Balduzzi and Tononi 2008; Oizumi et al. 2014; Tononi et al. 2016; Tononi 2008 Manifesto). A core intuition from IIT is that the ‘integration of information’ represents a fundamental aspect of consciousness—and therefore, quantifying integrated information (suitably defined, as we explore in ‘Technical preliminaries’) enables an effective quantification of consciousness.
Quantification is a key step in the scientific process, and the notion that consciousness could be quantified has contributed in no small part to the scientific study of consciousness in the last two decades. After quantification, decomposition into fundamental elements can be a fruitful next step in the scientific process, driving major advances in fields such as physics and chemistry over the last two centuries. As an illustrative example, knowing whether the clear liquid in one’s glass is composed by twice as many hydrogen atoms as oxygen atoms, or oxygen and hydrogen in equal parts, represents the difference between drinking refreshing water or poisonous hydrogen peroxide. We believe that understanding the information-theoretic composition of consciousness will be similarly crucial for its scientific characterization.
Within this context, the aim of this paper is to shed light on consciousness from an information-theoretic perspective by capitalizing on major advances in information theory, specifically within the recent framework of Partial Information Decomposition (PID) (Bertschinger et al. 2014; Griffith and Koch 2014; Wibral et al. 2017; Lizier et al. 2018) and its multivariate extension, Integrated Information Decomposition (ΦID) (Mediano et al. 2021). Shannon’s seminal results on information theory are mainly focused on information transmission between a single source and a single target; PID extends classic information-theoretic approaches to systems involving multiple sources of information (Wibral et al. 2017). Moreover, the more recent development of ΦID further extends PID to scenarios involving multiple targets as well as multiple sources (Mediano et al. 2021). Such an extension is necessary if we are to investigate complex, multivariate systems with intricate causal relationships, of which the human brain is a prime example (Turkheimer et al. 2021; Varley et al. 2020b). Thus, information decomposition—and ΦID in particular—proves especially valuable for our purposes, being ideally suited to accommodate the multifaceted dynamics that characterize neural activity.
Here we propose a shift in perspective beyond the information-theoretic quantification of consciousness and towards its decomposition into fundamental information-theoretic elements. For this purpose, we explore the consequences of viewing the core intuition that consciousness can be quantified in terms of integrated information in the light of ΦID. Note that we are not thereby committed to any of IIT’s additional theoretical positions: for instance, we remain agnostic on whether integrated information is identical with consciousness or merely co-extensive with it under certain descriptions. Likewise, our approach does not deal with ‘composition’ in the IIT sense of which qualia contribute to a specific experience (see section: From bits to bats): rather, our focus is entirely on the notion of consciousness as quantifiable in terms of information and what the decomposition of this information can tell us about consciousness.
Overall, this paper has two key goals. First, to demonstrate that understanding the information-theoretic composition of consciousness may be crucial to obtain insights about what consciousness is—and the various modes in which it can be configured. Our second major goal is the formal demonstration, within the ΦID framework, that consciousness can comprise both emergent and non-emergent phenomena—which we demonstrate based on its information-theoretic composition.
We call this ΦID-based approach to consciousness ‘Psy-ID’ (ΨID), as it is the result of an application of ΦID to psychological phenomena. Thus, ΨID is a theoretical framework that seeks to understand consciousness and other mental phenomena using insights from the broadly applicable mathematics of information decomposition—and ΦID in particular. Importantly, this framework also sheds new light on other prominent theories of consciousness such as the Global Neuronal Workspace Theory (Dehaene and Changeuz 2011; Mashour et al. 2020) by providing an information-theoretic definition of the workspace in terms of synergistic interactions (Luppi et al. 2020b). In contrast to other theoretical accounts of consciousness, ΨID provides a formal framework that is applicable to neuroimaging data, which enables a range of practical investigations on such observed dynamics (Mediano et al. 2021; Luppi et al. 2020a). This is especially important because we take it as imperative to our theoretical endeavours to provide predictions about consciousness that can be tested—and possibly falsified—by our current neuroimaging methods.
The rest of this paper is structured as follows. First, ‘Technical preliminaries’ provides an accessible overview of the main information-theoretic intuitions and basic premises on which our work builds. Then, ‘Theoretical contributions’ introduces ΨID to explicate the ramifications of ΦID for understanding consciousness and the neural dynamics on which it depends. Therein, we specify core terminology that is relevant to the hypotheses and predictions we propose in the third section, ‘Empirical predictions’. In this final section, we explore testable hypotheses and predictions as applied to recent experimental work on psychedelics and consciousness. This paper concludes with a series of remarks on the implications of ΨID and its potential limitations.
Technical preliminaries
This section develops the formal intuitions and basic premises behind IIT, from which our paper takes its start. We then follow with an elaboration of the PID framework and its extension to IIT, called ΦID.
The mind’s Φ: integrated information theory
The starting point of our investigation is the notion that consciousness can be quantified in terms of the integrated information of a system—the fundamental intuition behind the early development of IIT (Tononi 2004; Balduzzi and Tononi 2008). Stemming from the seminal ideas put forward by Tononi et al. (1994), IIT’s core premise (which we share) is that the brain can be comprehensively characterized by its dynamics—i.e. the way in which the brain’s activity unfolds over time (Tononi and Edelman 1998; Northoff et al. 2020). Correspondingly, these dynamics allow the brain’s current state to contain some information about its past and future states. Mathematically, this information that ‘flows’ from the past to the future of a dynamical system can be captured by the so-called time-delayed mutual information (TDMI) (Barrett and Seth 2011), denoted as , where and indicate the state of the system at consecutive times t and t+1. Broadly speaking, TDMI provides a first step towards quantifying the dynamical structure of a complex system (James et al. 2011).
A further refinement on TDMI is to consider not only the overall amount of information, but also its spatiotemporal distribution. Different parts of the brain exchange information constantly—and the existence and relevance of these precise informational patterns is uncontroversial in cognitive neuroscience. Moreover, although a precise, theoretically-based measure remains to be discovered, there is mounting evidence that the patterns of information that spread across the brain are related to consciousness (Casali et al. 2013; Luppi et al. 2020b).
One of the key insights of Tononi, Sporns, and Edelman was to realize that this information must be shared across the brain in particular ways, such that it is simultaneously integrated (so the brain can behave as a whole) and differentiated (so its parts can perform independent processing). These ideas materialized into specific formulae to quantify integration and differentiation in the brain. In particular, the first such quantity to explicitly include the brain’s dynamics into its formulation was the measure of integrated information initially proposed by Balduzzi and Tononi (2008) and subsequently revised to be applicable to experimental time-series data1 by Barrett and Seth (2011). For a given bipartition of into two parts , the measure is given by
.
As above, here denotes the state of the system as a whole at time t denotes the ith part of X at time t (and likewise for and ). Thus, this measure compares the information flow between the past and the future (as captured by TDMI) observed in the whole system X with the flow observed within each of its parts—for this reason it is also referred to as ‘whole-minus-sum’ Φ (Mediano et al. 2021).2 This measure is easy to compute (compared with other Φ measures) (Oizumi et al. 2016) and represents a noteworthy attempt to capture the powerful intuitions behind IIT. However, once the original formulation from Balduzzi and Tononi is rendered suitable for practical empirical application (Barrett and Seth 2011;Barrett and Mediano 2019), the resulting mathematical formulation has known shortcomings, including the fact that it can yield negative values in some cases—which are hard to interpret, as a system cannot intuitively be ‘negatively integrated’ or have negative consciousness (Oizumi et al. 2016; Mediano et al. 2018). In the following, we show how these shortcomings can be overcome by means of the mathematical framework of ΦID.
Note that the formula for ΦWMS above stems from what is known as IIT 2.0, but TDMI is by no means the only way of quantifying the dynamical structure of a system: indeed, subsequent developments in IIT 3.0 used alternative metrics with a more explicit focus on causal interpretations (Oizumi et al. 2014), which were in turn replaced in the latest iteration known as IIT 4.0 (Barbosa et al. 2020). Our rationale for following the quantification of integrated information from IIT 2.0 rather than these later versions is that IIT 2.0 is the last version of IIT to be within the scope of Shannon’s information theory. Since the goal of the present work is to investigate the potential of information decomposition to shed light on integrated information and consciousness (see section: Theoretical contributions), the more recent versions of IIT are not suitable for our purposes—thereby requiring us to work with the IIT 2.0 formulation of Φ.
Information decomposition
The TDMI, on which ΦWMS depends, is a special case of Shannon’s mutual information, I. On a conceptual level, this ‘information’ can be understood in several distinct but converging ways (Shannon 1948; Hellman and Raviv 1970; Feder and Merhav 1994; Jaynes 2003; Parrondo et al. 2015). While extremely versatile, Shannon’s information theory is (mainly) confined to interactions between pairs of variables (e.g. a sender and a receiver), and it is not equipped to study the information that multiple parts of a system have about each other’s dynamical evolution.
