Skip to main content
Sage Choice logoLink to Sage Choice
. 2021 Oct 8;52(1):3–34. doi: 10.1177/03063127211048945

The politics of scaling

Sebastian Pfotenhauer 1,, Brice Laurent 2, Kyriaki Papageorgiou 3, and Jack Stilgoe 4
PMCID: PMC8771885  PMID: 34625011

Abstract

A fixation on ‘scaling up’ has captured current innovation discourses and, with it, political and economic life at large. Perhaps most visible in the rise of platform technologies, big data and concerns about a new era of monopolies, scalability thinking has also permeated public policy in the search for solutions to ‘grand societal challenges’, ‘mission-oriented innovation’ or transformations through experimental ‘living labs’. In this paper, we explore this scalability zeitgeist as a key ordering logic of current initiatives in innovation and public policy. We are interested in how the explicit preoccupation with scalability reconfigures political and economic power by invading problem diagnoses and normative understandings of how society and social change function. The paper explores three empirical sites – platform technologies, living labs and experimental development economics – to analyze how scalability thinking is rationalized and operationalized. We suggest that social analysis of science and technology needs to come to terms with the ‘politics of scaling’ as a powerful corollary of the ‘politics of technology’, lest we accept the permanent absence from key sites where decisions about the future are made. We focus in on three constitutive elements of the politics of scaling: solutionism, experimentalism and future-oriented valuation. Our analysis seeks to expand our vocabulary for understanding and questioning current modes of innovation that increasingly value scaling as an end in itself, and to open up new spaces for alternative trajectories of social transformation.

Keywords: scale, innovation, platform technologies, living labs, randomized controlled trials


I meant no harm I most truly did not,

but I had to grow bigger so bigger I got.

I biggered my factory, I biggered my roads,

I biggered the wagons, I biggered the loads,

of the Thneeds I shipped out I was shipping them forth

from the South, to the East, to the West, to the North.

I went right on biggering … selling more thneeds.

And I biggered my money which everyone needs.

From The Lorax, by Dr. Seuss

A scalability zeitgeist

In 2014, tech billionaire and investor Peter Thiel’s published his start-up manifesto ‘Zero to One’, in which he unabashedly put the appetite for scaling and monopoly at the heart of technological entrepreneurship:

Every single company in a good venture portfolio must have the potential to succeed at vast scale. … Everyone needs to know exactly one thing that even venture capitalists struggle to understand: we don’t live in a normal world; we live under a power law. … The power law becomes visible when you follow the money: in venture capital, where investors try to profit from exponential growth in early-stage companies, a few companies attain exponentially greater value than all others. … The most successful companies make the core progression – to first dominate a specific niche and then scale to adjacent markets – a part of their founding narrative. (Thiel, 2014)

Thiel’s ‘notes on how to build the future’ illustrate how much scaling 1 has become an obsession of innovation discourses and, with it, contemporary social, political and economic life at large. Perhaps most visible in the rise of platform technologies and surveillance capitalism, ‘vast scale’ has become quasi-synonymous with the success of companies that did not exist two decades ago, but now easily reach hundreds of millions of users across the globe – like Facebook, Twitter, Uber, and Airbnb. The ramifications of this scale, while hard to anticipate when these companies were in their infancy, have quickly emerged as problematic at the level of entire societies as well as globally. Frontpage news regularly zooms in on one big tech behemoth or another whose business model is challenging established socioeconomic orders, constitutional rights, political systems, and labor markets. Frequently, the strategy has been one of ‘Blitzscaling’ – a shock-and-awe tactic openly aimed at social disruption that strives to ‘achieve massive scale at incredible speed, … prioritizes speed over efficiency’, and risks ‘potentially disastrous defeat in order to maximize speed and surprise’ (Hoffman and Yeh, 2018). The current business literature and consulting industry is rife with manuals on how ‘how to create an exponential mindset’ (Bonchek, 2016) how to hack growth (Ellis and Brown 2017), or ‘How to move fast: Corporate innovation at speed and scale’ (McKinsey, 2019). Singularity University, the famous Silicon Valley breeding ground for would-be entrepreneurs, openly embraces the ambition to ‘improve the life of a billion people’ (Singularity University, 2020, see Figure 1). Social entrepreneurs are warned that ‘if you don’t know how to scale, don’t innovate’ (Seelos and Mair, 2017).

Figure 1.

Figure 1.

‘Introduction to exponentials’, a graphic used by Singularity University to capture transformative thinking (Constine, 2018). © Courtesy of Stephanie Papaioanu, Chrysalis Studios.

On the public policy side, too, scalability has moved to the center stage, in keeping with a growing obsession with innovation and partly mirroring its logics (Pfotenhauer et al., 2019). Policy initiatives and public research programs are increasingly rationalized in the name of ‘grand societal challenges’, as in the forthcoming Horizon Europe funding program by the European Commission or in the many initiatives surrounding the UN Sustainable Development Goals. These challenges demand scalable solutions, for example in the form of ‘mission-driven innovation’ that portions socio-technical transformations into manageable and scalable pieces (Mazzucato, 2018, see Figure 2) or in corollary debates about ‘deep transitions’ (Schot and Kanger, 2018). Even ‘social innovation’ debates, usually concerned more with bottom-up dynamics and local alternatives than with megalomaniac technocratic interventions, are increasingly pushing for up-scaling (Gabriel, 2014; Musa and Rodin, 2016; Westley et al., 2014).

Figure 2.

Figure 2.

A graphic used by the European Commission to explain the logic of ‘mission-oriented innovation’. Promoted by economist Mazzucato (2018), among others, ‘missions’ serve as a meso-level organizing principle to coordinate actors and projects and direct their innovation activity toward grand societal challenges. Mission-oriented innovation has been embraced by the upcoming funding program by the European Commission, ‘Horizon Europe’.

Scalability ambitions have, of course, always been essential to the modernist project. As Tsing (2012) writes, ‘projects that could expand through scalability were the poster children of modernization and development’ (p. 523). Tsing’s call for ‘non-scalability’ to account for ‘non-scalable diversity’ echoes a long tradition in science and technology studies (STS) of exploring the conflicts that ensue when knowledge and solutions are framed as universal rather than local and situated (Bowker and Star, 2000; Haraway, 1988; Jasanoff, 2012; Tsing, 2005). These works have studied how the modernist’s totalizing gaze tends to beget a politics of exclusion of alternative ways of living and knowing, as evidenced by decades of development policy (Ezrahi, 1990; Latour, 1993; Miller, 2004; Scott, 1999; Visvanathan, 1997a).

Yet, the current entrepreneurial appetite for quantity, speed and scale seems to have a constitutive quality of its own. While in older markets companies might grow if their products and services are successful, in the era of big tech, the aim is frequently to scale up first and profit later. Silicon Valley financiers explicitly select new ventures for their (blitz-) scalability in all-or-nothing domination strategies, which can leave the public and policymakers reeling in their attempts to account for technology’s winners and losers. For some of these technologies, the consequences of their scale is outright ‘unfathomable’, as Gillespie (2018) notes. Policy initiatives, whether in development economics or sustainability transitions, increasingly bet on experimental ‘lab’ approaches with a scalable impact logic, aimed at re-shaping some of the fundamental ways in which societies function. In this sense, ‘scale’ ceases to be an analytic category that refers to geographic reach, nested units of analysis or the marginal costs of production. Rather, as an actors’ category, it signifies an imperative and framing device for businesses, governments and NGOs alike that prescribes what seems worth doing, what the rules of engagement are and how we define problems or solutions.

In this paper, we interrogate the scalability zeitgeist as a key ingredient of contemporary political and economic ordering. Following a discussion of theorizing efforts on scaling from STS and elsewhere, we analyze three sites where scaling has become a dominant logic – platform technologies, ‘living labs’ and experimental development economics. From these diverse sites, we identify several elements of how the politics of scaling manifest in practice. We argue that the prioritization of rapid up-scaling entails a series of normative assumptions about how society and social change function (and ought to function), what kind of solutions are feasible and desirable, and who authorizes social change. We further suggest that STS’s engaged program needs to come to terms with the ‘politics of scaling’ as a powerful corollary of the ‘politics of technology’.

What critique of scalability?

Questions of scale have been a staple of economics and management research for a long time (Arrow, 1979; Colombo and Grilli, 2010; Davidsson, 1991; Morroni, 2009; Scherer, 1980), and both economic historians and historians of technology have interrogated the social transformations, corporate models and forms of capitalisms economies of scale beget (Chandler, 1994; Hounshell, 1985; McCraw and Chandler, 1991; Scranton, 1999). Such economies of scale are linked to the rise of mass production, ‘big business’ and Wall Street, and corollary notions of ‘corporate America’ and ‘too big to fail’. One can read economists’ dogmatic rebuttal of monopoly power and its corrosive effects on market dynamics as indirect critiques of the consequences of economies of scale. This includes the domain of innovation – for example with regard to perennial questions of whether patents stimulate or stifle innovation (Heller and Eisenberg, 1998; Viscusi et al., 2000), how incumbency relates to innovation pressures (Hart, 2001) or how to reckon with antitrust in the new era of big tech (Khan, 2016; Khan and Vaheesan, 2017; Manne and Wright, 2011; Wu, 2018). Questions of scale have also been prominent in economic sociology studying the diffusion of innovation (Rogers, 2003).

According to Tsing, economies of scale can be best understood through their mechanistic essence that turns scaling into a material routine. Tsing (2012) points to ‘the ability of a firm to expand without changing the nature of what it does’ (p. 508) and to a mode of reasoning epitomized by the early colonial plantations, whose formula for smooth expansion across different landscapes was later adopted by factories during industrialization. For Tsing, certain features of sugarcane plantations have become defining features of scalability, namely alienation, interchangeability and expansion. When applied successfully, these can generate remarkable profits, as well as large human and environmental costs and ruins. It is against these ruins, or where the logic of scalability fails, that the non-scalable emerge and are made visible. Non-scalable projects, Tsing emphasizes, deserve attention, not because they are necessarily better than the scalable ones, but because they embody the kinds of transformative and mutualistic relations that scalability erases.

Tsing’s account echoes earlier work in STS, particularly in the actor-network theory (ANT) tradition, that has addressed questions of scale in science and technology by studying the enlargement of material-semiotic networks through processes of translation and attachment. Interrogating the transformative power of science, Latour (1999) famously argues that technologies effectively never leave the lab, but rather that society is gradually transformed to resemble the conditions of the lab. In this view, the lab is expanded outward to enable an up-scaling of a technology while at the same time reconfiguring society through new power structures tied to central nodes in the network – often those who control the technology. Innovation, in this sense, is a colonizing act of network expansion that depends, among other things, on the mobilization of strong allies and spokespersons (Akrich et al., 2002a, 2002b). But Tsing’s work also resonates with STS scholarship that has treated ‘non-scalability’ as a kind of foundational premise: Partly as a response to generalizing tendencies of systems theories of society and the economy, STS research has consistently emphasized the political contestation, historical contingency and interpretive flexibility that a more situated perspective engenders.

