Abstract
Our ability to comprehend and produce language is one of humans’ most impressive skills, but it is not flawless. We must convey and interpret messages via a noisy channel in ever-changing contexts and we sometimes fail to access an optimal combination of words and grammatical constructions. Here, we extend the notion of good-enough (GN) comprehension to GN production, which allows us to unify a wide range of phenomena including overly vague word choices, agreement errors, resumptive pronouns, transfer effects, and children’s overextensions and regularizations. We suggest these all involve the accessing and production of a ‘GN’ option when a more-optimal option is inaccessible. The role of accessibility highlights the need to relate memory encoding and retrieval processes to language comprehension and production.
Keywords: language production, communication, good-enough processing
‘when I was in court I forgot what to call the judge and I accidentally called him Your Majesty and he was like WHAT and I REPEATED IT ’ – vidawgggon Twitter
Language processing is impressive but imperfect
Humans are remarkably adept at using language to communicate their ideas, but language processing does not operate flawlessly. People may misinterpret what they hear or see: for example, The dog was bitten by the professor may be misunderstood as the more plausible utterance The dog bit the professor [1]. In this review, we extend the familiar idea of ‘good-enough (GN) comprehension’ to the arena of production to focus on when and why language users produce utterances that are only good enough rather than optimal. We begin with a brief description of GN comprehension before proceeding to the focus of our opinion article, a range of phenomena that constitute evidence of GN production, with examples from adult and child speech. We then discuss the relationship between GN comprehension and production and the implications for language processing generally.
GN comprehension is recognized to reflect a divergence between what a person says and what the comprehender understands. It is illustrated with systematic errors evoked in experimental contexts, as illustrated in Table 1 (for a review see [2]). Since it is widely accepted that comprehenders combine all available cues – contextual, semantic, and formal – to incrementally access relevant prior linguistic and non-linguistic representations required for interpretation [3., 4., 5., 6.], here we more specifically characterize GN comprehension as resulting from a failure to access the particular combination of linguistic tools – lexical and grammatical constructions -that were generated by the speaker or a failure to access them fully during the interpretation of the utterance. Note that this interpretation of GN comprehension differs slightly from what is commonly meant by ‘shallow parsing’, although the terms are often used interchangeably. GN comprehension is broader, as it allows for misinterpretations from sources other than imperfectly parsed syntax. For instance, a classic example of GN comprehension, the ‘Moses illusion’ ([7], see Box 1) results from a failure of appropriate lexical access rather than any misparsed syntax. GN comprehension can alternatively arise from fully accessing an incorrect grammatical (syntactic) construction. This understanding allows us to bring GN production into focus.
Table 1.
Lexical misinterpretations | |
How many of each kind of animal did Moses take on the Ark?
What’s the name of the Mexican dip made with mashed up artichokes? After an airplane crash, where should the survivors be buried? |
Responses such as ‘two’, ‘guacamole’, and ‘in a graveyard’, respectively, due to: (i) priming of a relevant semantic frame; (ii) semantic and/or phonological relatedness between the witnessed and intended words (Moses ~ Noah; artichokes ~ avocado; survivors ~ victims) [7,85] |
Misinterpretations of grammatical constructions | |
The dog was bitten by the professor | Misinterpreted as ‘The dog bit the professor’ due to easier accessibility of (i) the more plausible and familiar semantic frame and (ii) the transitive construction being more frequent than the full passive [1,86,87] |
The ancient manuscript that [the grad student who the new card catalog had confused a great deal was studying] was missing a page | Misinterpreted as acceptable even without the underlined obligatory verb phrase, in part due to complexity-induced overload of working memory [88., 89., 90., 91.] |
While Keisha changed the baby played in the crib | Misinterpretation due to a failure to (i) inhibit ‘Keisha changed the baby’ and (ii) to access the reflexive meaning of ‘changed’; due to interference as a result of local coherence - the naturalness of a word sequence within an utterance [8,92., 93., 94.] |
Good-enough (GN) production
The term ‘good-enough production’ has rarely been invoked (but see [8., 9., 10.]), despite the widespread recognition of GN comprehension. One reason for this may be the perspective clearly articulated by one expert who viewed comprehension errors as arising from a failure to process syntax and notes the lack of a clear analog in production:
‘many of the aspects of a sentence’s surface form appear to play a relatively minor role in comprehension, in comparison with higher level semantic and knowledge integration processes…[I]n sentence production, on the other hand, it is necessary to create a surface structure…[and] to do so requires the paraphernalia of the correct morphology, constituent structure and order’ ([11], see pp. 1–2).