Part of the necessary technical equipment for such analysis was introduced by Williams and Beer (2010) with their framework of PID. PID, in short, decomposes the total information that two sources give about a target into four distinct ‘partial information atoms’, typically called ‘synergistic’, ‘redundant’, and ‘unique’ information [note that for the sake of simplicity, throughout this work we will only consider the case of bivariate systems: for details of generalization to more than two variables, we refer the reader to Mediano et al. (2021)].
As an illustrative example of redundant, unique, and synergistic information, consider humans’ two sources of visual information about the world: the eyes. The two eyes provide in part the same information, which is the information that is not lost when closing one or the other eye. This information is therefore carried redundantly by both sources. However, information about the very edge of the visual field is unique to each eye: this unique information is lost when the corresponding eye is closed. Finally, closing either eye will also remove stereoscopic information about depth: this information is not carried by either eye alone, but rather it requires both eyes together, arising synergistically from their interaction.
Thus, it is important to note that atoms are ways in which the information is being carried and should not be confused with the sources of information that are doing the carrying, nor with the specific content that is being carried: any reference to e.g. ‘synergy’ or ‘redundancy’ should be understood as shorthand for ‘information carried synergistically’ and ‘information carried redundantly’, and likewise for other atoms. Therefore, as a way of example, if both my eyes show me that there is a red apple in front of me, then each eye (source) is carrying redundantly (atom) information about an apple (target), with the information in question being that the apple is red (content).
By allowing us to distinguish qualitatively different phenomena involving multiple information sources that cannot be disentangled by classic information theory (Rosas et al. 2016), PID moves beyond Shannon’s information theory (James and Crutchfield 2017). These novel capabilities of PID have found fruitful application in multiple areas of neuroscience, from spike trains to whole-brain dynamics (Stramaglia et al. 2014; Wibral et al. 2017).
Decomposing information flow
Thanks to the new lens provided by PID, it is now possible to decompose the information that the past state of each part of the system, , , carries about the future of the whole system, . Formally, for a system with two parts, PID states that the information that part i has about the future of the system can be decomposed as
where is the so-called ‘redundant information’ provided by the sources (here, the parts of the system) and is the information that provides uniquely. Similarly, the joint mutual information (i.e. information that the past state of the system as a whole carries about its future) is decomposed as
Here we see that in addition to redundancy and unique atoms, this expression includes , which accounts for the so-called ‘synergistic’ information: information provided by both sources jointly, but not separately (Fig. 1a).
Thus, PID provides the means to understand how each part of the system carries information about the future state of the system as a whole, decomposing this information flow into redundant, unique and synergistic contributions. However, a key drawback of PID is that, while it is naturally applicable to multiple source variables, it can only be applied to scenarios with a single target. Thus, within the PID framework the future state of the system is still considered as a monolithic entity, without being able to consider the future state of each part individually. To resolve this shortcoming and extend the range of applicability of PID, Mediano et al. (2021) put forward the framework of ΦID, which forms the mathematical basis of our proposal. Formally, ΦID is a multi-target extension of PID that can identify the redundant, unique, and synergistic components of the information that multiple source variables carry about multiple target variables.
Specifically, the information that is carried in terms of each of the original four PID atoms (Red, Un1, Un2, and Syn, see Fig. 1a) at one point in time, at the next point in time may be carried as the same atom, or as any of the other atoms. Therefore, there are 4 × 4 = 16 combinations of PID atoms (Fig. 1b), which correspond to the decomposition established by ΦID. For instance, denotes the information that is initially carried uniquely by the first source and subsequently becomes carried synergistically. For more details about the interpretation of each of the ΦID atoms, and the generalization to more than two variables, we refer the reader to Mediano et al. (2021).
Taken together, PID and ΦID constitute valuable tools to refine our understanding of information processing in dynamical systems—and, therefore, can be used to refine our theories of any phenomenon that depends on such information processing, like consciousness. In the same way as PID allows us to refine our understanding of mutual information, we will see that ΦID allows us to refine our understanding of ΦWMS.
Refining Φ through ΦID
ΦID makes it possible to decompose the information flow between the past and future states of each part of a system. Thus, a key feature of ΦID for our purposes is that it makes PID applicable to dynamical processes—including neural dynamics. A growing body of recent work has demonstrated that considering dynamical aspects of the brain can shed critical light on various aspects of consciousness (Northoff et al. 2020). For example, it has been shown that brain dynamics are significantly altered when consciousness is suppressed by anaesthesia or severe brain injury (Luppi et al. 2019; Luppi et al. 2021a; Huang et al. 2020; Demertzi et al. 2019; Barttfeld et al. 2015), or altered by psychedelics (Atasoy et al. 2017; Lord et al. 2019; Luppi et al. 2020c, 2021b). These results highlight the key role of neural dynamics for consciousness, vindicating the approach adopted by Tononi et al. (1998).
Specifically, ΦID allows us to decompose the total information flow from the past to the future [TDMI, introduced above as ] into a range of modes of information dynamics, which can be used to deepen our understanding of various dynamical phenomena observed in the brain. A deeper understanding of ΦWMS and its drawbacks, such as the reasons why it can adopt negative values, can be gained by decomposing it into its constituent information atoms.
Let us recall that ΦID decomposes the TDMI of a dynamical system with two parts into 16 disjoint atoms [illustrated in Fig. 1(b)]. Of those 16 atoms, it can be shown mathematically (Mediano et al. 2021) that 10 are represented in ΦWMS (Fig. 2a): seven correspond to all the synergistic information in the system, two correspond to the information transferred from one part to the other, and, importantly, one redundancy atom with a negative sign. Through this decomposition of ΦWMS one can understand why ΦWMS can sometimes take negative values: the subtraction of the redundancy atoms implies that ΦWMS will be negative in redundancy-dominated systems, whenever redundancy is greater than the sum of synergy and information transfer. Note that transfer and synergy are rather different phenomena: while transfer refers to information that ‘moves’ from one variable to another, synergy corresponds to phenomena that involve both variables, but cannot be seen in any of them when they are examined separately (Mediano et al. 2021).
Leveraging ΦID, a revised measure of integrated information, termed ‘ΦR’, can then be formulated by focusing on the synergy and transfer components and dropping the negative redundancy atom from the definition of integrated information (Mediano et al. 2021). Specifically, ΦR is the sum of synergistic and transfer atoms, and it is thereby guaranteed to be non-negative. Thus, the information decomposition of ΦWMS provided by ΦID can successfully identify the source of Φ’s theoretical difficulties and provide a straightforward solution. In addition to the theoretical improvement (which will be further discussed in Section ‘A tale of ice and ΦR: From neural dynamics to the ΦR-ing ratio’), there is also recent evidence that ΦR also provides empirical advantages over the original formulation: unlike ΦWMS, ΦR is reduced between the same sets of brain regions both in patients with chronic disorders of consciousness and during loss of consciousness induced by the intravenous anaesthetic, propofol (Luppi et al. 2020b). Importantly, reductions in ΦR were reversed when participants recovered consciousness after anaesthesia, demonstrating the relevance of ΦR for supporting human consciousness. Thus, given the theoretical advantages of ΦR over Φ outlined here, as well as these recently demonstrated empirical benefits (Luppi et al. 2020b), we will consider ΦR as our primary metric of integrated information and conscious level throughout the rest of this work.
A deepness in the Φ: quantifying causal emergence
Another important feature of ΦID is that it provides a mathematical framework to build a formal, quantitative definition of causal emergence (Rosas et al. 2020a). Technically, the ΦID account of causal emergence rests on the following definitions. First, we say that a feature is ‘supervenient’ on the instantaneous state of the system at time t (denoted by ) if is a function of , so that there is nothing about that can be predicted from the system’s previous state, , that cannot be already predicted from the system’s current state, . Then, we say that a supervenient feature is ‘causally emergent’ if it has predictive power about the future evolution of that is unique (in the PID sense) with respect to the state of each part of the system.
Causal emergence is therefore defined here as the property of supervenient features to provide predictive power that cannot be explained from underlying microscale phenomena. In this manner, the coexistence of supervenience and irreducible predictive power of emergence—that have been previously thought as paradoxical (Bedau 1997, 2002)—can be resolved by operationalizing supervenience in terms of instantaneous relationships between the system and its features and identifying emergence with predictive power across time. Thus, a feature could be supervenient without being causally emergent, but not vice versa.
Crucially, the unique predictive power enabled by emergent features is quantified by ΦID. It is possible to prove that, under relatively general assumptions (Rosas etal. 2020b), a system’s capacity to host causally emergent features depends directly on how synergistic the system’s dynamics are. Furthermore, ΦID allows us to distinguish two qualitatively different types of emergence: ‘downward causation’, in which an emergent feature has unique predictive power over individual parts; and ‘causal decoupling’, in which it has unique predictive power not over any constituent, but only over the system as a whole (Figs 2b and 3).
Interestingly, causal decoupling corresponds to the persistent synergies in the system (top atoms in the ΦID lattice of Fig. 2b), which can be thought of as ‘the macroscale having causal influence on the macroscale, above and beyond the microscale effects’ (Rosas et al. 2020a) (Fig. 2b). Microscale and macroscale are then related by downward (macro-to-micro) causation, as well as upward (micro-to-macro) causation, which respectively correspond to transformations of information from and to synergy. The distinction between supervenience and emergence (i.e. causal decoupling and downward causation) is also illustrated in Fig. 3.