Early work in STS has been concerned with a rebuke of universalisms – whether in scientific claims to truth and objectivity (Fleck, 1981; Jasanoff, 1987; Latour and Woolgar, 1986), the transfer and expansion of technological systems (Bijker et al., 1987; Jasanoff, 1995; Star, 1999; Visvanathan, 2005), or the governance structures that accompany them (Hilgartner, 2000; Jasanoff, 1994; Wynne, 1992). The term ‘situatedness’ has become a shorthand for an analytic perspective that explicitly accounts for differences in social, cultural, political, economic, and institutional positionality (Butler, 1990; Haraway, 1988; Jasanoff, 2004). This has opened up spaces for a normative critique of hegemonic power structures and colonial tendencies that threaten to erase epistemic and political diversity (Harding, 2006; Prasad, 2014; TallBear, 2013; Visvanathan, 1997b), or ‘meaningful diversity’ in Tsing (2005: 38) language. These works relate to broader critiques of modernity premised on legibility, standardization, industrialization or massive development interventions that tend to ignore local diversity and inevitably run into resistance (Callon et al., 2009; Foucault, 1980; Scott, 1999; Visvanathan, 1997b). 2

As STS reminds us, however, one should not think of scalability merely in terms of homogenizing acts of translation and the flattening-out of difference. For one, ‘economies of scale’ and ‘diffusion’ are specific modes of calculative reasoning for scaling up technical and economic projects that, like any other market device, depend on distributed material agency and diverse actors (Callon et al., 2007). This prompts us to scrutinize the intricate relations and persistent power inequalities that hold such hybrid assemblages together across place and time (Haraway, 2016; Ong and Collier, 2004; Strathern, 2020). For example, companies such as General Motors, Walmart or McDonald’s associate pockets of cheap labor with places of consumption in ways that make diversity an ingredient for bigness (Tsing, 2009).

For another, the success of certain scalability logics also depends on their compatibility with sticky local ways of reasoning and meaning-making that are often highly institutionalized. What seems readily scalable for scientific, technical or economic reasons might thus vary significantly across regional, cultural, and jurisdictional boundaries (Felt, 2015; Jasanoff and Kim, 2009; Levidow et al., 2007, 2013; Pfotenhauer and Jasanoff, 2017a; Winickoff and Mondou, 2017). In this sense, the expectation that things can be scaled up hinges upon the problematic assumption that technological and knowledge orders could co-evolve in a sufficiently synchronized and harmonious way with (other) existing elements of collective meaning-making, including (self-)imagination, political culture, and institutionalized (state) apparatuses of knowing, ascertaining, and demonstrating. Ensuing controversies associated with the scaling of novel technologies can thus be interpreted as expressions of these co-productionist alignments being destabilized, at least for parts of society (Hurlbut, 2015; Jasanoff, 2004, 2005).

This co-productionist perspective also foregrounds the important link between innovation, scale and imagination. Ambitions to scale up technologies and associated economic structures are linked to the creation of widely shared collective visions about the future, which makes these visions a key battleground. Hilgartner’s (2015) work on ‘vanguard visions’ explores how ‘relatively small collectives [regularly] formulate and act intentionally to realize particular sociotechnical visions of the future that have yet to be accepted by wider collectives, such as the nation. … How, for example, do “unimaginable” technological revolutions become not only imaginable but, at least for a time, plausible?’ Reversing the direction of scalability from big to small, Jasanoff (2010) analyzes the mismatch between the scientific construct of ‘global climate change’ and the capacity to imagine its meaning vis-à-vis local experience and identities. A similar observation has recently been made by Latour (2018) when talking about illusory seamlessness between the local and the global when zooming in and out in Google Earth.

These extant theoretical perspectives are useful for us to probe the current scalability zeitgeist. They invite us to ask programmatic questions such as: Which current forms, instrumental or otherwise, do scalability ambitions take in debates around innovation, entrepreneurship and ‘Big Tech’? Who are the new prophets of scalability and how do they attain credibility and wider audiences? How do present scalability logics relate to earlier modes of colonization, globalization, and ostensible homogenization? How are they able to credibly connect to the diversity of social concerns they claim to address? What is left out of scaling up processes, and to whose benefit or detriment? Where does stability in scaling processes derive from and for whom does (in)stability matter? How does the promise of scalability relate to the promise of innovation, and how do both shape present political economies? In short, how do the politics of scaling manifest and how do they relate to well-known concerns about politics of technology?

Three scalability snapshots

The three empirical snapshots presented below derive from larger research projects in which the authors of this paper are engaged, including on the future of mobility, the mainstreaming of co-creative innovation practices and real-world experimentation. They represent a synthesizing effort of diverse empirical material that we have partly published, or are planning to publish, elsewhere. The three snapshots were specifically selected on the basis of their partly overlapping timelines and relevance to the larger conceptual questions of this paper. Although all three are not without historical antecedents, they epitomize certain elements of the politics of scaling that are particularly palpable today. For example, platform technologies have impacts that can rise to the level of entire democracies or markets within few years, making macro-political phenomena like echo-chambers, election meddling, real estate speculation, surveillance, or even genocide an explicit part of the conversation. ‘Test beds’ and ‘living labs’ promise to deliver scalable solutions in ways where possible transformations are tested before rolling them out more widely, as currently pursued in many government initiatives in energy, mobility or information technology. Experimental development economics reflect a commitment to ‘evidence-based policy’ rooted in data-driven approaches to politics that treats policy as a scale-up from local interventions. Together, the three snapshots help us identify how current initiatives envision scalable expansion and growth.

Scalable platform technologies and the uberization of everything

Uber, one of the most notorious examples of platform capitalism and its accompanying ‘gig economy’, provides a telling starting point for an illustration of what the current scalability zeitgeist entails. The company has pursued an aggressive ‘scale first; ask questions later’ strategy, running years and billions of losses, engaging in predatory pricing (Duprey, 2020) and counting on network effects to bring exponential growth and eventual winner-takes-all profits. Within little more than a decade, the company has infiltrated the transport systems of 900 cities in 85 countries and become one of the world’s largest transportation companies, with 75 million active users and 3 million registered drivers. More recently, Uber has also pushed its platform as a solution in adjacent sectors, including food and goods delivery.

Countless upstarts aspire to be the ‘Uber for X’, aiming to build a platform that allows for scaling at negligible marginal cost and the disruption of markets while externalizing responsibilities. The story told by Uber, Airbnb and others is of a ‘sharing’ economy, with spare resources voluntarily shared among empowered owners and users for a bit of extra cash on the side. A 2017 article co-authored by Jonathan Hall, Uber’s head of policy research, and Princeton’s Alan Krueger, former head of Obama’s Council of Economic Advisors, primarily emphasizes the benefits of flexibility for drivers (Hall and Krueger, 2018). But the ‘uberization’ of the economy has led to wide controversy and occasionally fierce resistance for its starkly unequal effects. Instead of empowerment, Uber has been criticized for creating a new class of precarious self-employment outside traditional regulatory or union protection (Uber calls its drivers ‘partners’ or ‘contractors’ rather than ‘employees’). It has been blamed for a sudden displacement of taxi drivers, new patterns of exploitation (e.g. dependence through rating systems), anticompetitive behavior, and a range of data privacy issues. As with other platform technologies, the speed of scaling has meant that both the company and the jurisdictions in which it operates have been unable to attend to the myriad issues created (Gillespie, 2010).

As a result, Uber and its peers operate largely in what is generally considered a legal gray area. Uber has repeatedly been accused of sidestepping health and safety regulation. The company continues to argue that it is a technology company, not a mobility company (Conger and Scheiber, 2019), to avoid concerns about drivers and safety. This ambiguity is symptomatic for platforms that challenge conventional ways of organizing markets and governance: They claim to be technology intermediaries linking supply and demand within existing markets while actually undercutting market dynamics through a vast influx of venture capital (Kenney and Zysman, 2019) – prompting one analyst to label Uber a ‘firm-market hybrid’ (Sundararajan, 2014, 2016). Cities looking to advance their public transport systems are now recognizing that this model looks more like a problem than a complementary private sector solution. One large analysis found that Uber and its copycats have contributed to worsening congestion, decreased public transport use and negligible change in car ownership (Diao et al., 2021).

Like other platform companies, Uber’s blitzscaling efforts are closely linked to a strategy of experimentation. The company touts its ‘Experimentation Platform’, XP, and argues that ‘experimentation is a critical stage of the product lifecycle; it is the process of discovering and determining whether or not new features are successful. Given Uber’s hypergrowth, the goal of our XP is to ensure that new features roll out successfully and then return actionable analysis’ (Feng and Zhenyu, 2017). Constant variation and experimentation mean that there is no one Uber, just as there is no one Facebook. Drivers and customers will experience different versions of Uber depending on their location, usage history and socioeconomic profile. While many of these experiments concern features such as pricing, routing, display feedback or engagement that are invisible to both drivers and customers, some are also physical experiments, including the controversial use of video recording in Uber vehicles (Conger, 2019a). What is more, participants are typically unaware that they are being experimented upon. Similar to other platform technology companies, consent clauses for experimentation are usually buried deep within the terms of use, which can only be accepted or rejected wholesale. Platform experimentation has increasingly sparked controversies, for example when Facebook published the results of a psychological experiment it had clandestinely run on 689,003 users to explore how positive or negative posts in their newsfeed influenced users’ own postings (Constine, 2014).

Scaling up from living labs and test beds for transformative technologies

In March 2020, Uber announced that it would resume public testing of autonomous vehicles (AV) in its hometown, San Francisco. Uber chose a notably humble tone in alerting the public of its plan, though not without hinting at its larger ambitions: ‘Our testing area will be limited in scope to start, but we look forward to scaling up our efforts in the months ahead and learning from the difficult but informative road conditions that the Bay Area has to offer’ (Hawkins, 2020). Uber’s plan came after a series of mis-steps, including a fatal crash in March 2018 in Tempe, Arizona, where a self-driving Uber vehicle killed a pedestrian walking her bicycle, the company’s 2017 refusal to mark its AVs as ‘test vehicles’ and the earlier loss of its license to operate in San Francisco (McCormick, 2016). The relaunch of public testing was also as a nod to investors after the company’s disappointing IPO of ‘only’ $69bn (Isaac et al., 2019), which had underscored that the deployment of AVs, with the cost-cutting potential of extracting drivers, was vital for the continuation of its business model (Conger, 2019b). Yet, later in 2020, Uber offloaded its AV division to a competitor, revealing the difficulties replacing human drivers and their attachments to the world (Tennant and Stilgoe, 2021) .

Uber’s public testing of a risky technology is representative of a broad wave of ‘living labs’ and ‘test beds’ currently sweeping across the ‘innovation’ world. In a nutshell, ‘living labs’ or ‘test beds’ are designated experimental spaces where potentially transformative technologies can be tested and developed in public under supposed real-world conditions (Engels et al., 2019; Evans and Karvonen, 2014; Gross, 2016; Kareborn and Stahlbrost, 2009; Renn, 2018). They represent a more overt, and possibly more extreme, form of many tendencies previously discussed by scholarship on the experimental nature of technology introduction (Beck, 1992; Krohn and Weyer, 1994; Lemov, 2006) and the world-making ambitions behind scientific and technological tests (Gooding et al., 1989; Latour, 1999; Laurent, 2016; Pinch, 1993; Shapin and Schaffer, 1985). Beyond mobility, living labs have been placed in domains as diverse smart cities (e.g. in Toronto’s Sidewalk Labs, Korea’s SongDo and India’s 100 Smart Cities), security (e.g. facial recognition tests in China and Germany), digital finance (e.g. Singapore’s FinTech sandbox), sustainability transitions (e.g. Masdar City in Abu Dhabi) or a mixture thereof.