By contrast, here we emphasize that both comprehenders and producers have a complex suite of lexical and grammatical tools with which to express a message or interpret an utterance. When the language user is unable to access the right tools for the job or is unable to access their form or content fully, they instead settle on options that are not optimal but which they believe (or hope) are good enough. During production, forms are necessarily articulated, but the selected forms do not necessarily optimally convey the intended message. That is, GN productions are utterances that only approximate an optimal way of expressing a speaker (or signer’s) intended message because of a failure to access optimal tools at the moment of speaking.
The claim that an utterance is nonoptimal predicts that speakers of the same dialect would, in principle, recognize it as nonoptimal, which can be demonstrated via judgment tasks, paraphrase tasks, or explicit comparisons with an alternative (e.g., [12., 13., 14.]). As is true for GN comprehension, GN production may result in miscommunication. However, as is also true of GN comprehension, a GN utterance may alternatively be good enough to avoid communication failure. That is, the extent to which GN processing results in miscommunication in naturalistic contexts remains unclear [15., 16., 17., 18., 19., 20.]. As the term ‘good enough’ suggests, a failure to interpret each and every sentence strictly veridically does not necessarily lead to miscommunication [16,17] and neither does the production of a nonoptimal utterance. For instance, if asked in a natural context, ‘How many of each kind of animal did Moses bring on the Ark?’ it may be more appropriate to respond ‘two’ than to object that the speaker should have asked about Noah. After all, speakers rarely intentionally mislead their audience in the way that experimenters do. GN comprehension, then, may be an adaptive response to the reality of GN production. It can be useful for comprehenders to infer an interpretation that reflects what the speaker is likely to have meant even if that differs from what was literally stated [16., 17., 18.].
Accessing any representation from memory is recognized to be affected by multiple interacting factors. Accessibility is positively influenced by relevance, appropriateness, frequency, and priming and is negatively influenced by noise, interference, competition, and time pressure [10,21., 22., 23., 24., 25., 26., 27., 28.]. Accessibility is also influenced by task demands [29., 30., 31.]; for instance, we expect comprehenders to interpret implausible utterances more quickly and accurately when tasked with judging their plausibility (e.g., [30]), and likewise, errors are detected more readily when participants are asked to act as fact checkers [31].
By emphasizing that GN production involves accessing a GN option rather than one that is optimal, it becomes clear that the psycholinguistic literature provides many examples of GN production by both adults and children.
Good-enough production in adults
Lexical choices
The epigraph of this opinion article provides a memorable example of the production of a lexical phrase that is nonoptimal but in the right semantic ballpark, influenced by accessibility (Your Majesty rather than Your Honor). Overly vague terms, such as those underlined in (i), provide another straightforward illustration of GN production:
-
(i)
Does this house have a tea thingy? Like, um... You know what I mean, like, um... Like a hot water source. A kettle! Kettle. A kettle. Man, I am not doing great. (COCA MOV 2019 [32])
The underlined words in (i) are fully accessed and clearly articulated, but the speaker does not view them as optimal, as is made explicit in the rest of the passage (cf. kettle). That is, since kettle is not immediately accessible to the speaker, nonoptimal formulations are used instead as reasonable approximations (e.g., thingy, a hot water source).