Note that the notion of causal emergence is not new, dating back at least to the book Problems of Life and Mind by George Lewes (Lewes 1879/2012; Turkheimer et al. 2021), with several proposed quantifications (see e.g. Bar-Yam 2004; Seth 2008), including in the context of IIT (Hoel et al. 2013, 2016). While the intervention-based approach of Hoel and colleagues has its own interest and domain of applicability, it does not fit well with our framework—which is not concerned with interventions, but is instead predicated in terms of information decomposition. Therefore, here we follow the approach introduced in Rosas et al. (2020a), while noting that future work may fruitfully combine these different approaches.
Theoretical contributions: ΨID
To recapitulate, the aim of the present work is to provide a shift from the quantification of consciousness (viewed as integrated information) to its decomposition and demonstrate how understanding consciousness in terms of ΦID atoms can shed light on several aspects of consciousness, including its relationship with emergence. If the close relationship between mental and neural dynamics assumed here turns out to be correct, and integrated information (ΦR) happens to be a valid metric of conscious level, then our ΨID framework is ideally suited to provide insight on the role of the different ‘modes’ of neural dynamics—as determined by the ΦID atoms—in supporting various aspects of mental phenomena.
Rising ΦR: quantifying consciousness as an emergent property
There has been abundant and vigorous philosophical debate over whether consciousness is an emergent phenomenon (Feinberg and Mallot 2020). By (i) understanding consciousness as integrated information, (ii) decomposing it into its constituent information-theoretic atoms through ΦID, and then (iii) viewing those atoms in terms of causal emergence, we are in a position to establish a grounded, formal, and falsifiable way to address this problem within the ΨID framework—representing the first core contribution of this paper.
In order to fully develop this argument, let us start noting that the ΦID decomposition of ΦR in Fig. 2a and of emergence in Fig. 2b shows that consciousness (quantified by ΦR) comprises the atoms of emergence among its constituents, but also comprises additional atoms that are beyond the scope of emergence. The implications of this mathematical fact are profound and far-reaching. In effect, note that nothing in IIT or ΦID mandates that a given system should exhibit ‘all’ atoms that constitute ΦR in order to be conscious: all that is required is the presence of at least one of ΦR’s constituent atoms with non-zero value. Following this rationale, we can draw two conclusions about the relationship between consciousness and emergence, based purely on a system’s information decomposition
Consciousness (integrated information) ‘can’ be an emergent phenomenon: there could be systems whose ΦR derives (entirely or in part) from emergent ΦID atoms.
Consciousness ‘does not have’ to be emergent: there could also be systems whose ΦR derives entirely from ΦID atoms that do not enter into the composition of emergence (e.g. information transfer or non-emergent synergy atoms).
Therefore, thanks to our information-decomposition approach to both consciousness and emergence, we can now see that the original question ‘Is consciousness an emergent phenomenon’ was fundamentally underspecified. Specifically, it was underspecified because neither consciousness nor emergence are monolithic constructs, but rather they are both constituted by multiple information-theoretic atoms, and—crucially—only some of the atoms that constitute integrated information are emergent. Once this is understood, the answer becomes clear: some possible kinds of consciousness are emergent, others are not, and others may comprise both emergent and non-emergent atoms—in a way that is amenable to empirical investigation.
A tale of ice and ΦR: from neural dynamics to the ΦR-ing ratio
Decomposing ΦR can also provide another important insight about the nature of consciousness. Since not all atoms enter into the composition of ΦR, dynamical processes with the same total amount of information flow (quantified by the TDMI) can still differ in their ΦR, and—conversely—organisms with the same ΦR can differ in TDMI (Fig. 4). The proportion of TDMI that is accounted for by ΦR, which we may refer to as the ‘ΦR-ing ratio’, can then be thought as quantifying the efficiency with which the organism transforms information into consciousness—its ‘nougenic rate’. In other words, cognitive architectures can differ in the ‘consciousness bang’ that they provide for a given ‘informational buck.’
Note that the ΦR-ing ratio is in one respect closer than ΦR to the original formulation of Φ, in terms of scaling negatively with redundancy. Original ΦWMS explicitly removed redundancy from the quantification of integrated information, but this led to the theoretical flaw that the resulting quantity was not guaranteed to be lower-bound by zero and could instead be negative if redundancy dominated the system (see Section ‘Refining Φ through ΦID’). Being predicated as the ratio of ΦR to TDMI, the ΦR-ing ratio implicitly takes redundancy into account, as a component of TDMI; in fact, the more redundancy there is in a system, the lower the ΦR-ing ratio will be even if ΦR is high overall. In other words, both ΦWMS and the ΦR-ing ratio acknowledge that there is an intuitive difference between a system where much of the information is redundant, and one that instead prioritizes dynamics related to consciousness (ΦR), and is therefore efficient in its ability to turn information into consciousness. The relationship between Φ and ΦR is illustrated in Fig. 4.
At this stage we will not take a stance on whether the part of TDMI that does not contribute to ΦR (e.g. the redundancy) is to be completely ignored from the study of consciousness—other than as contributing to the calculation of the ΦR-ing ratio—or whether perhaps it could be regarded as ‘preconscious’ or ‘potential consciousness’.
Thus, we argue that it can be beneficial to characterize information-processing systems with both ΦR and ΦR-ing ratio, since they provide complementary views on integration information. Therefore, it should be clear that our proposed ΦR-ing ratio is not intended to replace ΦR, but rather to complement it, thereby enabling a more encompassing framework for quantifications of consciousness.
Carved from ΦR: carving consciousness at its joints
Following a similar reasoning, an even more fundamental observation afforded by information decomposition is that even when two systems have the same ΦR and the same ΦR-ing ratio, they may be entirely different in the composition of their ΦR. In fact, no single ΦID atom is essential for ΦR, suggesting that ‘two systems may have the same ΦR despite not sharing any of its constituent atoms’ (e.g. a purely emergent system versus a transfer-only system). This possibility raises the fundamental question of whether different ΦID atoms may correspond to ‘different ways of being conscious’.
Implicitly, IIT is committed to an affirmative answer to this question: some ΦID atoms—it posits—are experienced and contribute to the system’s consciousness (integrated information), while other atoms are not: there is nothing it is like to instantiate those atoms (note that this is not the same as the problem of qualia; see section: From bits to bats). In contrast, ΨID suggests a richer perspective on this issue, by raising the possibility that different information-theoretic atoms may correspond to fundamentally different ‘ways of being conscious’—or, as we call them, ‘modes of consciousness’: broad-strokes aspects of how consciousness is subjectively experienced, which may be more or less extended in time.
Illustrative examples of specific modes of consciousness may include the selflessness experienced during deep meditation or under the effects of psychedelic drugs; or the general way that depression may feel to those suffering from it (see Colombetti and Ratcliffe 2012; Seth and Friston 2016; Deane 2020; Deane et al. 2020). Note also that although empirical evidence suggests that different cognitive functions rely on different information-theoretic atoms (Luppi et al. 2020a), our focus here is on altered states of consciousness, rather than normal fluctuations within day-to-day cognitive states.
In other words, ΨID contends that beyond the total amount of integrated information in an organism, additional insight may be gleaned from knowing its specific information-theoretic composition, which can be investigated through ΦID. By investigating the phenomenology associated with specific atoms, these ‘modes of consciousness’ may provide a way to eventually understand the phenomenology of different states of consciousness from the third-person perspective—as explained in the next section.
From bits to bats
To demonstrate how ΨID can enrich our understanding of consciousness, we contend that if integrated information is an effective measure of conscious level, then the corollaries obtained from ΨID would bring us one step closer to addressing the famous conundrum that has dogged the philosophy of mind: ‘What it is like to be a bat’. That is, even though we elect to use the term ‘modes of consciousness’, and this term is different in its extension from the debate on qualia (for which Nagel’s (1974) is typically placed as the cornerstone), it may still allow progress in that matter.
The alchemists of old sought to turn lead into gold and failed mainly because their understanding of these substances reached only the level of their surface properties (shiny or dull, yellow, or grey). Today, thanks to our understanding of atomic composition, turning lead into gold via nuclear transmutation is feasible (although not financially wise). Likewise, ΨID may represent a similar change of reference frame for our understanding of consciousness: rather than talking of ‘human consciousness’ or ‘bat consciousness’ tout court (like alchemists conceived of gold and lead as ‘substances’), we propose that it may be a more proficuous avenue to consider their respective atomic constitutions in terms of ΦID and think in terms of information atoms rather than ‘molecules’. Put differently, rather than trying to perform the mental ‘human-to-bat’ conversion all at once, as Nagel proposed, an atomic understanding of integrated information may provide us with a Rosetta stone to guide a more nuanced comparison.