Living labs and test beds are frequently the spearheads of policy initiatives aimed at large-scale sociotechnical transitions, often in the form of public-private hybrids. For example, in 2008, the European Energy Forum (EUREF) living lab campus was launched in Berlin as a ‘an urban neighborhood model for a climate-neutral, resource-saving, smart city of tomorrow’ and ‘model for the Energiewende in Germany’, referring to Germany’s national flagship initiative for a sustainable energy transition (EUREF, 2018b, translation by the authors). Combining an array of energy supply, smart grid, mobility and building technologies (Figure 3), Berlin’s mayor Michael Muller heralded EUREF ‘as a space for experimentation [where] solutions are devised and tested that will touch all our lives tomorrow and into the future, [and] a place of innovation, where more than 150 companies, both established and young start-ups, exchange ideas with research institutions on important issues about the future’ (EUREF, 2018a). For many EUREF actors, testing on campus was seen as a stand-in for testing in Berlin (and other metropolitan regions in Europe), with technologies being explicitly developed ‘in a very small, scalable way’, as one engineer noted (Engels et al., 2019). Built on fenced-off private grounds and accessible only through guarded gates, EUREF was able to act with considerable organizational and regulatory leeway and partly outside Germany’s strict regulatory environment (e.g. customized charging stations or road traffic regulation). However, because of this sharp demarcation, the campus’ promise of seamless integration with its Berlin environment and stand-in character fell arguably short, prompting some citizens to call it a ‘UFO’ (Engels, 2020). As Engels et al. (2019) have argued, EUREF displays a fundamental tension between living labs conceived on the one hand as highly controlled, quasi-scientific test environments and, on the other, dynamic places representative of real-world messiness and full of unexpected ‘co-creative’ opportunities for innovation and learning.

Figure 3.

Figure 3.

View of the European Energy Forum (EUREF) campus in Berlin, a ‘living lab’ for energy transitions and new digital and mobility technologies aimed at broader urban (and global) transformations. Technology tests include, for example, the parameters of different charging stations for electric mobility, seen in the center of the image. Courtesy of EUREF AG.

The value proposition of living labs is closely tied to the dual promise of scalability and competitiveness. Living labs are heralded as launchpads for broader systemic change that can address ‘grand challenges’. If successful, the insights and socio-technical configurations are envisioned to provide a blueprint for wider societal roll-out and transformation. This promise has sparked renewed discussions about social testing at a meso-scale and the role of experimental attachments, and whether one could think of them also as a lever for developing scalable governance models for emerging technologies (Engels et al., 2019; Laurent and Tironi, 2015; Marres, 2020; Tennant and Stilgoe, 2021). At the same time, living labs have become a prominent avenue for cities and regions to position themselves competitively as innovation leaders and to attract tech firms (Laurent et al., 2021; Pfotenhauer, 2017). Conversely, companies are vying for municipalities as potential clients with deep pockets and transferable implementation templates. The EUREF campus, for example, has emerged as a featured stop for many national and international delegations to display Germany’s technology prowess and underscore its export potential in energy and IT. At the same time, the pressure to display market-ready solutions can force early closure of experimental technology developments in favor of quick scalable solutions. In the case of EUREF, this has led to repeated conflicts between business and engineering perspectives on how to best utilize the living lab (Engels et al., 2017).

Living lab initiatives have attracted considerable criticism, echoing in part well-known critiques of scientism from STS and beyond. Some of the main lines of critique concern the surrender of public space to commercial interests; the creation of material lock-ins through the weight of flagship demonstration projects; the fabrication of new inequalities and potential threats to democracy under the guise of openness and inclusion; a lack of attention to problems of risk governance and consent for emerging technologies; unclear ethical ramifications on large-scale public experimentation; and misguided promises of ready-made transferability and scalability. Many of these issues also apply to our next snapshot.

Scalable policy interventions: Experimental economics and evidenced-based policy in development contexts

On October 14th, 2019, the Nobel prize in economics was awarded to Abhijit Banerjee, Esther Duflo and Michael Kremer ‘for their experimental approach to alleviating global poverty’ (Nobel Prize Committee, 2019). Pioneers in the field of experimental economics and its application to development policy, Banerjee, Duflo and Kremer spearheaded a wave of applied economic scholarship based on randomized controlled trials (RCTs) as the basis for policy intervention. This method, inspired by the natural sciences (and particularly the medical sciences), compares the differential response between a ‘treatment group’ (i.e. a population/site subjected to an intervention) and a ‘control group’ (i.e. one without such intervention) to prove or disprove the efficacy of a treatment. Following this scientific logic, effective treatments – for example, public health or training programs, a medication or vaccination fix, or cheap sanitation technology – are then meant to scale up to achieve global impact at the level of grand societal challenges (Tollefson, 2015). In the words of MIT’s Abdul Latif Jameel Poverty Action Lab (J-PAL, 2020b), an institution that is the brainchild of Banerjee and Duflo, ‘over 400 million people have been reached by programs that were scaled up after being evaluated by J-PAL affiliated researchers’.

By grounding development policy in scalable local experiments, the three Nobel winners and the institutions they inspired are part of a broader wave of development scholarship that seem to upend decades of received wisdom on development policy. Instead of understanding development as a macroeconomic domain driven by national indicators in which international funders need to come to terms with local political and institutional conditions, they argue that development interventions can be purely ‘evidence-based’ and free from (or at least agnostic to) such political considerations thanks to the scientific authority of experimentation: ‘What works’ clearly speaks for itself. Once evidence of efficacy has been established, the intervention can then be harnessed beyond the experimental site to trigger wider policy initiatives (Bold et al., 2013). The RCT approach mirrors, in a bottom-up fashion, long-standing top-down tendencies by international development organizations such as the World Bank who, according to Tsing (2012), tend to envision scalable activities that ‘could be spread to other villages without changing project elements’. It does so by reducing the initial ‘project’ to a limited set of parameters fit for experimentation and expanding the envisioned impact of the would-be tested solution to nothing else than ‘solving poverty’ (Stein, 2019).

One of the regularly cited examples of projects run by J-PAL is an experiment conducted in the Delhi area that demonstrated that deworming young children was beneficial to school participation, thus inspiring deworming policies in Africa and India (Abdelghafour, 2017). This experiment alone has solicited substantial debate about the nature of data generated by RCTs, and particularly efficacy and scalability claims associated with it (see Evans, 2015). Critics of RCT use in development policy have further pointed to their inherently contradictory premise that that their findings are context-specific yet scalable (Bédécarrats et al., 2019, 2020; Deaton and Cartwright, 2018), thus casting doubt on the key premise of initiatives like J-PAL (2020a) ‘to reduce poverty by ensuring that policy is informed by scientific evidence’.

Proponents of experimental economics tend to counter such criticism with a claim of efficiency: The evidence created by RCTs allows policy-makers to put scarce development resources to optimal use. This situates experimental economics in a wider trend of evidence-based policy-making that has also tapped into behavioral economics. For example, in the UK, Nesta runs as Innovation Growth Lab that promotes ‘a more experimental approach to innovation and growth policy’ by running and sponsoring RCTs (IGL, 2020). The Behavioural Insights Team started as small unit in the UK government and grew into ‘a global social purpose company’ with the mission to ‘generate and apply behavioural insights to inform policy, improve public services and deliver results for citizens and society’ (BIT, 2020). The logic is remarkably consistent: An initial experimental intervention is intended to produce outcomes that can generate scaled-up policy change. The Behavioural Insights Team borrows venture capital language in its claim to create ‘policy unicorns’, that is, massively scalable behavioral nudges that ‘had an impact of more than £1 billion’ (Halpern, 2019).

Soon after Banerjee, Duflo and Kremer received the Nobel Prize, Sanjay Reddy, a professor of economics at the New School argued in Foreign Policy that even though RCTs had become dominant in development economics, they were often conducted ‘at the expense of the world’s poor’ (Reddy, 2019). At a time of nearly unanimous celebration, Reddy and others exposed some of the issues of experimental economics in development contexts, such as the ethical implications of involving human subjects in experiments 3 (Rayzberg, 2019), the scientific robustness of the ‘evidence’ produced (Bédécarrats et al., 2019), and the unintended consequences of scaling up isolated initiatives without taking side effects into account (Abdelghafour, 2017; Jatteau, 2013). These discussions invite us to explore the radical re-definition of development policies that RCTs imply. They also suggest that reasoning in the terms of local initiatives meant to be scaled up has profound consequences in the world of development.

Exploring elements of the politics of scaling

As illustrated by our three snapshots, scalability is currently featured prominently in initiatives of innovation, entrepreneurship and public policy – cutting across regions, sectors, and scientific domains. While there are many ways to analyze these cases, three analytic themes seem particularly salient to the politics of scaling and its effects: Their shared emphasis on tech solutionism, public experimentation, and future-oriented valuation practices.

Solutionism

A first element shared by our three snapshots is their affinity for solutionism – that is, the framing of problem diagnoses in response to readily available, often technological solutions. Solutionist thinking is closely related to notions of ‘technological fixes’ (Johnston, 2018; Rosner, 2004; Volti, 2006) and ‘technology optimism’ (Tiles and Oberdiek, 1995), which cast a long and consequential shadow over the history of engineering and public policy, and which have gained renewed currency in the area of tech entrepreneurship. To authorize certain problem diagnosis, solutionism tends to draw on technical languages, visionary promises, and other forms of exclusive expertise to assert causal relationships and credibility. Problems are cut into smaller, discrete pieces that warrant ready-made solutions, which are in turn owned or controlled by specialized organizations or individuals (entrepreneurs, innovators, scientists, innovators etc.). Alternative problem framings that might benefit different groups of actors are thus frequently sidelined. Morozov (2013) analyzes how tech companies, and specifically Silicon Valley-based unicorns, craft misleadingly narrow problem diagnoses around available gadgets. Different solutions to this problem are then often presented as equivalent to one another, when in their socio-economic reality they are clearly not (e.g. addressing obesity as a public health concern by either regulating the food industry or by using a self-tracking nutrition app). Similarly, Pfotenhauer et al. (2019) explore a ‘deficit model’ in innovation policy where a lack of innovative solutions is regularly diagnosed as the reason for why we cannot address societal challenges, thus treating innovation as a kind of panacea across social and policy domains (see also Pfotenhauer and Jasanoff, 2017b).

Platform technologies, living labs and experimental economics all frame their quest for scalability in the language of solutionism. Here, the commitment to a scalable solution affects which problems are deemed relevant – that is, those that can be addressed through a scalable solution – and the type of intervention that is expected to follow. Platform technologies such as Uber propose to solve a large-scale mismatch between local supply and demand for individual transportation through a decentralized, scalable matching platform. Yet, the controversies surrounding Uber reveal the multiplicity of possible specific problem definitions (e.g. inefficient matching of potential drivers and potential clients, insufficient public transportation infrastructures, underutilized private cars, corrupt taxi markets, excessive labor market regulation) and corollary framings as to what kind of solution the company is actually providing (a software, a mobility service, a platform for independent contractors, a taxi company with thousands of employees, a complement to public transportation, a brazen attempt to undercut minimum wages, and diverse regulatory standards etc.). Here, the company’s own framing of the problem and the solution, as well as the suppression of alternative framings in public debates such as the California Prop 22 decision (Uber Newsroom, 2021), can be seen as a purposeful (mis)direction in favor of scalability and away from less scalable solutions. Some of Uber’s investors would argue that the real problem the company is tackling is the expectation of investors for exponential growth, inhibited by the inconvenience of social-democratic laws, minimum wages, employee benefits and organized unions.