The role of accessibility in language production is supported by a good deal of experimental work. For example, a higher-frequency word, being more easily accessed, is more likely to be used to convey a novel related meaning than a semantically similar less-frequent word [10,33,34]. Beyond frequency is the positive influence of priming on lexical choice. In one series of experiments, participants were given a preamble such as The woman went to the convent to become a __ and were then asked to immediately label an image of a priest [9]. Participants produced nun rather than priest roughly 20% of the time. Participants were also lured by phonological accessibility. For instance, following I thought there would still be some cookies left but there were __, participants labeled the image of the priest nun 10% of the time. In both cases, participants produced a description (nun) that was made highly accessible and that was in the semantic ballpark of an optimal description (priest) but clearly not the optimal form.
Recent results from another clever experiment demonstrate that speakers are willing to sacrifice accuracy in favor of a GN option that is more accessible even without prior priming [10]. Adults were taught eight novel words that named particular compass angles; four of the novel terms were witnessed less often than four other terms, making them lower frequency in the context of the experiment (lower frequency vs higher frequency; Figure 1). When asked to name angles that fell between those that had been labeled (indicated in gray), speakers tended to use the higher-frequency terms, even when a lower-frequency label more accurately described the angle. When no time pressure was imposed, speakers were able to access and appropriately use the lower frequency novel terms, demonstrating that the failure to use them when a speedy response was required was due to the challenge of accessing them rather than a failure to learn them at all [10]. The study also found that participants responded more slowly as the target angle was closer to the middle of two angles (Figure 1B), since these positions rendered the competition between two labels stronger.
Participants were taught HF and LF novel words for particular angles and were then queried about various angles between them (in gray). High competition trials included the angles close to the midpoint of two named angles. Under time pressure, participants showed a tendency to use the HF words, even when a LF word would have been more accurate. Image from Koranda et al. (2018) [10].
Agreement errors
The idea that we access and combine lexical and grammatical constructions during production, occasionally retrieving a competing but nonoptimal option, finds support in work on systematic ‘agreement’ errors; for instance, speakers regularly produce verbs that erroneously agree in number with the noun that happens to immediately precede rather than with the subject of the sentence. For instance, in (ii), the plural verb were agrees with the plural noun earrings rather than the singular noun value:
-
(ii)
I don’t know what the value of the earrings were. (COCA_SPOK_2004 [32])
To produce the more-optimal verb form (was), the speaker needed to reactivate the subject noun (value) and suppress interference from the plural noun earrings. Agreement errors are influenced by meaning: they increase when a formally singular subject receives a plural interpretation (e.g., the label on the bottles were) [35] and they are more difficult to detect when there is a strong semantic association between the intervening noun and verb (e.g., the drawer of knives cut) [36]. Another influence in English is the existence of a competing (quantificational) construction in which N2 rather than N1 is the controller of agreement, as in (iii) [37]:
-
(iii)
A lot of the books are
(cf. The cover of the books is)
Speakers with stronger working memory are more successful at inhibiting interference from the intervening noun and irrelevant competing construction [35,38], as is expected if such errors arise as the speaker aims to inhibit nonoptimal constructions to access an optimal one [37,39]. By recognizing that speakers need to access grammatical patterns as well as words, we predict that languages with different inventories of grammatical constructions will be affected by lexical accessibility in different ways, as has been found to be the case [40].
When no optimal option exists: resumptive pronouns in English
Speakers (and signers) aim to produce an optimal combination of constructions to express their intended messages in context. At the same time, production is incremental in that language users do not fully access all words and constructions before they begin their utterances. This can lead language users to find themselves midway through an utterance without an optimal combination of constructions available. In this case, they often carry on as best they can, even if doing so results in an utterance that sounds awkward or contains an error. This can be illustrated by resumptive pronouns in English relative clauses (RCs).
Fully acceptable English RCs can be thought of as containing a ‘gap’ where the head noun would normally appear in a canonical clause. For instance, in (iv) certain codes appears before the RC, not after the verb, broken, as it would in a simple clause (she had broken certain codes):
-
(iv)
She knew certain codes that no one suspected she had broken ___.
Certain grammatical and discourse contexts disfavor gaps for reasons that remain debated, (e.g., [41,42]). For instance, English speakers judge sentences such as (v) to be relatively unacceptable:
-
(v)
There are certain codes that if you break ____, you suffer something much worse than political defeat.