More generally, we claim that thinking in terms of ‘modes’ or ‘kinds’ of consciousness may be advantageous for the exploration of conscious states within, and potentially also across, organisms3. From this point of view, the work of Nagel may be seen as shaping the debate too narrowly, focusing the discussion on fine-grained aspects of being a bat (flying through the air, echolocating its prey, etc.), when it is unclear how much progress can be made from such a starting point towards truly understanding ‘what it is like to be a bat’. We contend that failure to solve the question on Nagel’s terms should not prescribe scientific pessimism, as it does not follow that ‘every’ aspect of bat consciousness is foreclosed from investigation. In fact, we claim that while the fine-grained details related to contents associated with certain qualia may be highly specific—and hence possibly incommensurable—one can still compare the broad-stroke modes. Indeed, if our approach proves viable, then there may be relevant inferences to be drawn in comparing quantified modes of consciousness via their corresponding ΦID atoms between different systems, which could lead to insightful phylogenetic or cognitive similarities between conscious creatures.
To illustrate this point, let us focus on the challenge of seeking a ΦID atomic decomposition of ‘what it is like to be a human experiencing an altered state of consciousness’, which can be thought as a first step paving a road towards addressing conscious experiences of other species. An atomic understanding of what it may be like to be in a given state of altered consciousness is based on three elements.
A description of the atomic composition of the integrated information generated by the human cognitive architecture under baseline conditions, to act as a reference point [although it should be noted that the question of defining a ‘baseline human state’ is itself not trivial, as even so-called ‘resting state’ may be better understood as ‘Random Episodic Spontaneous Thought’ (Breakspear et al. 2004)].
A description of the atomic composition of the integrated information generated in a particular state of interest. (If no ΦR is generated, then the question would be solved with the trivial answer ‘nothing’, which might be the case for the alterations of consciousness induced by anaesthesia or disorders of consciousness, and indeed there is ongoing empirical research on this topic; see Luppi et al. 2020b).
An understanding of what kind of changes in consciousness may correspond to each observed change of the atoms that constitute ΦR.
Given these three pieces of information, we may be able to chart the atomic composition of baseline and altered human consciousness in a common ΦID space (an example of this is shown in Fig. 5).
The atomic composition of ΦR may be found empirically by identifying an appropriate level at which neural information operates and then quantifying the prevalence of each atom in the human brain at baseline and during altered states of consciousness. While this endeavour is far from straightforward, there is at least a plausible understanding of how we may address this challenge. Importantly, while current neuroimaging techniques might not be able to provide a description at the desirable level of resolution, it is still possible for them to provide a trustworthy reflection of the lower level. Hence, the main challenge is finding out what synergy, transfer, and non-ΦR atoms are like, i.e. finding a phenomenological answer to ‘what it is like to be a bit’. The combination of ΦID with phenomenological interpretations of information-theoretic atoms is therefore the core of our proposed framework, ΨID.
Here we propose different (but potentially complementary) strategies that could be followed to identify which modes of consciousness could correspond to each of the atoms of ΦR. One avenue is to consider altered states of consciousness that one may expect to show an abundance—or lack of—specific atoms and understand how these differences might be reflected in the corresponding phenomenological alterations. These differences may be due to alterations induced by drugs (e.g. psychedelics and anaesthesia), neurological conditions, or even regular physiological alterations such as sleep, dreaming, or meditation. For instance, deep meditation and psychedelics such as lysergic acid diethylamide (LSD) can produce a state characterized by ‘loss of self’, or ‘ego dissolution’, and we may seek to identify which ΦID atoms or combination thereof correspond to this phenomenology by examining the information decomposition of neural signals during such states. Because this approach takes phenomenological evidence as a starting point, we refer to it as the ‘a posteriori’ ΨID approach.
An alternative approach to relate phenomenology and ΦID atoms is to try to identify what each atom may correspond to, in terms of subjective experience, based on what the atoms capture in terms of information processing. This may lead to predictions about how phenomenology should change if the atom in question were manipulated. Such predictions may then be tested empirically by studying perturbations that have been shown to alter the atomic composition [which may be discovered through the first (a posteriori) avenue described above]. Because it starts from abstract considerations in terms of information processing, we refer to this avenue as the ‘a priori’ approach of ΨID.
What it is like to be a bit
At this point, it is worth clarifying an important difference between ΨID and IIT. Although for the present work we draw inspiration from IIT’s quantification of consciousness, IIT 3.0 and subsequent iterations also seek to address the qualitative character of consciousness (Oizumi et al. 2014). Briefly, IIT posits that each particular experience is identical with a so-called ‘maximally irreducible conceptual structure’ that is specified by a set of elements of a system, each being in a specific state and thereby jointly specifying a cause–effect structure for the system. Each quale (a ‘concept’ in the structure) specifies some qualitative aspect of the experience, based on what parts of the system’s cause–effect repertoire it constrains, which corresponds to phenomenal distinctions. In this context, the quantity of consciousness is intended to correspond to the distance between the conceptual structure specified by the state of the system as a whole and that specified by the system’s parts (i.e. its irreducibility). On the other hand, IIT posits that the geometry of the conceptual structure fully specifies the way that the experience feels—its qualitative character (Balduzzi and Tononi 2009; Tsuchiya et al. 2016; Moon and Pae 2019).
It follows that two specific experiences may have the same quantity of integrated information (i.e. they are equally irreducible), but different conceptual structures, corresponding to different phenomenal qualities (qualia: the redness of this particular apple; the painfulness of this specific instance of stubbing one’s toe). In this sense, IIT also goes beyond quantification, providing a conceptual account of how qualia contribute to a given experience (Albantakis et al. 2019; Haun and Tononi 2019; Albantakis and Tononi, 2019). However, this approach is fundamentally different from our own: IIT 3.0 aims to identify the phenomenological components of a specific experience. In contrast, ΨID’s modes of consciousness do not pertain to specific aspects of distinct individual experiences, but rather they are ways of experiencing, based on how the information is carried in the system. Thus, ΨID’s account in terms of modes of consciousness is more coarse-grained than the account of IIT 3.0: for instance, the contents of a given experience may change and that would change the qualia but may leave the mode the same (e.g. someone under the effects of LSD may be consistently experiencing the world through a low-synergy mode, regardless of what specific hallucination they are experiencing at a particular point in time; see Section ‘Me, Myself, and Φ’).
On the other hand, an advantage of our account is that it provides a full taxonomy of the information atoms that jointly constitute the information dynamics of any possible system—whereas we do not have a taxonomy of the fundamental elements that could compose any given conceptual structure (what IIT calls ‘qualia sensu stricto’), because each of them is specified in terms of a system’s cause–effect repertoire, and therefore the possible composition of each experience is not universal, but rather system-specific (i.e. species- or possibly even individual-specific). This means that although a bat may have qualia that are ‘alien’ to a human because of their different senses, the same information atoms may be found in principle both in the brain of a human and a bat, and this may provide avenues to relate human consciousness and bat consciousness. In other words, while the modes cannot tell us what a specific bat may be experiencing at a specific time (which the ‘conceptual structures’ of IIT 3.0 are allegedly intended to capture), nevertheless the modes may tell us what information processing in general (i.e. not pertaining to a specific content) is like for bats in general.
Empirical predictions: Φnomenology
In the following sections, we outline how the theoretical framework of ΨID proposed here could function in practice, by conjecturing specific equivalences between ΦID atoms and various aspects of phenomenology and other psychological phenomena. These provisional predictions are empirically testable using current neuroimaging techniques and illustrate the practical value of ΨID.
At this point, it is worth recapitulating the extent and structure of our theoretical commitments. A fundamental assumption of this work is that it is theoretically possible and meaningful to quantify subjective experience (consciousness) in terms of integrated information of some (suitably chosen) neural dynamics. Subsequent to this background assumption, the core of our contribution is the hypothesis that it may be possible to obtain further insight into subjective experiences in terms of individual information-theoretic atoms, based on the ΦID framework.
Me, myself, and Φ: self and persistent synergies
A fundamental aspect of phenomenology that may be understood in terms of ΨID is the self. Specifically, we propose that a system may constitute an individuated ‘self’ to the extent that its dynamics allow a persistent macroscale description of the system that is causally decoupled (as described in Section ‘A deepness in the Φ: Quantifying causal emergence’) from its individual constituent parts—here understood as the microscale. In other words, we posit that a self is associated with neural dynamics in which the macroscale has a causal influence on its own dynamics, beyond what is explainable from the individual microscale components. As discussed in ‘A deepness in the Φ: Quantifying causal emergence’, this notion corresponds to the presence of persistent synergies in the system, i.e. the ΦID atom of causal decoupling (Figs 2 and 3). The specific reason for identifying selfhood with causal decoupling is that only causal decoupling, among all ΦID atoms, identifies the emergence of a new causally efficacious macroscale entity that needs to be distinguished from the parts of the system, in order to obtain an accurate account of their joint future evolution. Note that these underlying intuitions are aligned with those of other recent works that conceptualize ‘being a self’in information-theoretic terms (Chang et al. 2020; Krakauer et al. 2020), although these works use mathematical frameworks that do not enjoy the expressive richness of ΦID (indeed, extension of these works with the ΦID framework would be an exciting avenue for future work).