While Uber was pitched as the solution for transport mismatches, EUREF was envisioned as a stand-in for urban energy transitions across Berlin and many other urban areas in Germany and Europe. It took on grand, messy societal challenges like sustainable energy provision or climate change and carefully constructed its activities as plug-in solutions with scalability potential, including micro-smart grids, e-scooters, lamp post charging stations, and charging location apps that can help overcome fears of a shortage of charging stations for potential customers of electric vehicles (Engels et al., 2017). As Wentland (2018) has shown, over the course of 10 years EUREF repeatedly re-framed its vision in response to shifting policy trends and problem diagnoses, including the Energiewende, Smart Cities or a Green New Deal, as well as broader imaginaries of an automobile nation, sustainability or energy security. Across these shifting societal challenges and problems, the living lab remained a demonstration site for a similar set of technologies portrayed as potential solutions and a mechanism meant to assure wider public acceptance. Engels et al. (2019) have argued that EUREF and other living labs serve as instruments to test and stabilize future societies around a predefined set of technological premises based on rather specific visions of the future, which raises questions about the inclusiveness of such visions.

With its grand aim to ‘solve poverty’, experimental economics, too, treats societal challenges as discrete, isolated problems that warrant localized interventions. In particular, many interventions focus on cheap technological fixes (such as the distribution of de-worming pills or low-cost water filtration) to achieve what decades’ worth of development policy could not. In this sense, the solution to the malaise of poverty-ridden regions of the Global South is higher skills levels of the population to allow them to participate in the global knowledge economy, made possible by increased school attendance, in turn made possible by decreased worm infections, guaranteed by drugs manufactured in another country. While all of these improvements are important achievements, they reduce the problem of a continent’s under-development (a framing that is in itself highly problematic) to something that can be tackled through a pill, sidestepping more complicated systemic challenges such as a consistent underinvestment in teachers and school buildings, dysfunctional governments or lack of legal protection against child labor, let alone the configuration of global value chains, trade agreements, or migration policies.

Experimentalism

Second, the promise of scalability hinges on the assumption that the efficacy of scalable solutions to ‘grand societal challenges’ can be established locally and, once proven effective, rolled out society-wide – addressing essentially the same problem through more of the same. The desired proof is in many cases closely tied to the notion of scientific experimentation and its appeal of objectivity – which are especially visible in living labs and RCTs. Our scalability snapshots fit well with a broader interest in laboratory practices and experimental knowledge beyond traditional laboratory settings (Engels et al., 2019; Laurent, 2017; Millo and Lezaun, 2006; Papageorgiou, 2017; Stilgoe, 2016).

Like all scientific experiments and tests (Latour, 1988; Pinch, 1993; Shapin and Schaffer, 1985), our three scalability cases can be read as (staged) public demonstrations – including toward companies, investors, regulators, future users or the citizenry at large – who are enrolled to attest to the credibility of the performance. Experimental sites for scalability may be created from scratch (e.g. automotive test tracks with artificial obstacles) or retrofitted onto a building, a campus, a village, a city, or a landscape (Guridi et al., 2020; Laurent et al., 2021; Laurent and Lechevalier, 2019). Models for how to turn places into experimental sites are increasingly circulated, similar to how innovation and policy practices travel around the globe (Pfotenhauer and Jasanoff, 2017a; Voß and Simons, 2014, 2018). Some of Uber’s experiments have taken place invisibly, powered by its software and with its users as subjects, and some have treated the world as a physical lab, as with its high-stakes prototyping on public roads in Arizona, with bystanders as unwitting participants (Stilgoe, 2020). The EUREF living lab was implemented on a privately owned, fenced-off campus within Berlin. J-PAL actively chooses sites as well as treatment and control populations for experimental RCT-type interventions.

However, these demonstrations are rife with frictions and contestations, including over questions of participation, power, foregone alternatives and the distribution of costs and benefits. Uber’s rapid diffusion through cities around the world is a signal to investors that the promised monopoly is indeed attainable. Yet publics around the globe can also witness how Uber’s experiments have overwhelmed cities and consistently squeezed margins for drivers, leaving a trail of controversy in their wake. The EUREF living lab is a highly visible panoply of demonstration efforts with considerable policy and economic traction, regularly featured as an international showcase for the superiority of German sustainable energy technologies and proof that the Energiewende is indeed feasible. The campus has become an obligatory passage point for many international delegations and a favored stage for national sustainability policy debates. At the same time, EUREF has seen internal controversies over how open-ended these developments really are, how quickly closure in R&D processes ought to occur, how big its transformative impact on Berlin or Germany has been, how the infrastructures needed for some demonstrations may prevent alternative projects, and how innovation districts are subject to investor logics and gentrification (Engels, 2020). J-PAL mobilizes the authority of controlled experiments to certify efficacy claims of policy intervention as scientific and hence potentially universally valid (given sufficient control over the boundary conditions). J-PAL’s researchers ‘help partners scale up effective programs’ to entire regions and nations (J-PAL, 2020c). But J-PAL, too, has been unable to avoid controversies about the generalizability of its findings to other regions with different conditions and the ethics of large-scale social experimentation.

Our three snapshots also point to ways in which experiments create path-dependencies, giving preference to some solutions over others while explicitly aiming for their scalability. From this perspective, the objective of the experiment is connected less to the possibility of replication of test results, or the relative efficacy of different interventions, than to gaining a head start for the extension of certain commercial solutions in tandem with processes of valuation and economization. Uber’s algorithmic experiments explicitly guide future development and expansion efforts with a view toward enhancing a monopoly position. Likewise, the company’s experiments with AV were a clear signal to investors. EUREF, which hosts many leading German energy companies, explicitly aims to become a model for Berlin and beyond. J-PAL’s approach is to ‘Innovate, test, scale: Replicating and expanding a successful evaluated pilot to similar contexts’ (J-PAL, 2020). This points to the possibility of the promise of extension becoming an end in itself for experimentalism, counting on ensuing path-dependencies and on making some experiments ‘permanent’ (Karvonen, 2018).

Future-oriented value

Finally, the promise of scalability is also a promise about future value, frequently in ways that blur social, economic, and moral value propositions. Uber’s hunt for monopoly profits is at once a proposition about sharing underutilized resources and enabling beneficial side-gigs for driver. Living labs like EUREF propose to revolutionize energy systems and evade the prohibitive social and economic costs of climate change by testing new products and services in situ as if the former had already diffused throughout society. Public health improvements for developing countries based on RCTs reiterate the problematic promises of development aid in conjunction with raising spending efficiency for policy makers and export markets for companies. In all three cases, the proposed value is largely speculative and tied to a carefully curated set of expectations about forthcoming transformations. What is more, this expectation is often tied to a corollary set of financial mechanisms that can derive revenues from these transformations. As such, the scalability zeitgeist resonates with the rise of shareholder value logics in management theory that link social value and responsibility to profit maximization (Jensen, 2001; Lazonick and O’Sullivan, 2000). It further resonates with current trends toward assetization and technoscientific rentiership, which turn present and future control over things – land, skills, people, rights etc. – into durable revenue streams for investors (Birch, 2020; Birch and Cochrane, 2021; Birch and Muniesa, 2020), and promises of economic opportunity into tradable entities (Sunder Rajan 2006, 2017). This link between transformation, scale and revenue is well captured by Peter Diamandis, co-founder of Singularity University, who evangelizes about the need for entrepreneurs to have a ‘Massively Transformative Purpose (MTP)’ (Diamandis, 2017). In connecting financial value explicitly with solutionism, he argues: ‘The best way to become a billionaire is to solve a billion-person problem’ (Diamandis and Kotler, 2016). These connections help explain why ‘scaling’ is increasingly treated as a goal in its own right, accepting the implied disruptive quality of innovation and de-emphasizing the details of the envisioned transformation as well as who gets to decide about them.

Accordingly, Uber’s scalability ambitions and those of its peers are tied up with a venture capital logic that expects disproportionate profits from one blockbuster out of a portfolio of many start-ups. Within this logic, each company must make grand claims to scalability while knowing, along with their investors, that most will fail or end up as components of others’ systems. Uber has become a symbol of speculative investments in unison with a move-fast-and-break-things attitude in the hope of future monopolistic revenue (Kaminska, 2016). Living Labs such as EUREF position their activities as both morally urgent and financially promising. EUREF promises to unlock both a clean, sustainable urban energy future and lucrative, growing clean-tech markets for German companies and investors. The research campus itself is a stock market-listed corporation that has raised ‘200 million euros of equity capital … and twice that much as debt’ and that has tried to frame its mission with ‘economic clarity and a hands-on controlling system’ (EUREF, 2018a). This fits the analysis that the Energiewende was from its inception as much a project of securing German economic and technology leadership as a response to climate change (Joas et al., 2016). Development interventions, including those by J-PAL, invoke a future where poverty is ‘solved’ and millions have been successfully integrated into global markets, presuming that governments and other funders spend resources in the present. Here, experimental interventions in developing countries serve simultaneously as an exploration of potential markets for innovations such as pharmaceuticals or financial transaction apps. Non-monetary values are thus part and parcel of the legitimacy of an extension of the expectations of future values to new territories, such as those of development and social policies.

The politics of scaling are thus an intensely future-oriented business that often gets entwined with claims to common good. What is at stake in visions of transformation and scalability – and the valuation instruments and practices that undergird them – is control over the future (see also Hilgartner, 2015, 2017), as shown by the tensions and controversies that scalability cause. Uber is betting on a future where its billions of sunk venture capital have finally outcompeted all rivals to enable monopoly profits, and where the economic dependences and the promise of comfort can be mobilized to outweigh concerns about workers’ rights and exploitation – as seen in the Prop 22 ballot controversy in California. The commercial orientation of living labs has often led to internal debates about trade-offs between speculative and socially inclusive research projects on the one hand, and the coveted financial returns on technologies or the value of the campus itself on the other. Interestingly, while EUREF has arguably fallen short of the promise of transforming Berlin through a roll-out of sustainable energy, IT and mobility technologies, it has attracted considerable attention as a scalable model to stimulate innovation, entrepreneurship and regional revitalization, which other regions have now turned to emulate (Engels et al., 2019). When experimental economists test development solutions for the sake of their future extension rather than present benefits in the experimental sites, they anticipate future social and economic value – possibly for an undefined general category of ‘the poor’ as future beneficiaries who are part of the promise of global extension.

Through the lens of scalability, then, well-known questions of power and distributive justice around valuation practices thus take a new pressing form: What role does scalability play in plausibilizing expectations about socioeconomic transformation and associated revenue streams? Which technical-instrumental form do promises about scalability take, underwritten by which expertise? What are the social, political, and material pre-conditions of the world in which promises of scalable solutions – whether by tech billionaires, scientists, or policy-makers – are not just plausible, but sought after? Who needs to be convinced about the value of scaling? Who gets to shape whose needs and vulnerabilities are represented and valued in up-scaling endeavors? The subjects of scalability experiments, while regularly asked to participate in the risks of such initiatives – whether as precarious drivers in the gig economy, pedestrians in a testbed for autonomous driving or experimental subjects in developmental interventions – are rarely asked to participate in the articulation of value propositions.

The constitutional quality of scaling: Coming to terms with the scalability zeitgeist

Our goal in this paper has been to draw attention to the widespread commitment to ‘scaling up’ across very different sites and domains. Our analysis has shown how such scaling efforts share a number of characteristics that shape our world: in how entrepreneurs and policy-makers frame societal problems and propose transformative solutions, in the configuration of public experiments that test and materialize future ways of living ‘as if’ consensus about this future had been reached, and in business plans and valuation practices where the rewards of quick fixes and rapid domination outpace those of careful design. Our cases provide illustrations of a desire for ‘blitzscaling’, which considers the speed of extension as an objective in itself, necessary to conquer markets or solve global problems. While this desire provides an explicit blueprint for companies like Uber, it serves as an implicit promise for living lab innovators and development economists – a promise that is never fulfilled, yet proves useful to convince partners, investors, or donors of the great transformational potential of local interventions. In all cases, the combination of solutionism, experimentalism, and future-oriented value not only frames collective issues and defines how to act on them, but also distributes the ability to intervene on these issues in unequal ways.