The sentence in (v) is improved by the inclusion of a ‘resumptive pronoun’ at the gap site as in (vi), which is likely due to the local formal and semantic acceptability of the phrase – if you break them – in isolation.
-
(vi)
‘There are certain codes that if you break them, you suffer something much worse than political defeat’ [43].
The presence of a resumptive pronoun improves certain utterances [e.g., (vi) vs (v)], but it does not make them fully acceptable [44]. Moreover, recent work has found that English sentences with resumptive pronouns can be more difficult to comprehend than grammatical controls [45]. Thus, a relative clause with a resumptive pronoun is nonoptimal in that it is inelegant and somewhat difficult for listeners to process. It is used, as a GN formulation, presumably because English does not provide an optimal means to continue the message in (vi) once the embedded clause (that if you) is begun. That is, English does not provide a simple way to introduce an entity while predicating a property of it in the same clause [which is presumably why (vi) was published in the prestigious New York Times].
It is surprisingly easy to elicit utterances containing resumptive pronouns in experimental settings. For example, in one study [46] participants were shown a series of trials comprising an image of an entity followed by a brief phrase. Through a combination of instructions and priming, participants were encouraged to produce utterances that began, This is a <image-label> that <phrase>. After trials such as those in (vii), if a third trial provided the phrase ‘don’t know,’ speakers tended to produce a relative clause with a resumptive pronoun, as in (viii):
-
(vii)
Experimenter: (image of a donkey + ‘lives in California’) ‘What is this?’
Participant: This is a donkey that lives in California.
Experimenter: (image of a donkey + ‘lives in Brazil’) ‘What is this?’
Participant: This is a donkey that lives in Brazil.
-
(viii)
Experimenter: (image of a donkey + ‘don’t know’) ‘What is this?’
Participant: This is a donkey that I don’t know where it lives.
While GN productions are generally reduced if there is no time pressure, in this case, since no more-optimal form was available, participants tended to produce resumptive pronouns even when no response deadline was imposed. Thus, speakers generally do the best they can, but given contextual and linguistic constraints, their best efforts can sometimes reliably lead to GN utterances.
Good-enough production in children
Children have less exposure to language than adults and slower lexical access [47]. Therefore, they are more prone to producing GN options than adults. Several apparently distinct types of child errors can be unified as GN productions, as described below [48].
Overextensions
Young children tend to overextend their early-learned words, applying them more broadly than is appropriate. For instance, a child may use dog to refer to cows, horses, or other animals. However, if a child who overextends the word dog is shown pictures of a dog and a cow and asked ‘Which is the dog?’, they reliably point to the dog and not the cow [49., 50., 51.]. This indicates that these children know that dog refers to dogs, or at least that dogs are better instances of the word dog than cows are. Why, then, do children ever use dog to label a cow? Presumably, it is because the better option (in this case, cow) has not yet been learned or is insufficiently accessible to the child at the moment of speaking. Since dog is highly accessible due to its high frequency, and since it is from the same general semantic domain (terms for animals), the word dog serves as a GN description for the intended message from the child’s perspective, given their limited vocabulary. Similarly, young children often rely on a deictic term (e.g., that) or simply point [52,53], which provide other GN solutions to the inaccessibility of a more conventional way to convey their intended message.
(Over)regularizations
We know that when preschool-aged English-speaking children are told that a novel creature is a wug, they reliably describe two novel creatures as wugs [54]. This requires them to: (i) implicitly recognize that the plural inflection is semantically appropriate, and (ii) access it from memory. Children’s incorrect uses of productive morphology are no different. That is, children often produce foots instead of feet or goed instead of went, applying regular inflections to irregular words. Suggestive evidence that overgeneralizations in morphology are due to GN production rather than a commitment to the incorrect forms comes from the fact that children vacillate between correct and incorrect forms for an extended period [55]. From a GN production perspective, whether a child produces an appropriate irregular form depends on whether it is accessible at the moment of speaking. This predicts that correct forms should be more accessible in the context of familiar phrases, since parts of a phrase can be expected to prime other parts [33]. Indeed, children are more likely to produce irregular forms correctly within frequent phrases (e.g., brush your teeth vs my tooths hurt) [56]. Also, in an elicitation task [57], while 5–6-year-old children produced overgeneralization errors and judged them to be acceptable roughly half the time (e.g., eated, ated), they judged the correct forms (e.g., ate) to be acceptable virtually all – 98% – of the time. This indicates that children have memory traces of the correct forms they have witnessed, as they reliably recognize them when they are provided, but children sometimes fail to access the conventional form at the moment of speaking or judging, in which case they generate or accept a GN form instead.