Seen from this perspective, Hume’s account of a ‘bundle of perceptions’ (Hume 1986) ignores one fundamental issue: namely, that the parts together can constitute a whole beyond their sum, and high-order structures can persist even when the parts change—as has been formally demonstrated through ΦID (Rosas et al. 2020a).
Preliminary empirical support for a relationship between causal emergence (i.e. persistent synergy in the system) and the self is found in recent work, which suggests the brain’s default mode network to be highly synergistic (Luppi et al. 2020a). This association is promising, as the default mode network has been consistently implicated in self-referential processing (Qin and Northoff 2011) as well as the sense of self or ‘ego’ (Carhart-Harris and Friston 2010), and its integrity is compromised during LSD-induced ‘ego dissolution’ (Nour et al. 2016). Furthermore, the default mode network is also implicated in loss of consciousness, whether induced by anaesthesia or severe brain injury (Vanhaudenhuyse et al. 2010; Boveroux et al. 2010; Di Perri et al. 2017; Luppi et al. 2019, 2020b; Spindler et al. 2021). Indeed, the effect of general anaesthesia on the self is also a topic of recent interest (Sleigh et al. 2020). Thus, the DMN may constitute a nexus for the confluence of synergy, consciousness, and self in the human brain.
At this point, it is worth distinguishing the notions of ‘selfhood’ from ‘sense of self’. The former concerns the extent to which a system can be demarcated from its environment and stably exist as an independent entity—the extent to which that system constitutes an individual (Weber and Varela 2002). Following Krakauer et al. (2020), we take a system’s selfhood to be a graded property, which is determined by the system’s dynamics (Levin 2019). Accordingly, selfhood pertains to systems at all levels of organization, from humans to paramecia. In contrast, by ‘sense of self’ we refer to the extent to which an organism perceives ‘itself’ as having or being a self, which is related to higher-level metacognition [but see Friston (2018) for an alternative suggestion]. Therefore, a sense of self requires some degree of selfhood that can be acknowledged by the organism’s (possibly inaccurate) read-out of their own selfhood, whereas it is possible to have selfhood without a sense of self if the corresponding metacognitive abilities are not available. We leave open the question of whether any systems may, despite lacking selfhood, nevertheless come to have a delusional belief in their own selfhood—that is, having a sense of self without selfhood. Although seemingly unlikely and even paradoxical, our framework does not rule this out from a formal standpoint—and indeed, surprising and striking dissociations between belief and reality can be observed e.g. in patients suffering from anosognosia, who can adamantly deny obvious deficits from which they suffer.
Remarkably, although sense of self and consciousness seem tightly intertwined in everyday experience, evidence suggests that they can be dissociated. Both experienced meditators and people under the influence of psychedelics often report feeling a reduction in their experienced sense of self without acknowledging a diminution of their overall subjective experience—in fact, quite the opposite (Deane et al. 2020). The account of consciousness, individuality, and sense of self put forth by ΨID could accommodate both of these subjective experiences. Namely, this account would explain both the ‘self-less consciousness’ reportedly experienced by advanced meditators (Deane et al. 2020) and the ego dissolution induced by serotonergic psychedelics such as LSD and psilocybin (Carhart-Harris and Friston 2019) in terms of ΦR being preserved, but with a different information-theoretic composition that includes diminished levels of causal decoupling (Fig. 2)—corresponding to a state of consciousness with relatively reduced selfhood, which would then be metacognitively interpreted as reduced sense of self. An alternative hypothesis is that selfhood would be preserved (no reduction in causal decoupling), and the diminished sense of self would instead come about as a result of impaired read-out of the causal decoupling/selfhood—in other words, meditation and psychedelics would lead to illusions about one’s selfhood. These conjectures could be readily tested on magneto- or electro-encephalography or functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) data, by determining whether reduced causal decoupling can be observed during the experiences in question.
An important implication of identifying selfhood with the ΦID atoms that correspond to causal decoupling is that ‘all systems that have selfhood would also be conscious’—since causal decoupling atoms are among the consciousness-related atoms that compose ΦR. However, and perhaps surprisingly, ‘the converse is not the case: transfer-only systems may be conscious despite having no selfhood’, according to our proposed framework (see Fig. 6). This observation highlights the information-theoretic source of another kind of objection levelled against IIT, based on an intuitive resistance to the notion of certain systems (namely, transfer-only systems) being conscious. In effect, most of the counterexamples of synthetic systems with high Φ, and arguably no consciousness, display only transfer and no synergy (Oizumi et al. 2014).
Fortunately, decomposing ΦWMS into its ΦID atoms allows us to bring this problem into focus, by formalizing it specifically in terms of whether or not information transfer should be considered as part of ΦWMS—whereas before the problem was merely about a collection of counterexamples. Prior to the information-decomposition approach, two answers were possible to the problem posed by these putative counterexamples: accepting the intuition behind them and rejecting tout court the idea that consciousness could be quantified in terms of ΦWMS; or rejecting the intuition. Our approach offers the possibility for a more nuanced, alternative middle ground: those who share the intuitions against transfer, but who also find appealing the intuitions at the core of IIT, now have the option of adopting (and trying to motivate) a transfer-free version of ΦWMS. This is analogous to the approach that we used to solve the problem of the negative values of ΦWMS: rather than simply rejecting ΦWMS as a whole, we modified it to exclude the negative redundancy from its calculation, thereby obtaining ΦR. Of course, this type of solution may generalize beyond these particular counterexamples: other measures of integrated information may be defined from different combinations of atoms to suit specific theoretical needs. Thus, rather than using counterintuitive examples to reject the theory as a whole, we argue for refining the theory without throwing the baby out with the bathwater, by capitalizing on the finer-grained understanding made possible by ΦID.
Zones of thought
One intriguing implication of the ΨID framework is that different environments may be conducive to the emergence of alternative modes of consciousness—just as they may be differently conducive to various forms of life. Most organisms harvest information about their environment through multiple sensory modalities. The various senses of these organisms often provide information that is, at least partly, about the same external stimuli. For example, the same event is often the cause of stimuli delivered by more than one modality, such as someone’s words being conveyed by their lip movements as well as their speech. This suggests that an environment where events tend to provide complementary information across sensory modalities can favour the presence of integration via synergy, and organisms that are able to exploit this property will likely find themselves at an advantage.
As an example, in a forest a red but not green round fruit is edible, but only when it smells sweet, so that edible exemplars are identifiable only when the two senses are combined. Such an environment may be expected to favour informational synergy between smell and sight in animals that rely on this fruit for nourishment. Conversely, animals whose main source of sustenance is easily identified by a single property (e.g. a specific colour or smell) may not benefit from synergy to the same degree. Thus, the neural architectures of different organisms may rely on different combinations of information-theoretic atoms, possibly shaped by their environment and evolutionary history—as suggested by recent empirical evidence demonstrating that human brains rely on synergy to a greater extent than macaque brains (Luppi et al. 2020a).
If, as we have argued, selfhood corresponds to causal decoupling (i.e. persistent synergies in the system), then environments that favour or discourage synergy may have an effect on selfhood (and presumably also sense of self, which here we propose to understand as an organism’s perception of its own selfhood). This prediction could be tested by means of virtual reality devices, which could be used to provide participants with visual, auditory, and tactile stimuli whose contents are entirely unrelated (i.e. stimuli that provide no synergy), and subsequently probe whether alterations have occurred in their sense of self, and also in the prevalence of ΦID atoms corresponding to causal decoupling in their neural dynamics, as measured e.g. with fMRI or other neuroimaging modality. Intriguingly, a multi-user virtual reality platform was recently found to produce ‘ego dissolution’ type experiences not incomparable to those produced by moderate doses of psychedelics (Glowacki et al. 2020).
Furthermore, as synergy derives from the advantage of combining different sensory sources, our theory predicts a degradation of selfhood as the unifying factor (and, presumably, the organism’s perception of its own selfhood, i.e. its sense of self) when there is a reduced benefit of integration between different sources of sensory information. In addition to modifying the structure of the environment, as proposed above, another way to reach a similar condition may be to add independent noise in each sensory modality. Doing so may be expected to result in a reduction of signal-to-noise ratio and, hence, a reduction in the proportion of information that each sensory source can contribute towards synergy. Further work will be required to make this hypothesis more specific; intriguingly, however, such a reduction in signal-to-noise ratio may be part of the mechanism by which LSD induces its well-known ego-dissolving effects—complementary of effects taking place in top-down activity (e.g. Carhart-Harris and Friston 2019). In effect, the 5-HT-2A agonistic properties of LSD lead to dysregulated spontaneous neuronal activity (Nutt et al. 2020), which may be expected to weaken the contingency between neuronal firing and external stimuli, hence introducing noise in each channel and reducing the ability of different sensory sources to provide synergistic information—corresponding to reduced causal decoupling, our proposed information-theoretic substrate for selfhood.