This sensibility reveals limits with the current framing of mainstream technological critique. For example, anti-trust debates about breaking up ‘Big Tech’ (Manne and Wright, 2011; Wu, 2018) or Zuboff’s (2019) analysis of surveillance capitalism tend to focus on where we are, rather than how we got here. That is, they sidestep the critical process dimension of up-scaling and hence questions about the conditions under which certain actors were able to acquire so much power so quickly. Likewise, the enthusiasm with which big tech companies have embraced ‘ethics’ approaches to ostensibly deal with the corrosive effects of their scale (e.g. in the problematic ‘AI ethics’ initiatives of Google and Facebook) suggests that this is a convenient mode of self-critique that seeks refuge in universal principles and post-hoc institutional fixes that apply independently of scale, obfuscating the fact that the questions that can be asked early on might be quite different. The STS literature has often looked for the ‘politics of technology’ in initial material configurations and ‘design ethics’, which has led to a push for deliberation ‘upstream’ in the R&D process (Wilsdon and Willis, 2004). Similar logics apply in current ‘ethics-by-design’ proposals in AI, neurotech or gene editing (IEEE, 2020; Poel and Robaey, 2017; Schwarz-Plaschg et al., 2017). In this sense, initial design considerations will inevitably affect the conditions of possibility for up-scaling and how power will get redistributed in the process. Yet the politics of technology clearly shift when expanding beyond the initial design or testing stage, and experiences made during up-scaling regularly feed back into the re-design of business models, as in the multi-layered experiments of Uber XP, the continuous data collection in AV open-road testing and machine learning, or impact assessment for J-PAL’s interventions (e.g. Stilgoe, 2018, 2019). What is more, scalability efforts inevitably straddle different social, cultural, and jurisdictional contexts, calling for a more dynamic understanding of the design ethics vis-à-vis the public good and the variegated polities of technology politics.

The politics of technology, in short, need a corollary politics of scaling. Taking the effects of scaling up seriously would require scrutiny of normative, epistemic and material configurations before things scale, while they scale, and after they have scaled. As well, it requires a critical appraisal of the political-economic conditions that make scaling plausible and desirable in the first place, and an analysis of how these conditions shape what is expected to scale and for whose benefits.

The three elements we highlight in our paper open up perspectives for future scholarship and policy interventions aimed at the politics of scaling. First, greater attention to patterns of solutionism can help us identify when, how and by whom problem spaces are configured to enable scalable solutions. Hilgartner (2017) has fruitfully interrogated nascent ‘knowledge-control regimes’ that allow vanguards to configure ‘categories of agents, spaces, objects and relationships among them’ in the name of prophetic revolutions to affect the distributive consequences of innovation. Along those lines, by giving scalability a preferential status among selection criteria for potential solutions, the usual checks and balances – for example, risk assessment, regulatory scrutiny, public consultation or protest – may be sidelined by sheer momentum or through locally justified ‘exemptions’. This puts the spotlight on moments where actors draw boundaries between supposedly ‘scalable’ and ‘non-scalable’ parts of reality. Why, for example, is the value proposition of ride-hailing companies linked to the total number of global rides, not the livelihood of healthy local communities? Why is the scaling-up of electric vehicles seen as a more plausible response to climate change than the redesign of urban spaces around or less car-centric forms of mobility? How much can de-worming pills really challenge deeply rooted global patterns of inequality and dependency? These are the kind of questions that are crucial to ask for global problems to be addressed in ways that are meaningful for the many, and not just profitable for the few (Figure 4).

Figure 4.

Figure 4.

A pile of shared bikes in Shanghai. © Getty Images.

Second, public experiments today almost inevitably raise questions about responsible governance. Attempts at ‘disruptive’ or ‘transformative’ innovation increasingly work within, or even purposefully create, zones of legal ambiguity and exception that may become institutionalized and permanent. Uber, Facebook, Google, and others continue to insist that existing laws, regulations, and norms on such issues as employment, privacy or freedom of speech do not apply to them because their innovative products and services operate in unprecedented legal territory. Living labs often purposefully lower regulatory burdens to experience the effects of novel technologies in real life ‘as if’ these technologies had already been proven safe and effective (Engels et al., 2019; Laurent, 2016; Laurent et al., 2021). Experiments in development economics enroll people in large-scale experiments with unclear answers to questions of consent, risk or benefit sharing. In all cases, innovators and policymakers tend to see existing regulations and norms as a hinderance to scaling. Scalability thinking thus fits in a highly problematic framing that sees innovation as the ‘driver’ of change and regulation ‘lagging’ behind (Hurlbut et al., 2020; Jasanoff, 2011; Pfotenhauer and Juhl, 2017). A critical analysis of the politics of scaling must broaden the space of reflection about how innovation and regulation can relate to each other beyond such one-dimensional framings.

This focus on the relationship between scaling and individual and collective rights also raises questions about consent. As Engels et al. (2019) note, population-scale testing in medical studies typically needs to meet very high ethical standards and requires some form of informed consent. In contrast, many current forms of public experimentation lack meaningful consent procedures, let alone clear rules for benefit sharing. Many ‘co-creative’ settings purposefully blur the differences between experimenters, test-subjects, consumers and citizens. A more optimistic reading on the proliferation of public experimentation might focus on opportunities for collective explorations of emerging issues, making experiments possibly more valuable for democratic-deliberative reasons rather than technical-instrumental ones (Callon et al., 2009; Marres and Stark, 2020; Tennant and Stilgoe, 2021). By extension, one could see experiments as opportunities to co-develop technologies, governance and social resilience in tandem, for example by treating living labs not as low-regulation zones, but as zones of greater scrutiny. Yet this would require a degree of reflexivity and political will that current experimental sites lack.

Third, and related, we should explore how the valuation mechanisms that currently incentivize scaling can be pluralized. Ours is not necessarily an argument against scale or against scaling. Nor do we argue that non-scalability is inherently good. Rather, our concern is that scaling, and in particular blitzscaling, often obscures and privatizes consideration of the opportunities and uncertainties of innovation, closing off a multitude of possible promising directions in favor of a few (Frahm et al., 2021; Leach et al., 2010). To that end, the routes of extension taken matter. Scaling up is never just ‘more of the same’. For example, letting autonomous vehicles out of a test environment and into our public road system does not just require additional hardware and additional data. It may also mean challenging existing ways of driving, policing, governing, planning, and kitting out local roads and communities – in ways that will inevitably bump up against institutionalized social norms and safeguards. The promise of extension thus hinges upon the continuous translation of heterogeneous actors, concerns, norms and things into a single scalability proposition that implicates experimental research ethics, finance, risk assessment, social justice, urban planning, anti-trust, international trade and more. A critical analysis of the politics of scaling can help us to get better at anticipating, understanding and navigating these junctures and tipping points in up-scaling processes where mechanisms that protect the most vulnerable come under pressure.

A key question for a critically engaged social science program on scalability might thus be whether we can get away from one-off engagements with the politics of technology (and the politics of policy), and instead foster a more continuous engagement with these politics across different scales – and, in the processes, figure out collectively what the scalability objective is about. We contend that such exploration is necessary lest we accept absence from some key sites where decisions about the future are presently made.

Some instruments from the STS engagement toolkit have emphasized the process dimension of research and innovation, including constructive technology assessment (Schot and Rip, 1997), anticipatory governance (Barben et al., 2008), midstream modulation (Fisher et al., 2006), or suggestions around ‘stage-gating’ in responsible research and innovation (Stilgoe et al., 2013). But their application to a politics of scaling would require differentiating better how such instruments can be applied at different scales, and, more importantly, how they can help us to problematize the injunction to scale things up. That is, can our practices of inclusion, deliberation and reflexivity work at different speeds and scales – and can they open up the range of speeds and scales that innovators, regulators, and concerned publics are engaged in? How can we rethink modes of deliberation and engagement to accompany innovations all the way through, beyond ‘design ethics’ and post-hoc regulation, in ways that never lets up pressures of democratic accountability? How can we embed our STS toolkits into settings where scalability work is currently done invisibly and with little scrutiny, especially in the private sector and start-ups (Pfotenhauer et al., 2021)? How could we, for example, scale public engagement activities with a company like Facebook from its inception in a Harvard dormitory to its 2.5 billion user quasi-utility with a data monopoly? How can we open up scalability processes to different space and time frames, allowing for debate on what should be replicated or extended, and by whom? How can we, rephrasing Collingridge’s (1980) dilemma of control, govern emerging technologies from the point where changes are easy but consequences are unclear, to the point where the consequences are mostly clear but change has become hard, in a way that always emphasizes plurality of options and configurations along the way (Winickoff and Pfotenhauer, 2018)?

In a way, the scalability zeitgeist forces us to look at the relationship between innovation and the public good more explicitly as a dynamic problem. Coming to terms with this zeitgeist will require strengthening the continuities between different modes of collective action across space and time. It will also require stressing the discontinuities that are being glossed over by proposing scalable solutions. To that end, we may take a hard look at a key lesson from the climate change debate: Why don’t some things scale easily? Scaling up our collective response to climate change has been notoriously difficult because people neither agree on problem definitions nor solutions; because the effects of climate change and mitigation efforts translate into different real-world experiments depending on location; and because different constituencies in the global political economy don’t agree on how to value what. Any site where scaling is made to look easy should thus raise red flags about a likely lack of comprehension or inclusiveness of perspectives.

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful for three years of intellectual exchange and inspiration as part of the Horizon 2020 project SCALINGS (‘Scaling up co-creation? Avenues and limits for integrating society in science and innovation’). Many members of the SCALINGS consortium helped improve this paper at various stages through their generous feedback. The authors are also indebted for feedback received from several members of the Science and Democracy Network during the Annual Meeting, including Ben Hurlbut, Sheila Jasanoff, Clark Miller, and Hilton Simmet, as well as two anonymous SSS reviewers who invested time and energy in helping us sharpen our argument. The discussion of the EUREF Campus living lab draws on the empirical work of Dr. Franziska Engels conducted during her PhD research (Engels, 2020) and joint work with one of the co-authors (SP) previously published in another paper (Engels et al., 2019).

Author biographies

Sebastian Pfotenhauer is the co-director of the Munich Center for Technology in Society (MCTS) and incoming head of the STS Department at Technical University of Munich. His research interests include regional innovation cultures and models, the global political economy of innovation, co-creation and responsible innovation practices, and the governance of emerging technologies. He serves as coordinator of the EU-H2020 Project SCALINGS and the BMBF-funded ‘Munich Cluster for the Future of Mobility in Metropolitan Regions’ (MCube). He tweets on all things related to STS and critical innovation studies @smpfotenhauer.

Brice Laurent is a researcher at Mines ParisTech’s Center for the Sociology of Innovation. His research focuses on the relationships between innovation and democracy. He is the author of Democratic Experiments: Problematizing Nanotechnology and Democracy in Europe and the United States (2017, MIT Press), European Objects: The Troubled Dreams of Harmonization (2022, MIT Press), and co-editor, with Alexandre Mallard, of Labelling the Economy: Qualities and Values in Contemporary Markets (2020, Palgrave).