Regularization/simplification of grammatical constructions
When children are briefly exposed to a mini-artificial language in which a meaningless morpheme is included in 60% of utterances, they display a tendency to either regularly produce the morpheme or systematically omit it [58]. Adults, by contrast, are far more likely to match the probabilities witnessed in the input [58,59]. Initially this finding was framed as a demonstration that children displayed an appropriate tendency to ‘regularize’ language [58] or that children may have a ‘regularization bias’ [60]. Instead, however, children may simply produce GN utterances before they learn the social, semantic, and discourse factors that condition the variation (natural language variation is nearly always conditioned in some way or other) [61]. Evidence comes from a study that introduced children to a kind of variation that exists in many natural languages that children reliably learn. In particular, adults and 4–6-year-olds were exposed to a mini-artificial language with two determiners. One determiner was systematically applied to stereotypically female puppets and one inanimate puppet, while the other determiner was consistently applied to stereotypically male puppets and a different inanimate puppet [62]. After multiple rounds of exposure, the experimenter elicited descriptions of the familiar puppets and new gendered puppets. As expected, adults applied the novel determiners systematically and extended them to new gendered puppets in a way that was congruent with the puppets’ assigned genders. The children, by contrast, failed to learn the semantic conditioning, likely because the gender cue was not always available [63]. They instead tended to produce only one or the other novel determiner with the vast majority of the puppets, as they do when faced with random variation: From the children’s perspective, the input did vary randomly. However, since generations of German- and Spanish-speaking children successfully learn gender systems that reflect a combination of natural gender and lexical conditioning, it is clear that the children’s behavior was a temporary experimental artifact due to the limited exposure they had witnessed. We suggest that children’s tendency to regularize is an example of GN production insofar as accessing a single form repeatedly is easier than toggling back and forth between two forms that vary in a way that cannot (yet) be predicted. A key piece of evidence that children’s tendency to regularize involves GN production comes from judgment studies. When both options are offered to children, thereby eliminating accessibility demands, children display recognition and acceptance of both [58,62].
To summarize, the reason children tend to temporarily overextend the meaning of words, overgeneralize inflectional morphology, and simplify variation they perceive to be random, is the same: if children are unable to access a more-appropriate option, potentially because no other option is perceived to be more appropriate, they simply produce an accessible option that is good enough [48]. Children, like adults, work with the tools they have available in the discourse contexts in which they find themselves. The main difference between children and adults is that, due to lack of experience with language, children have fewer tools at their disposal and the tools they have are less easily accessible. Space prevents us from discussing adult language learners, but GN is clearly influential in this case as well [64., 65., 66.].
Good-enough production and comprehension
As indicated in Figure 2, we have portrayed GN production and comprehension as distinct from optimal production and comprehension and we have focused here on relatively clear cases of GN processing. At the same time, there is a growing recognition that speakers must access and combine grammatical constructions as well as words [33,37,38,48,67], and we endorse the idea that production and comprehension always involve an attempt to access an optimal combination of lexical and grammatical constructions to express a message or interpret someone else’s. By shining a light on GN processing, we intend to draw attention to the importance of accessibility in language processing generally [67]. GN productions occur when a competing and nonoptimal option is retrieved, resulting in a nonoptimal utterance. Parallel factors that influence the GN production and comprehension of constructions, whether lexical items or grammatical patterns, are specified in Figure 3.