The converse of these hypotheses suggests that providing stimulation across different sensory modalities that allows for high synergy may reduce the extent of psychedelic-induced ego dissolution. Partial support to this hypothesis is provided by recent studies on the effect of different stimuli under LSD, which suggest a competition between the psychedelic effect of the drug and stimulus (Mediano et al. 2020). We predict that by increasing the synergy between different sensory sources through concurrent stimulation of multiple sensory modalities, one might reinforce the self-other boundary—and the subjective evaluation of it—resulting in diminished ego dissolution.
Discussion
We have provided theoretical contributions about the nature of consciousness (understood as integrated information) based on its decomposition into elementary information-theoretic atoms and the key insight that the same total integrated information may be composed of different combinations of information atoms. This approach has allowed us to provide empirical predictions that could be tested with the tools of contemporary neuroscience. A schematic summary of our contributions, and the underlying assumptions, is provided in Fig. 7.
To inΦnity and beyond
The main premise of this piece—and of ΨID more broadly—is that there is merit to the principle of quantifying consciousness via integrated information (suitably defined). We acknowledge that the predictions of ΨID outlined here are broad and high level (Fig. 7); however, we believe that it is important for a theoretical account to be clear about its empirical commitments. Indeed, we have made predictions in a broad range of areas—many of which could already be tested. Of course, there is still work to be done on finding the right temporal and spatial scale at which neural information should be best assessed and extending this framework to larger systems (e.g. based on recent developments of information decomposition that scale linearly with system size; Rosas et al. 2020b). Crucially, however, it is already possible to approach this quantification with effective results (see e.g. Luppi et al. 2020b).
Importantly, the advantages of a ΦID-based account of consciousness are not restricted to IIT, but rather this framework represents a general lens through which to understand consciousness. Indeed, the presented framework also provides insights about other theoretical approaches to consciousness, such as the Global Neuronal Workspace Theory (GNWT) (Dehaene and Changeuz 2011; Mashour et al. 2020). In effect, by re-thinking information exchange in the human brain in terms of synergy and redundancy, it is possible to delineate a ‘synergistic global workspace’ purely from functional considerations—based on brain regions whose connections are predominantly synergistic (Luppi et al. 2020b). Furthermore, analysis of resting-state fMRI data showed that loss of consciousness due to anaesthesia or brain injury corresponds to a reduction of ΦR between regions of this synergistic workspace (more specifically, in the regions that regulate the entrance of information to the workspace, referred to as gateways by Luppi et al. 2020b). In this way, the more nuanced view on neural information processes offered by ΦID brings us closer to reconciling IIT’s and GNWT’s accounts of consciousness and offers the promise of further insights for our understanding of consciousness.
Another intriguing future research direction is to explore the relationship between the elaboration of ΨID explored herein and hierarchical predictive coding and the Free Energy Principle (FEP) (see Seth and Hohwy 2020). Interestingly, ideas in this direction have been put forward by Friston and colleagues in the context of IIT (Friston et al. 2020), where they suggest that—at least in terms of numerical analyses—the minimization of variational free-energy (which, according to the FEP, is a basic imperative for any self-maintaining cognitive system) ‘maximizes’ Φ and vice versa (Friston et al. 2020). Thus, an exciting question for future research is to assess how the notion of free-energy minimizing agents that also maximize Φ relates to our theoretical contributions put forward above: does maximization of Φ also correspond to maximization of ΦR and how is it reflected in the ΦR-ing ratio? Is it driven by any specific ΦID atoms—such as synergy or transfer? Additionally, one could ask about the relationship between downward causation, discussed throughout our paper, to predictive mechanisms in a control hierarchy; specifically, where a higher-level component predicts some general feature of lower-level constituents. We thus believe there are promising overlaps between our account of ΨID and the theoretical ambitions of predictive coding and FEP approaches, which deserve to be explored in the future.
So long, and thanks for all the Φs
The distinction of different ΦID atoms within integrated information leads to a new understanding of the space of possible consciousness, providing a phenomenological understanding of information-theoretic atoms: we call this framework ΨID. This framework provides not only a revised measure of integrated information, ΦR, but also a way to measure the efficiency of a system at turning information into consciousness—i.e. its ‘ΦR-ing ratio’. Importantly, when combined with a mathematical framework for the definition of causal emergence, ΨID enables us to propose a formal solution to the long-standing question of whether consciousness is an emergent phenomenon: namely, we show that both consciousness (understood as integrated information, ΦR) and emergence each comprise distinct sets of information-theoretic atoms, and only some of them overlap.
Thus, whether consciousness is emergent or not will depend on its information-theoretic composition. Moreover, since ΦR is composed of different atoms, different systems may achieve the same amount of integrated information through different combinations of information-theoretic atoms. By investigating the phenomenology associated with specific atoms, these ‘modes of consciousness’ may provide a way to eventually understand the phenomenology of different states of consciousness that are not immediately accessible.
In addition to these theoretical contributions for a more nuanced understanding of consciousness, our ΨID framework also provides empirically testable predictions. In particular, we have hypothesized that ΦID atoms involving synergy may correspond to modes of being conscious that involve selfhood. We look forward to empirical tests of these predictions and the possible extension of our work to other mental phenomena, such as psychiatric conditions.
Acknowledgements
The authors are grateful to Marta Halina and members of her research group for helpful discussions. The authors would also like to acknowledge the intellectual influence of Dr Vernor Vinge, whose vision helped to shape the context of this work – especially as laid out in the Zones of Thought series: ‘A Fire upon the Deep’ and ‘A Deepness in the Sky’. The authors believe that the influence of works of science fiction in shaping scientific inquiry is insufficiently acknowledged in the scientific literature and wish to contribute to redress this state of affairs.
Footnotes
The formulation of Φ in Balduzzi and Tononi requires a choice of reference distribution. The original choice of the maximum-entropy distribution, although theoretically attractive for a causal interpretation, is not always well-suited for practical applications: it is ill-defined for many systems of interest (Barrett and Mediano 2019); the transition probabilities from states that are rarely visited are difficult (if not impossible) to estimate accurately from empirical data; and the resulting measure may fail to capture a balance between integration and segregation—as one should expect from Φ-like measures (Mediano et al. 2021). Therefore, throughout this paper we adopt the ‘practical’ version of Φ proposed by Barrett and Seth (2011), which is based on the stationary distribution and addresses most of these issues.
Throughout the paper, and for consistency with prior literature (Mediano et al. 2018), we use the symbol ΦWMS to refer to the specific quantity in the equation above and Φ to refer to the concept of integrated information in general.
We provide examples of this in Section ‘Me, Myself, and Φ’.
Contributor Information
Andrea I Luppi, Division of Anaesthesia, School of Clinical Medicine, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 0QQ, UK; Department of Clinical Neurosciences, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 0QQ, UK; Leverhulme Centre for the Future of Intelligence, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 1SB, UK.
Pedro A M Mediano, Department of Psychology, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 3EB, UK.
Fernando E Rosas, Center for Psychedelic Research, Department of Brain Science, Imperial College London, London W12 0NN, UK; Data Science Institute, Imperial College London, London SW7 2AZ, UK; Centre for Complexity Science, Imperial College London, London SW7 2AZ, UK.
David J Harrison, Leverhulme Centre for the Future of Intelligence, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 1SB, UK; Department of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 3RH, UK.
Robin L Carhart-Harris, Center for Psychedelic Research, Department of Brain Science, Imperial College London, London W12 0NN, UK.
Daniel Bor, Department of Psychology, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 3EB, UK.
Emmanuel A Stamatakis, Division of Anaesthesia, School of Clinical Medicine, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 0QQ, UK; Department of Clinical Neurosciences, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 0QQ, UK.
Data availability
Code to perform Integrated Information Decomposition is available upon request from author P.A.M.: email pam83@cam.ac.uk.
Funding
This work was supported by the Gates Cambridge Trust (to A.I.L.); the Stephen Erskine Fellowship (Queens College, Cambridge, to E.A.S.); the Wellcome Trust (grant no. 210920/Z/18/Z; to P.A.M. and D.B.); The History and Philosophy of Science Trust Fund (to D.J.H.); the Ad Astra Chandaria foundation (to F.R.); and Ad Astra Trust, Tim Ferriss, The Nikean Foundation, and The Tamas Family (to R.L.C.-H.) The Canadian Institute for Advanced Research (CIFAR) (RCZB/072 RG93193; to E.A.S.).
Conflict of interest statement
None declared.