Kyriaki Papageorgiou is the Director of Research at Fusion Point, Esade Business and Law School. Her work is located at the intersection of anthropology and STS. Her current research examines policies, discourses and practices of innovation in tackling big societal challenges, and the emergent role of robotics and AI in transforming work and daily lives. She is particularly interested in the future of learning and engaged in collaborative projects on co-creation in education and challenge-driven innovation.

Jack Stilgoe is associate professor in the department of Science and Technology Studies at University College London, where he runs the Driverless Futures? project. He works on science and technology policy, the governance of emerging technologies and responsible innovation. His most recent book is Who’s Driving Innovation? New Technologies and the Collaborative State (2020, Palgrave). He hosts the Received Wisdom podcast with Shobita Parthasarathy and is a fellow of the Alan Turing Institute.

1.

We use the terms ‘up-scaling’, ‘scaling’, and ‘scalability’ somewhat interchangeably, depending on context.

2.

STS research on scale has evolved in conversation with work in other academic fields such as geography. At the interface with cultural, human and political geography, Barry’s work has addressed the controversies and geopolitics surrounding the scale of technical and knowledge infrastructures (Barry, 2001, 2013). This work taps into decades of research centrally concerned with questions of scale, particularly as part of globalization discourses and as a methodological yardstick for geographic inquiry (e.g. Herod and Wright, 2008; Sheppard and McMaster, 2008). Researchers in geography have, for example, investigated socio-material practices of association (Cox, 1997), subtle processes of socio-cultural reproduction and consumptions (Marston, 2000) and the historical-material ‘producedness’ of nature-culture that begets its own politics of scale beyond traditional Marxist readings of economic power and material determinism (Swyngedouw, 2008). They have also engaged in their fair share of controversy about the utility and ontological status of the concept of scale, for example in favor of flat ontologies or praxeological approaches (Hoefle, 2006; Marston et al., 2005).

3.

This echoes well-known challenges from the history of (medical) randomized controlled trials in terms ethics, bias, and social justice concerns (Baele, 2013; Deaton and Cartwright, 2018; Petryna, 2009; Teele, 2014; Wahlberg and McGoey, 2007).

Footnotes

Funding: The author(s) disclosed receipt of the following financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article: The authors gratefully acknowledge support by European Comission’s Horizon 2020 Science with and for Society (SwafS) program through the SCALINGS project (Grant No. 788359). In addition, SP acknowledges support by the DFG grant ‘Technoscientific Constitutionalism’ (Grant No. 643981).