References
- Albantakis L, Marshall W, Hoel E. et al. What caused what? A quantitative account of actual causation using dynamical causal networks. Entropy 2019;21:459. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Albantakis L, Tononi G. Causal composition: structural differences among dynamically equivalent systems. Entropy 2019;21:1–29.doi: 10.3390/e21100989. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Atasoy S, Roseman L, Kaelen M. et al. Connectome-harmonic decomposition of human brain activity reveals dynamical repertoire re-organization under LSD. Sci Rep 2017;7:17661. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Atasoy S, Vohryzek J, Deco G. et al. Common neural signatures of psychedelics: frequency-specific energy changes and repertoire expansion revealed using connectome-harmonic decomposition. Prog Brain Res 2018;242:97–120. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Balduzzi D, Tononi G. Integrated information in discrete dynamical systems: motivation and theoretical framework. PLoS Comput Biol 2008;4:e1000091. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Balduzzi D, Tononi G. Qualia: the geometry of integrated information. PLoS Comput Biol 2009;5:e1000462. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barbosa LS, Marshall W, Streipert S. et al. A measure of intrinsic information. Sci Rep 2020;10:18803. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barrett AB. An integration of integrated information theory with fundamental physics. Front Psychol 2014;5:63. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barrett AB, Mediano PAM. The phi measure of integrated information is not well-defined for general physical systems. J Consciousness Stud 2019;26:11–20. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett AB, Seth AK. Practical measures of integrated information for time series data. PLoS Comput Biol 2011;7:e1001052. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barttfeld P, Uhrig L, Stitt J. et al. Signature of consciousness in the dynamics of resting-state brain activity. Proc Natl Aca Sci 2015;112:887–92. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bar-Yam Y. A mathematical theory of strong emergence using multiscale variety. Complexity 2004;9:15–24. [Google Scholar]
- Bedau MA. Weak emergence. Philos Perspec 1997;11:375–99. [Google Scholar]
- Bedau MA. Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia: Int J Epistemology 2002;6:5–50. [Google Scholar]
- Bertschinger N, Rauh J, Olbrich E. et al. Quantifying unique information. Entropy 2014;16:2161–83. [Google Scholar]
- Boveroux P, Vanhaudenhuyse A, Bruno MA. et al. Breakdown of within- and between-network rsting stake functional magnetic resonance imaging connectivity during propofol-induced loss of consciousness. Anesthesiology 2010;113:1038–53. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Breakspear M, Williams LM, Stam CJ. A novel method for the topographic analysis of neural activity reveals formation and dissolution of dynamic cell assemblies. J Comput Neurosci 2004;16:49–69. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cai L, Wang J, Guo Y. et al. Altered inter-frequency dynamics of brain networks in disorders of consciousness. J Neural Eng 2020;17:036006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cao B, Chen Y, Yu R. et al. Abnormal dynamic properties of functional connectivity in disorders of consciousness. NeuroImage 2019;24.doi: 10.1016/j.nicl.2019.102071. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Carhart-Harris RL, Friston K. The default-mode, ego-functions and free-energy: a neurobiological account of Freudian ideas. Brain: A J Neurol 2010;133:1265–83. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Carhart-Harris RL, Friston K. REBUS and the anarchic brain: toward a unified model of the brain action of psychedelics. Pharmacol Rev 2019;71:316–44. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Casali AG, Gosseries O, Rosanova M. et al. Theoretically based index of consciousness independent of sensory processing and behavior. Sci Transl Med 2013;5:198ra105. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cavanna F, Vilas MG, Palmucci M. et al. Dynamic functional connectivity and brain metastability during altered states of consciousness. NeuroImage 2018;180:383–95. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cea I. Integrated information theory of consciousness is a functionalist emergentism. Synthese 2020;1–26.doi: 10.1007/s11229-020-02878-832989333 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Chang AYC, Biehl M, Yu Y. et al. Information closure theory of consciousness. Front Psychol 2020;11:1–15.doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01504. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Colombetti G, Ratcliffe M. Bodily feeling in depersonalization: a phenomenological account. Emotion Rev 2012;2:145–50.doi: 10.1177/1754073911430131. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Crick F, Koch C. A framework for consciousness. Nat Neurosci 2003;6:119–26. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- De Caro M, Grasso M. Three views on mental downward causation. In: Paoletti MP, Orilla F (eds), Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives on Downward Causation. New York: Routledge, 2017;313–27. [Google Scholar]
- Deane G. Dissolving the self: active inference, psychedelics, and ego-dissolution. Philosophy Mind Sci 2020;1:1–27.doi: 10.33735/phimisci.2020.I.39. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Deane G, Miller M, Wilkinson S. Losing ourselves: active inference, depersonalization, and meditation. Front Psychol 2020;11:539726. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Deco G, Cruzat J, Cabral J. et al. Awakening: predicting external stimulation to force transitions between different brain states. Proc Natl Aca Sci 2019;116:18088–97. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dehaene S, Changeuz JP. Experimental and theoretical approaches to conscious processing. Neuron 2011;70:200–27. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Demertzi A, Tagliazucchi E, Dehaene S. et al. Human consciousness is supported by dynamic complex patterns of brain signal coordination. Sci Adv 2019;5:1–11.doi: 10.1126/sciadv.aat7603. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Di Perri C, Amico E, Heine L. et al. Multifaceted brain networks reconfiguration in disorders of consciousness uncovered by co-activation patterns. Hum Brain Mapp 2017;39:89–103. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dinesh P, Li D, Dean JG. et al. Level of consciousness is dissociable from electroencephalographic measures of cortical connectivity, slow oscillations, and complexity. J Neurosci 2020;40:605–18. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Eagleman S, Chander D, Reynolds C. et al. Nonlinear dynamics captures brain states at different levels of consciousness in patients anesthetized with propofol. PLoS One 2019;14:e0223921. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Feder M, Merhav N. Relations between entropy and error probability. IEEE Trans Inf Theory 1994;40:259–66. [Google Scholar]
- Feinberg TE, Mallot J. Phenomenal consciousness and emergence: eliminating the explanatory gap. Front Psychol 2020;11:1041. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. A free energy principle for biological systems. Entropy 2012;14:2100–21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. Am I self-conscious? (Or does self-organization entail self-consciousness?) Front Psychol 2018;9:1–10.doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00579. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K, Sengupta B, Auletta G. Cognitive dynamics: from attractors to active inference. Proc IEEE 2014;102:427–445. [Google Scholar]
- Friston KJ, Wiese W, Hobson AJ. Sentience and the origins of consciousness: from Cartesian duality to Markovian monism. Entropy 2020;22:516. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Glowacki DR, Wonnacott MD, Freire R. et al. Isness: using multi-person VR to design peak mystical type experiences comparable to psychedelics. In: CHI 20: Proceedings of the 2020 CHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems. Honolulu, HI, USA: 2020. 1–14.doi: 10.1145/3313831.3376649. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Griffith V, Koch C. Quantifying synergistic mutual information. In: Prokopenko M. (eds) Guided Self-Organization: Inception. Emergence, Complexity and Computation vol 9. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer, 2014. 10.1007/978-3-642-53734-9_6. [Google Scholar]
- Hahn G, Zamora-Lopez G, Uhrig L. et al. Signature of consciousness in brain-wide synchronization patterns of monkey and human fMRI signals. NeuroImage 2021;226:117470. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haun A, Tononi G. What does space feel the way it does? Towards a principled account of spatial experience. Entropy 2019;21:1160. [Google Scholar]
- Hellman M, Raviv J. Probability of error, equivocation, and the Chernoff bound. IEEE Trans Inf Theory 1970;16:368–72. [Google Scholar]
- Hesp C, Smith R, Parr T. et al. Deeply felt affect: the emergence of valence in deep active inference. Neural Comput 2021;33:398–446.doi: 10.1162/neco_a_01341. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hoel EP, Albantakis L, Marshall W. et al. Can the macro beat the micro? Integrated information across spatiotemporal scales. Neurosci Consciousness 2016;2016:1–12.doi: 10.1093/nc/niw012. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hoel EP, Albantakis L, Tononi G. Quantifying causal emergence shows that macro can beat micro. Proc Natl Aca Sci 2013;110:19790–5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Huang Z, Zhang J, Wu J. et al. Temporal circuit of macroscale dynamic brain activity supports human consciousness. Sci Adv 2020;6:eaaz0087. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hume D A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning . London: Penguin Classics, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Hutchinson RM, Hutchinson M, Manning KY. et al. Isolurane induces dose-dependent alterations in the cortical connectivity profiles and dynamic properties of the brain’s functional architecture. Hum Brain Mapp 2014;35:5754–75. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- James RG, Crutchfield JP. Multivariate dependence beyond shannon information. Entropy 2017;19:531. [Google Scholar]
- James RG, Ellison C, Crutchfield J. Anatomy of a bit: information in a time series observation. Chaos 2011;21:037109. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jaynes T Probability Theory: The Logic of Science . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Kleiner J. Mathematical models of consciousness. Entropy 2020;22:609. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Koch C, Massimini M, Boly M, Tononi G. Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nat Rev Neurosci 2016;17:307–21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Krakauer D, Bertschinger N, Olbrich E. et al. The information theory of individuality. Theory Biosci 2020;139:209–23. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lee. H, Golkowski D, Jordan D. et al. Relationship of critical dynamics, functional connectivity, and states of consciousness in large-scale human brain networks. NeuroImage 2019;188:228–38. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Levin M. The computational boundary of a “self”: developmental bioelectricity drives multicellularity and scale-free cognition. Front Psychol 2019;10:1–14.doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02688. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lewes HG. Problems of Life and Mind. Memphis, Tennessee: General Books LLC, 1879/2012. [Google Scholar]