References

  1. Abdelghafour N. (2017) Randomized controlled experiments to end poverty? Anthropologie and Développement 46–47: 235–262. [Google Scholar]
  2. Akrich M, Callon M, Latour B, et al. (2002. a) The key to success in innovation part i: The art of interessement. International Journal of Innovation Management 6(2): 187–206. [Google Scholar]
  3. Akrich M, Callon M, Latour B, et al. (2002. b) The key to success in innovation part ii: The art of choosing good spokespersons. International Journal of Innovation Management 6(2): 207–225. [Google Scholar]
  4. Arrow KJ. (1979) The Division of Labor in the Economy, the Polity, and Society. Adam, IA: Adam Smith and Modern Political Economy: Bicentennial Essays on the Wealth of Nations, 153–164. [Google Scholar]
  5. Baele SJ. (2013) The ethics of new development economics: Is the experimental approach to development economics morally wrong? The Journal of Philosophical Economics 7(1): 2–42. [Google Scholar]
  6. Barben D, Fisher E, Selin C, et al. (2008) Anticipatory governance of nanotechnoiogy: Foresight, engagement, and integration. In: Hackett EJ, Amsterdamska O, Lynch ME. (eds) The Handbook of Science and Technology Studies. Cambridge: MIT Press, 979–1000. [Google Scholar]
  7. Barry A. (2001) Political Machines: Governing a Technological Society. London: Athlone Press. [Google Scholar]
  8. Barry A. (2013) Material Politics: Disputes Along the Pipeline. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  9. Beck U. (1992) Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: SAGE Publications Ltd. [Google Scholar]
  10. Bédécarrats F, Guérin I, Roubaud F. (2019) All that glitters is not gold. The political economy of randomized evaluations in development. Development and Change 50(3): 735–762. [Google Scholar]
  11. Bédécarrats F, Guérin I, Roubaud F. (2020) Randomized Control Trials in the Field of Development: A Critical Perspective. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  12. Bijker W, Hughes TP, Pinch T. (1987) The Social Construction of Technological Systems: New Directions in the Sociology and History of Technology. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  13. Birch K. (2020) Technoscience rent: Toward a theory of rentiership for technoscientific capitalism. Science Technology & Human Values 45(1): 3–33. [Google Scholar]
  14. Birch K, Cochrane DT. (2021) Big Tech: Four emerging forms of digital rentiership. Science and Culture. Epub ahead of print 26 May 2021. DOI: 10.1080/09505431.2021.1932794 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  15. Birch K, Muniesa F. (2020) Assetization: Turning Things Into Assets in Technoscientific Capitalism. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  16. BIT (2020) The behavioural insights team. Available at: https://www.bi.team/about-us/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  17. Bold T, Kimenyi M, Mwabu G, et al. (2013) Scaling up what works: Experimental evidence on external validity in Kenyan education. Available at: https://www.cgdev.org/publication/scaling-what-works-experimental-evidence-external-validity-kenyan-education-working (accessed 11 October 2020).
  18. Bonchek M. (2016) How to create an exponential mindset. Available at: https://hbr.org/2016/07/how-to-create-an-exponential-mindset (accessed 11 October 2020).
  19. Bowker GC, Star SL. (2000) Sorting Things Out: Classification and Its Consequences. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Butler J. (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  21. Callon M, Lascoumes P, Barthe Y. (2009) Acting in an Uncertain World: An Essay on Technical Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  22. Callon M, Millo Y, Muniesa F. (eds) (2007) Market Devices. Oxford: Blackwell Publications. [Google Scholar]
  23. Chandler AD. (1994) Scale and Scope: The Dynamics of Industrial Capitalism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  24. Collingridge D. (1980) The Social Control of Technology. London: Frances Pinter. [Google Scholar]
  25. Colombo MG, Grilli L. (2010) On growth drivers of high-tech start-ups: Exploring the role of founders’ human capital and venture capital. Journal of Business Venturing 25(6): 610–626. [Google Scholar]
  26. Conger K. (2019. a) Uber embraces videotaping rides, raising privacy concerns. New York Times, 20 November.
  27. Conger K. (2019. b) Uber’s self-driving cars are valued at $7.25 billion by investors. New York Times, 18 April.
  28. Conger K, Scheiber N. (2019) California’s contractor law stirs confusion beyond the gig economy. New York Times, 11 September.
  29. Constine J. (2014) The morality of A/B testing. TechCrunch. Available at: https://social.techcrunch.com/2014/06/29/ethics-in-a-data-driven-world/ (accessed 22 September 2020).
  30. Constine J. (2018) Beyond the BS of Singularity U’s $32M raise to teach trendspotting. TechCrunch. Available at: https://social.techcrunch.com/2018/02/15/singularity-university/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  31. Cox KR. (ed.) (1997) Spaces of Globalization: Reasserting the Power of the Local. New York, NY: Guilford Press. [Google Scholar]
  32. Davidsson P. (1991) Continued entrepreneurship: Ability, need, and opportunity as determinants of small firm growth. Journal of Business Venturing 6(6): 405–429. [Google Scholar]
  33. Deaton A, Cartwright N. (2018) Understanding and misunderstanding randomized controlled trials. Social Science & Medicine 210: 2–21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Diamandis PH. (2017) Discovering your massively transformative purpose. Available at: https://www.diamandis.com/blog/discovering-your-massively-transformative-purpose (accessed 11 October 2020).
  35. Diamandis PH, Kotler S. (2016) Bold: How to Go Big, Create Wealth and Impact the World. New York: Simon and Schuster. [Google Scholar]
  36. Diao M, Kong H, Zhao J. (2021) Impacts of transportation network companies on urban mobility. Nature Sustainability 4(6): 494–500. [Google Scholar]
  37. Duprey R. (2020) Lawsuit alleging Uber’s anti-competitive practices drove rival out of business is moving forward. Available at: https://www.fool.com/investing/2020/05/04/lawsuit-alleging-ubers-anti-competitive-practices.aspx (accessed 22 September 2020).
  38. Ellis S, Brown M. (2017) Hacking Growth: How Today’s Fastest-Growing Companies Drive Breakout Success. New York: Crown. [Google Scholar]
  39. Engels F. (2020) Testing technologies – Re-configuring societies: Testing, contesting, and materializing visions of energy futures in two German test beds. PhD Dissertation. Technische Universität München, München. [Google Scholar]
  40. Engels F, Münch AV, Simon D. (2017) One site—multiple visions: Visioneering between contrasting actors’ perspectives. NanoEthics 11(1): 59–74. [Google Scholar]
  41. Engels F, Wentland A, Pfotenhauer SM. (2019) Testing future societies? Developing a framework for test beds and living labs as instruments of innovation governance. Research Policy 48(9): 103826. [Google Scholar]
  42. EUREF (2018. a) 10 years EUREF. Berlin: European energy forum. Available at: https://euref.de/wp-content/uploads/EUREF-EN_201108-Doppelseiten.pdf (accessed 11 October 2020). [Google Scholar]
  43. EUREF (2018. b) Die energiewende auf dem EUREF-campus. Available at: https://euref.de/die-energiewende-auf-dem-euref-campus-inforadio-berichtet/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  44. Evans D. (2015) Worm wars: The anthology. Available at: https://blogs.worldbank.org/impactevaluations/worm-wars-anthology (accessed 22 September 2020).
  45. Evans J, Karvonen A. (2014) ‘Give me a laboratory and I will lower your carbon footprint!’—Urban laboratories and the governance of low-carbon futures. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 38(2): 413–430. [Google Scholar]
  46. Ezrahi Y. (1990) The Descent of Icarus: Science and the Transformation of Contemporary Democracy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  47. Felt U. (2015) Keeping technologies out: Sociotechnical imaginaries and the formation of Austria’s technopolitical identity. In: Jasanoff S, Kim SH. (eds) Dreamscapes of Modernity: Sociotechnical Imaginaries and the Fabrication of Power. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 103–125. [Google Scholar]
  48. Feng E, Zhenyu Z. (2017) Uber XP: Building an intelligent experimentation platform with Uber engineering. Available at: https://eng.uber.com/experimentation-platform/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  49. Fisher E, Mahajan RL, Mitcham C. (2006) Midstream modulation of technology: Governance from within. Bulletin of Science Technology & Society 26(6): 485–496. [Google Scholar]
  50. Fleck L. (1981) Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
  51. Foucault M. (1980) Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977. New York: Vintage. [Google Scholar]
  52. Frahm N, Doezema T, Pfotenhauer S. (2021) Fixing technology with society: The coproduction of democratic deficits and responsible innovation at the OECD and the European Commission. Science Technology & Human Values. Epub ahead of print 15 March 2021. DOI: 10.1177/0162243921999100 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  53. Gabriel M. (2014) Making It Big. Strategies for Scaling Social Innovations. London: National Endowment for Science, Technology and the Arts. [Google Scholar]
  54. Gillespie T. (2010) The politics of ‘platforms’. New Media & Society 12(3): 347–364. [Google Scholar]
  55. Gillespie T. (2018) The scale is just unfathomable. Available at: https://logicmag.io/scale/the-scale-is-just-unfathomable/ (accessed 22 September 2020).
  56. Gooding D, Pinch T, Schaffer S. (1989) The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  57. Gross M. (2016) Give me an experiment and I will raise a laboratory. Science Technology & Human Values 41(4): 613–634. [Google Scholar]
  58. Guridi JA, Pertuze JA, Pfotenhauer SM. (2020) Natural laboratories as policy instruments for technological learning and institutional capacity building: The case of Chile’s astronomy cluster. Research Policy 49(2): 103899. [Google Scholar]
  59. Hall JV, Krueger AB. (2018) An analysis of the labor market for Uber’s driver-partners in the United States. ILR Review 71(3): 705–732. [Google Scholar]
  60. Halpern D. (2019) Finding the ‘unicorns’: Behavioural science in government grows up. Available at: https://quarterly.blog.gov.uk/2019/10/30/finding-the-unicorns-behavioural-science-in-government-grows-up/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  61. Haraway D. (1988) Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies 14(3): 575. [Google Scholar]
  62. Haraway DJ. (2016) Staying With the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Experimental Futures. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
  63. Harding S. (2006) Science and Social Inequality: Feminist and Postcolonial Issues. Champaign: University of Illinois Press. [Google Scholar]
  64. Hart DM. (2001) Antitrust and technological innovation in the US: Ideas, institutions, decisions, and impacts, 1890–2000. Research Policy 30(6): 923–936. [Google Scholar]
  65. Hawkins AJ. (2020) Uber has resumed testing its self-driving cars in San Francisco. The Verge. Available at: https://www.theverge.com/2020/3/10/21172213/uber-self-driving-car-resume-testing-san-francisco-crash (accessed 22 September 2020).
  66. Heller MA, Eisenberg RS. (1998) Can patents deter innovation? The anticommons in biomedical research. Science 280(5364): 698–701. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  67. Herod A, Wright MW. (2008) Geographies of Power: Placing Scale. Hoboken: John Wiley and Sons. [Google Scholar]
  68. Hilgartner S. (2000) Science on Stage: Expert Advice as Public Drama. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  69. Hilgartner S. (2015) Capturing the imaginary: Vanguards, visions and the synthetic biology revolution. In: Hilgartner S, Miller C, Hagendijk R. (eds) Science and Democracy: Making Knowledge and Making Power in the Biosciences and Beyond. London: Routledge, 33–55. [Google Scholar]
  70. Hilgartner S. (2017) Reordering Life: Knowledge and Control in the Genomics Revolution. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  71. Hoefle SW. (2006) Eliminating scale and killing the goose that laid the golden egg? Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 31(2): 238–243. [Google Scholar]
  72. Hoffman R, Yeh C. (2018) Blitzscaling: The Lightning-Fast Path to Building Massively Valuable Companies. New York: Currency. [Google Scholar]
  73. Hounshell D. (1985) From the American System to Mass Production, 1800-1932: The Development of Manufacturing Technology in the United States. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. [Google Scholar]
  74. Hurlbut JB. (2015) Remembering the future: Science, law, and the legacy of Asilomar. In: Jasanoff S, Kim S-H. (eds) Dreamscapes of Modernity: Sociotechical Imaginaries and the Fabrication of Power. Chicago: University Of Chicago Press, 126–151. [Google Scholar]
  75. Hurlbut JB, Jasanoff S, Saha K. (2020) Constitutionalism at the nexus of life and law. Science Technology & Human Values 45(6): 979–1000. [Google Scholar]
  76. IEEE (2020) IEEE – Ethically aligned design, version 1, translations and reports. Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers. 30 March. Available at: https://standards.ieee.org/industry-connections/ec/ead-v1.html (accessed 30 March 2020). [Google Scholar]
  77. IGL (2020) Innovation growth lab. Available at: https://www.innovationgrowthlab.org/innovation-growth-lab (accessed 11 October 2020).
  78. Isaac M, Merced MJ, Sorkin AR. (2019) How the promise of a $120 billion uber I.P.O. Evaporated. Available at: https://www.nytimes.com/2019/05/15/technology/uber-ipo-price.html (accessed 22 September 2020).
  79. Jasanoff S. (1994) The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers As Policymakers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  80. Jasanoff S. (1995) Product, process, or programme: Three cultures and the regulation of biotechnology. In: Bauer M. (ed.) Resistance to New Technology: Nuclear Power, Information Technology, and Biotechnology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 311–332. [Google Scholar]
  81. Jasanoff S. (ed.) (2004) States of Knowledge: The Co-production of Science and the Social Order. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  82. Jasanoff S. (2005) Designs on Nature: Science and Democracy in Europe and the United States. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  83. Jasanoff S. (2010) A new climate for society. Theory Culture & Society 27(2–3): 233–253. [Google Scholar]
  84. Jasanoff S. (ed.) (2011) Reframing Rights: Bioconstitutionalism in the Genetic Age. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  85. Jasanoff S. (2012) Science and Public Reason. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  86. Jasanoff S, Kim S-H. (2009) Containing the atom: Sociotechnical imaginaries and nuclear power in the United States and South Korea. Minerva 47(2): 119–146. [Google Scholar]
  87. Jasanoff SS. (1987) Contested boundaries in policy-relevant science. Social Studies of Science 17(2): 195–230. [Google Scholar]
  88. Jatteau A. (2013) Expérimenter le développement ? Geneses 93(4): 8–28. [Google Scholar]
  89. Jensen MC. (2001) Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 14(3): 8–21. [Google Scholar]
  90. Joas F, Pahle M, Flachsland C, et al. (2016) Which goals are driving the Energiewende? Making sense of the German Energy Transformation. Energy Policy 95(C): 42–51. [Google Scholar]
  91. Johnston SF. (2018) The technological fix as social cure-all: Origins and implications. IEEE Technology and Society Magazine 37(1): 47–54. [Google Scholar]
  92. J-PAL (2020. a) About us. Available at: https://www.povertyactionlab.org/about-j-pal (accessed 22 September 2020).
  93. J-PAL (2020. b) Evidence to policy. Available at: https://www.povertyactionlab.org/evidence-to-policy (accessed 11 October 2020).
  94. J-PAL (2020. c) J-PAL Europe. Available at: https://www.povertyactionlab.org/europe (accessed 22 September 2021).
  95. J-PAL (2020. d) Scaling up an evaluated pilot. Available at: https://www.povertyactionlab.org/evidence-to-policy/scaling-evaluated-pilot (accessed 22 September 2021).
  96. Kaminska I. (2016) Mythbusting Uber’s valuation. Available at: http://ftalphaville.ft.com/2016/09/13/2173631/mythbusting-ubers-valuation/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  97. Kareborn BB, Stahlbrost A. (2009) Living lab: An open and citizen-centric approach for innovation. International Journal of Innovation and Regional Development 1(4): 356–370. [Google Scholar]
  98. Karvonen A. (2018) The city of permanent experiments? In: Turnheim B, Kivimaa P, Burkhout F. (eds) Innovating Climate Governance: Moving Beyond Experiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 201–215. [Google Scholar]
  99. Kenney M, Zysman J. (2019) Unicorns, Cheshire cats, and the new dilemmas of entrepreneurial finance. Venture Capital 21(1): 35–50. [Google Scholar]
  100. Khan LM. (2016) Amazon’s antitrust paradox. The Yale Law Journal 126(3): 710. [Google Scholar]
  101. Khan LM, Vaheesan S. (2017) Market power and inequality: The antitrust counterrevolution and its discontents. Harvard Law and Policy Review 11: 235. [Google Scholar]
  102. Krohn W, Weyer J. (1994) Society as a laboratory: The social risks of experimental research. Science and Public Policy 21(3): 173–183. [Google Scholar]
  103. Latour B. (1988) The Pasteurization of France (Sheridan A, Law J, trans). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  104. Latour B. (1993) We Have Never Been Modern (Porter C, trans). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  105. Latour B. (1983) Give me a laboratory and I will raise the world. In: Knorr-Cetina K, Mulkay M. (eds) Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of Science. London: SAGE Publications, 141–170. [Google Scholar]
  106. Latour B. (2018) Down to Earth: Politics in the New Climatic Regime. Malden: Wiley. [Google Scholar]
  107. Latour B, Woolgar S. (1986) Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  108. Laurent B. (2016) Political experiments that matter: Ordering democracy from experimental sites. Social Studies of Science 46(5): 773–794. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  109. Laurent B. (2017) Democratic Experiments: Problematizing Nanotechnology and Democracy in Europe and the United States. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  110. Laurent B, Lechevalier S. (2019) Innovation for whom? City experiments and the redefinition of urban democracy. In: Lechevalier S. (ed.) Innovation Beyond Technology: Science for Society and Interdisciplinary Approaches. Singapore: Springer, 265–283. [Google Scholar]
  111. Laurent B, Doganova L, Gasull C, et al. (2021) The test bed island: Tech business experimentalism and exception in Singapore. Science and Culture 30(3): 367–390. [Google Scholar]
  112. Laurent B, Tironi M. (2015) A field test and its displacements. Accounting for an experimental mode of industrial innovation. CoDesign 11(3–4): 208–221. [Google Scholar]
  113. Lazonick W, O’Sullivan M. (2000) Maximizing shareholder value: A new ideology for corporate governance. Economy and Society 29(1): 13–35. [Google Scholar]
  114. Leach M, Stirling AC, Scoones I, et al. (2010) Dynamic Sustainabilities: Technology, Environment, Social Justice. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  115. Lemov R. (2006) World As Laboratory: Experiments With Mice, Mazes, and Men. New York: Hill and Wang Pub. [Google Scholar]
  116. Levidow L, Birch K, Papaioannou T. (2013) Divergent paradigms of European agro-food innovation. Science Technology & Human Values 38(1): 94–125. [Google Scholar]
  117. Levidow L, Murphy J, Carr S. (2007) Recasting “substantial equivalence”: Transatlantic governance of GM food. Science Technology & Human Values 32(1): 26–64. [Google Scholar]
  118. Manne GA, Wright JD. (2011) Google and the limits of antitrust: The case against the antitrust case against Google. Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 34: 171–244. [Google Scholar]
  119. Marres N. (2020) Co-existence or displacement: Do street trials of intelligent vehicles test society? British Journal of Sociology 71(3): 537–555. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  120. Marres N, Stark D. (2020) Put to the test: For a new sociology of testing. British Journal of Sociology 71(3): 423–443. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  121. Marston SA. (2000) The social construction of scale. Progress in Human Geography 24(2): 219–242. [Google Scholar]
  122. Marston SA, Jones JP, Woodward K. (2005) Human geography without scale. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 30(4): 416–432. [Google Scholar]
  123. Mazzucato M. (2018) Mission-Oriented Research and Innovation in the European Union: A Problem-Solving Approach to Fuel Innovation-Led Growth. Brussels: European Comission. [Google Scholar]
  124. McCormick R. (2016) Uber forced to remove self-driving cars from San Francisco roads. Available at: https://www.theverge.com/2016/12/21/14049070/uber-san-francisco-self-driving-removed-registration-revoked (accessed 22 September 2020).
  125. McCraw TK, Chandler AD. (1991) The Essential Alfred Chandler: Essays Toward a Historical Theory of Big Business. Boston: Harvard Business Press. [Google Scholar]
  126. McKinsey (2019) How to move fast: Corporate innovation at speed and scale. The Verge. Available at: https://www.mckinsey.com/business-functions/strategy-and-corporate-finance/our-insights/how-to-move-fast-innovation-at-speed-and-scale (accessed 11 October 2020).
  127. Miller C. (2004) Climate science and the making of a global political order. In: Jasanoff S. (ed.) States of Knowledge: The Co-production of Science and Social Order. New York: Routledge, 46–67. [Google Scholar]
  128. Millo Y, Lezaun J. (2006) Regulatory experiments: Genetically modified crops and financial derivatives on trial. Science and Public Policy 33(3): 179–190. [Google Scholar]
  129. Morozov E. (2013) To Save Everything, Click Here: The Folly of Technological Solutionism. New York: PublicAffairs. [Google Scholar]
  130. Morroni M. (2009) Knowledge, Scale and Transactions in the Theory of the Firm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  131. Musa M, Rodin J. (2016) Scaling Up Social Innovation (SSIR). Available at: https://ssir.org/articles/entry/scaling_up_social_innovation (accessed 11 October 2020).
  132. Nobel Prize Committee (2019) The Sveriges Riksbank prize in economic sciences in memory of Alfred Nobel 2019. Available at: https://www.nobelprize.org/prizes/economic-sciences/2019/prize-announcement/ (accessed 22 September 2020).
  133. Ong A, Collier SJ. (eds) (2004) Global Assemblages: Technology, Politics, and Ethics as Anthropological Problems. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  134. Papageorgiou K. (2017) Labs for social innovation. Barcelona, Spain: ESADE Institute for Social Innovation/Robert Bosch Stiftung. Available at: https://itemsweb.esade.edu/research/Labs-Social-Innovation-ESADE.pdf (accessed 08 September 2021). [Google Scholar]
  135. Petryna A. (2009) When Experiments Travel: Clinical Trials and the Global Search for Human Subjects. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  136. Pfotenhauer S. (2017) Co-producing Emirati science and society at Masdar Institute of Science and Technology. In: Siddiqui A and Anadon LD (eds) Science and Technology Development in the Gulf States. Berlin, Germany: Gerlach Press, 89–113. [Google Scholar]
  137. Pfotenhauer S, Jasanoff S. (2017. a) Panacea or diagnosis? Imaginaries of innovation and the ‘MIT model’ in three political cultures. Social Studies of Science 47(6): 783–810. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  138. Pfotenhauer S, Jasanoff S. (2017. b) Traveling imaginaries: The ‘practice turn’ in innovation policy and the global circulation of innovation models. In: Tyfield D, Randalls S, Lave R. (eds) The Routledge Handbook of the Political Economy of Science. New York: Routledge, 416–428. [Google Scholar]
  139. Pfotenhauer SM, Juhl J, Aarden E. (2019) Challenging the “deficit model” of innovation: Framing policy issues under the innovation imperative. Research Policy 48(4): 895–904. [Google Scholar]
  140. Pfotenhauer SM, Juhl J, Aarden E. (2019) Challenging the “deficit model” of innovation: Framing policy issues under the innovation imperative. Research Policy 48(4): 895–904. [Google Scholar]
  141. Pfotenhauer SM, Frahm N, Winickoff D, et al. (2021) Mobilizing the private sector for responsible innovation innovation in neurotechnology. Nature Biotechnology 39: 68–94. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. Pinch T. (1993) ‘Testing – one, two, three … Testing!’: Toward a sociology of testing. Science Technology & Human Values 18(1): 25–41. [Google Scholar]
  143. Poel I van de, Robaey Z. (2017) Safe-by-design: From safety to responsibility. NanoEthics 11(3): 297–306. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  144. Prasad A. (2014) Imperial Technoscience: Transnational Histories of MRI in the United States, Britain, and India. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  145. Rayzberg MS. (2019) Fairness in the field: The ethics of resource allocation in randomized controlled field experiments. Science Technology & Human Values 44(3): 371–398. [Google Scholar]
  146. Reddy SG. (2019) Economics’ biggest success story is a cautionary tale. Available at: https://foreignpolicy.com/2019/10/22/economics-development-rcts-esther-duflo-abhijit-banerjee-michael-kremer-nobel/ (accessed 11 October 2020).
  147. Renn O. (2018) Real-world laboratories - the road to transdisciplinary research? GAIA - Ecological Perspectives for Science and Society 27(1): 1–1. [Google Scholar]
  148. Rogers EM. (2003) Diffusion of Innovations, 5th edn. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
  149. Rosner L. (2004) The Technological Fix: How People Use Technology to Create and Solve Problems, illustrat edn. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  150. Scherer FM. (1980) Industrial Market Structure and Economic Performance. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. [Google Scholar]
  151. Schot J, Kanger L. (2018) Deep transitions: Emergence, acceleration, stabilization and directionality. Research Policy 47(6): 1045–1059. [Google Scholar]
  152. Schot J, Rip A. (1997) The past and future of constructive technology assessment. Technological Forecasting and Social Change 54(2–3): 251–268. [Google Scholar]
  153. Schwarz-Plaschg C, Kallhoff A, Eisenberger I. (2017) Making nanomaterials safer by design? NanoEthics 11(3): 277–281. [Google Scholar]
  154. Scott JC. (1999) Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed, new edn. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
  155. Scranton P. (1999) Creating the corporate soul: The rise of public relations and corporate imagery in American big business. Journal of American History 86(2): 819. [Google Scholar]
  156. Seelos C, Mair J. (2017) Innovation and Scaling for Impact: How Effective Social Enterprises Do It. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  157. Shapin S, Schaffer S. (1985) Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  158. Sheppard E, McMaster RB. (2008) Scale and Geographic Inquiry: Nature, Society, and Method. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  159. Singularity University (2021) Our Mission. Available at: https://www.su.org/about (accessed 22 September 2021).
  160. Star SL. (1999) The ethnography of infrastructure. American Behavioral Scientist 43(3): 377–391. [Google Scholar]
  161. Stein J. (2019) 3 Share Nobel Prize in economics for ‘experimental approaches’ to solving poverty. The Washington Post, 14 October. Sergio: EIC. [Google Scholar]
  162. Stilgoe J. (2016) Geoengineering as collective experimentation. Science and Engineering Ethics 22(3): 851–869. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  163. Stilgoe J. (2018) Machine learning, social learning and the governance of self-driving cars. Social Studies of Science 48(1): 25–56. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  164. Stilgoe J. (2019) Self-driving cars will take a while to get right. Nature Machine Intelligence 1(5): 202–203. [Google Scholar]
  165. Stilgoe J. (2020) Who’s Driving Innovation? New Technologies and the Collaborative State. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  166. Stilgoe J, Owen R, Macnaghten P. (2013) Developing a framework for responsible innovation. Research Policy 42(9): 1568–1580. [Google Scholar]
  167. Strathern M. (2020) Relations: An Anthropological Account. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
  168. Sundararajan A. (2014) What Airbnb gets about culture that Uber doesn’t. Harvard Business Review. Available at: https://hbr.org/2014/11/what-airbnb-gets-about-culture-that-uber-doesnt (accessed 22 September 2020).
  169. Sundararajan A. (2016) The Sharing Economy: The End of Employment and the Rise of Crowd-Based Capitalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  170. Sunder Rajan K. (2006) Biocapital: The Constitution of Postgenomic Life. Durham: Duke University Press Books. [Google Scholar]
  171. Sunder Rajan K. (2017) Pharmocracy: Value, Politics, and Knowledge in Global Biomedicine. Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
  172. Swyngedouw E. (2008) Scaled geographies: Nature, place, and the politics of scale. In: Sheppard E, McMaster RB. (eds) Scale and Geographic Inquiry. Hoboken: John Wiley and Sons, 129–153. [Google Scholar]
  173. TallBear K. (2013) Native American DNA: Tribal Belonging and the False Promise of Genetic Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
  174. Teele DL. (2014) Field Experiments and Their Critics: Essays on the Uses and Abuses of Experimentation in the Social Sciences. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
  175. Tennant C, Stilgoe J. (2021) The attachments of ‘autonomous’ vehicles. Social Studies of Science. Epub ahead of print 14 August 2021. DOI: 10.1177/03063127211038752 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  176. Thiel P. (2014) Zero to One: Notes on Startups, or How to Build the Future. New York: Crown Business. [Google Scholar]
  177. Tiles M, Oberdiek (1995) Living in a Technological Culture: Human Tools and Human Values. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  178. Tollefson J. (2015) Can randomized trials eliminate global poverty? Nature 524(7564): 150–153. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  179. Tsing A. (2009) Supply chains and the juman condition. Rethinking Marxism 21(2): 148–176. [Google Scholar]
  180. Tsing AL. (2005) Friction: An Ethnography of Global Connection. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  181. Tsing AL. (2012) On nonscalability: The living world is not amenable to precision-nested scales. Common Knowledge 18(3): 505–524. [Google Scholar]
  182. Uber Newsroom (2021) First independent survey shows 4 out of 5 California drivers with Uber are happy. Prop 22 passed. Available at: https://www.uber.com/newsroom/prop-22-survey-results/ (accessed 20 August 2021).
  183. Viscusi WK, Vernon JM, Harrington JE. (2000) Economics of Regulation and Antitrust. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  184. Visvanathan S. (1997. a) A Carnival for Science: Essays on Science, Technology and Development. Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  185. Visvanathan S. (1997. b) On the annals of the laboratory state. In: A Carnival for Science: Essays on Science, Technology and Development. Delhi: Oxford University Press, 15–47. [Google Scholar]
  186. Visvanathan S. (2005) Knowledge, justice and democracy. In: Leach M, Scoones I, Wynne B. (eds) Science and Citizens: Globalization and the Challenge of Engagement. London: Zed Books, 83–94. [Google Scholar]
  187. Volti R. (2006) Society and Technological Change, 5th edn. New York, NY: Worth Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  188. Voß J-P, Simons A. (2014) Instrument constituencies and the supply side of policy innovation: The social life of emissions trading. Environmental Politics 23(5): 735–754. [Google Scholar]
  189. Voß J-P, Simons A. (2018) A novel understanding of experimentation in governance: Co-producing innovations between ‘lab’ and ‘field’. Policy Sciences 51(2): 213–229. [Google Scholar]
  190. Wahlberg A, McGoey L. (2007) An elusive evidence base: The construction and governance of randomized controlled trials. BioSocieties 2(1): 1–10. [Google Scholar]
  191. Wentland A. (2018) Charging visions: Eelectric cars and the reimagination of industrial and social order in Germany. PhD Dissertation, Technical University Berlin, Germany. [Google Scholar]
  192. Westley F, Antadze N, Riddell DJ, et al. (2014) Five configurations for scaling up social innovation: Case examples of nonprofit organizations from Canada. The Journal of Applied Behavioral Science 50(3): 234–260. [Google Scholar]
  193. Wilsdon J, Willis R. (2004) See-Through Science: Why Public Engagement Needs to Move Upstream. London: Demos. [Google Scholar]
  194. Winickoff D, Pfotenhauer S. (2018) Technology governance and the innovation process. In: OECD Science, Technology and Innovation Outlook 2018 Adapting to Technological and Societal Disruption. Paris: Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development Publishing, 221–240. [Google Scholar]
  195. Winickoff DE, Mondou M. (2017) The problem of epistemic jurisdiction in global governance: The case of sustainability standards for biofuels. Social Studies of Science 47(1): 7–32. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  196. Wu T. (2018) The Curse of Bigness: Antitrust in the New Gilded Age. New York: Columbia Global Reports. [Google Scholar]
  197. Wynne B. (1992) Misunderstood misunderstanding: Social identities and public uptake of science. Public Understanding of Science 1(3): 281–304. [Google Scholar]
  198. Zuboff S. (2019) The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier of Power. New York: PublicAffairs. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Social Studies of Science are provided here courtesy of SAGE Publications

RESOURCES