- Lizier J, Bertschinger N, Jost J. et al. Information decomposition of target effects from multi-source interactions: perspectives on previous, current and future work. Entropy 2018;20:307. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lord LD, Expert P, Atasoy S. et al. Dynamical exploration of the repertoire of brain networks at rest is modulated by psilocybin. NeuroImage 2019;199:127–42. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi A, Craig M, Pappas I. et al. Consciousness-specific dynamic interactions of brain integration and functional diversity. Nat Commun 2019;10:1–12. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi AI, Carhart-Harris R, Roseman L. et al. LSD alters dynamic integration and segregation in the human brain. NeuroImage 2021b;227:1–18.doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.117653. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi AI, Golkowski D, Ranft A. et al. Brain network integration dynamics are associated with loss and recovery of consciousness induced by sevoflurane. Hum Brain Mapp 2021a. 10.1002/hbm.25405. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi AI, Carhart-Harris RL, Roseman L. et al. LSD alters dynamic integration and segregation in the human brain. NeuroImage 2021b;227:117653.doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.117653 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi A, Mediano PAM, Rosas FE. et al. A synergistic workspace for human consciousness revealed by integrated information decomposition. bioRxiv 2020b. 10.1101/2020.11.25.398081. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi A, Mediano PAM, Rosas FE. et al. A synergistic core for human brain evolution and cognition. bioRxiv 2020a. 10.1101/2020.09.22.308981. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Luppi A, Vohryzek J, Kringelbach ML. et al. Connectome harmonic decomposition of human brain dynamics reveals a landscape of consciousness. bioRxiv 2020c. 10.1101/2020.08.10.244459. [Google Scholar]
- Mashour G, Roelfsema P, Changeux JP. et al. Conscious processing and the global neuronal workspace hypothesis. Neuron 2020;105:776–98. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mediano PAM, Rosas FE, Luppi AI. et al. Towards an extended taxonomy of information dynamics via Integrated Information Decomposition. arXiv:2109.13186 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Mediano P, Seth AK, Barrrett AB. Measuring integrated information: comparison of candidate measures in theory and simulation. Entropy 2018;21:17. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mediano PAM, Rosas FE, Timmerman C. et al. Effects of external stimulation on psychedelic state neurodynamics. bioRxiv 2020. 10.1101/2020.11.01.356071. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Moon K, Pae H. Making sense of consciousness as integrated information – evolution and issues of integrated information theory. J Cognitive Psychol 2019;20:1–52. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel T. What is it like to be a bat? Philos Rev 1974;83:435–50. [Google Scholar]
- Northoff G, Wainio-Theberge S, Evers K. Is temporo-spatial dynamics the ‘common currency’ of brain and mind? In quest of ‘spatiotemporal neuroscience. Phys Life Rev 2020;33:34–54. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nour MM, Evans L, Nutt D. et al. Ego-dissolution and psychedelics: validation of the Ego-Dissolution Inventory (EDI). Front Hum Neurosci 2016;10:1–13.doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00269. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nutt D, Erritzoe D, Carhart-Harris RL. Psychedelic psychiatry’s brave new world. Cell Commentary 2020;181:24–8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Oizumi M, Albantakis L, Tononi G. From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: integrated information theory 3.0. PLoS Comput Biol 2014;10:e1003588. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Oizumi M, Tsuchiya N, Amari S. Unified framework for information integration based on information geometry. Proc Natl Aca Sci 2016;113:14817–22. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Palacios ER, Isomura T, Parr T. et al. The emergence of synchrony in networks of mutually inferring neurons. Sci Rep 2019;9:1–14.doi: 10.1038/s41598-019-42821-7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Palacios ER, Razi A, Parr T. et al. Biological self-organisation and Markov blankets. bioRxiv 2017;9:1–14.doi: 10.1101/227181. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Parr T, Friston K. Generalised free energy and active inference: can the future cause the past? Biol Cybern 2019;113:495–513. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Parrondo JMR, Horowitz JM, Sagawa T. Thermodynamics of information. Nat Phys 2015;11:131–9. [Google Scholar]
- Qin P, Northoff G. How is our self related to midline regions and the default-mode network? NeuroImage 2011;57:1221–33.doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.05.028. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rosas F, Ntranos V, Ellison CJ. et al. Understanding interdependency through complex information sharing. Entropy 2016;18:38. [Google Scholar]
- Rosas FE, Mediano PAM, Rassouli B. et al. An operational information decomposition via synergistic disclosure. J Phys A: Math Theor 2020b;53:485001. [Google Scholar]
- Rosas FE, Mediano PAM, Jensen JH. et al. Reconciling emergences: an information-theoretic approach to identify causal emergence in multivariate data. PLoS Comput Biol 2020a;16:e1008289. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Schwitzgebel E’ Phenomenal consciousness, defined and defended as innocently as i can imagine. J Consciousness Stud 2016;23:224–35. [Google Scholar]
- Seth A. Measuring emergence via nonlinear Granger causality. Artif Life 2008;11:545. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Seth A, Friston K. Active interoceptive inference and the emotional brain. Philos Trans R Soc B 2016;371:1–10.doi: 10.1098/rstb.2016.0007. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Seth AK, Hohwy J. Predictive processing as an empirical theory for consciousness science. Cognitive Neurosci 2020;12:1–2.doi: 10.1080/17588928.2020.1838467. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Shannon CE. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical J 1948;27:379–423, 623–656. [Google Scholar]
- Sleigh J, Warnaby C, Tracey I. General Anaesthesia as fragmentation of selfhood: insights from electroencephalography and neuroimaging. Br J Anaesthesia 2020;121:233–40. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Spindler LRB, Luppi AI, Adapa RM, Craig MM. et al. Dopaminergic brainstem disconnection is common to pharmacological and pathological consciousness perturbation. Pro Nat Acad Sci 2021;118:e2026289118. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Standage D, Areshenkoff CN, Nashed JY. et al. Dynamic reconfiguration, fragmentation, and integration of whole-brain modular structure across depths of consciousness. Cereb Cortex 2020;30:5229–41. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stramaglia S, Cortes JM, Marinazzo D. Synergy and redundancy in the Granger causal analysis of dynamical networks. New J Phys 2014;16:105003. [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G. An information theory of consciousness. BMC Neurosci 2004;5:42. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G. Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto. Biol Bulletin 2008;215:216–42. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G, Boly M, Massimini M. et al. Integrated information theory: from consciousness to its physical substrate. Nat Rev Neurosci 2016;17:450–61. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G, Edelman G. Consciousness and complexity. Science 1998;282:1856–1851. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G, Koch C. Consciousness: here, there, and everywhere? Philos Trans R Soc B 2015;370:20140167. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G, Sporns O, Edelman G. A measure for brain complexity: relating functional segregation and integration in the nervous system. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1994;91:5033–7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tononi G, Sporns O, Edelman G. Complexity and coherency: integrating information in the brain. Trends Cognitive Sci 1998;2:474–84. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tsuchiya N, Taguchi S, Saigo H. Using category theory to assess the relationship between consciousness and integrated information theory. Neurosci Res 2016;107:1–7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Turkheimer FE, Rosas FE, Dipasquale O. et al. A complex systems perspective on neuroimaging studies of behaviour and its disorders. Complex Systems Perspective on Neuroimaging Studies of Behaviour and Its Disorders Preprints2020.doi: 10.20944/preprints202008.0654.v1. [DOI]
- Turkheimer FE, Rosas FE, Dipasquale O. et al. A complex systems perspective on neuroimaging studies of behavior and its disorders. Neuroscientist2021. 10.1177/1073858421994784. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- Uhrig L, Stitt JD, Jacob A. et al. Resting-state dynamics as a cortical signature of anaesthesia monkeys. Anesthesiology 2018;129:942–58. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Vanhaudenhuyse A, Noirhomme Q, Tshibanda LJ-F. et al. Default network connectivity reflects the level of consciousness in non-communicative brain-damaged patients. Brain: A J Neurol 2010;133:161–71. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Varley TF, Luppi A, Pappas I. et al. Consciousness & brain functional complexity in propofol anaesthesia. Sci Rep 2020b;10:1018. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Varley TF, Denny V, Sporns O. et al. Topological analysis of differential effects of ketamine and propofol Anesthesia on brain dynamics. R Soc Open Sci 2021;8:201971.doi: 10.1098/rsos.201971. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Vlisides PE, Li D, Zierau M. et al. Dynamic cortical connectivity during general anesthesia in surgical patients. Anesthesiology 2019;130:885–97. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Weber A, Varela J. Life after Kant: natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenol Cognit Sci 2002;1:97–125. [Google Scholar]
- Wibral M, Priesemann V, Kay JW. et al. Partial information decomposition as a unified approach to the characterization and design of neural goal functions. Brain Cognition 2017;112:25–38.doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2015.09.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Williams PL. Information dynamics: its theory and application to embodied cognitive systems. Ph.D. Thesis, Indiana University, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Williams PL, Beer RD. Nonnegative decomposition of multivariate information. arXiv:1004.2515 2010. [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Data Availability Statement
Code to perform Integrated Information Decomposition is available upon request from author P.A.M.: email pam83@cam.ac.uk.