To summarize, speakers (and signers) aim to produce an optimal combination of constructions to express their intended message in context, but they are constrained by their ability to access the required lexical and grammatical constructions. We appeal to optimal combinations of constructions rather than ‘ideal’ combinations to avoid assuming that there exists an ideal way to convey an intended message in context. The match between the constructions of the producer and those of the comprehender is always approximate rather than ideal [68], since linguistic representations are subject to individual variation [69]. Moreover, insofar as conventional linguistic resources are based on prior linguistic experiences, using familiar resources in novel contexts requires those resources to be extended, if only in minor ways [48,68]. In addition, optimal utterances are neither maximally explicit nor maximally precise, since language users tend to be efficient [17,70., 71., 72., 73., 74.]. In these ways, an intended message in context may never be perfectly or ideally matched by a combination of words and grammatical constructions. Instead, language users aim to access an optimal combination of constructions to express a message in context [48]. With this in mind, it is possible to construe all language production as GN production, insofar as our utterances only ever approximate our intended message. Again, we have focused here on clear cases, in which speakers of the same dialect would agree that that an utterance is nonoptimal.
Concluding remarks
GN productions occur when speakers (or signers) access and combine lexical and/or grammatical constructions that are in the intended ballpark semantically but are less than optimal for expressing the intended message. This offers a unified way to view a wide range of production phenomena ranging from errors (agreement errors, children’s overextensions) and vague word choices (thingy) to quasi-conventional language (resumptive pronouns in English). By recognizing the variety of phenomena that reflect GN language production, we aim to draw attention to the need to focus on factors known to influence accessibility in context, particularly those related to memory retrieval. Other outstanding questions come to the fore as well (see Outstanding questions).
Outstanding questions.
To what extent do speakers (and signers) adjust how closely the constructions they use approximate optimal choices? That is, GN production is a matter of degree (e.g., while the production of kettle is ideal, the thing that heats water is a better approximation than thingy is). Do speakers more closely approximate optimal options when they talk on the phone compared with when they interact face to face, for instance?
What role do other modalities, such as gesture, play in GN production? For example, if a speaker is unable to retrieve the word pumpernickel and says dark bread instead, are they more likely to produce a pointing gesture?
Can GN production involve full access of the form of a construction without full access of its function? This would seem to occur when we use a word or idiom without knowing precisely how it is conventionally used.
To what extend does the fact that nonoptimal productions tend to semantically approximate optimal productions follow from the nature of memory retrieval? That is, does the intention to access an optimal option predict that an option that is at least semantically related is likely to be accessed?
Is it reasonable to presume that optimal choices typically exist or does it make more sense to view all language production as only good enough, insofar as we always only approximate our intended messages?
The current review allows GN comprehension to be adaptive, at least some proportion of the time, because comprehenders need to infer the speaker’s intended message and to do this they cannot rely exclusively on what was uttered. They instead rely on linguistic signals in combination with the nonlinguistic context and common ground to arrive at an appropriate interpretation in context [25,74., 75., 76.]. Comprehenders may need to infer missing sounds, resolve lexical and syntactic ambiguities or vagueness, and derive appropriate inferences [4,19,25,72., 73., 74., 75., 76., 77., 78., 79., 80., 81., 82., 83., 84.] Thus, comprehenders’ understanding routinely differs from what was explicitly stated: the definition of GN comprehension.
The fact that language production is only good enough does not undermine the idea that languages are optimized for effective communication (e.g., [17,21,78,83]). A system cannot optimize for every possible utterance in every potential situation; instead, we rationally prioritize communication over perfection. It is useful for listeners to aim to interpret the speaker’s intended message rather than trying to extract the literal meaning of an utterance, particularly if speakers produce less-than-optimal options to convey their intended messages on a regular basis. Interlocutors typically work together to confirm and elaborate their intended messages [76,84]. Because both production and comprehension are flexible, people can communicate ideas reasonably successfully despite the challenges that arise from imperfect access from memory, limited linguistic resources, and noisy environments. In this way, both GN comprehension and GN production reflect the fact that communicators allocate resources rationally (e.g., [17,72,78,80., 81., 82., 83.]). That is, GN production and comprehension combine to support effective communication, at least most of the time.
Highlights.
The possibility of good-enough (GN) language production has rarely been raised until recently, although GN comprehension is widely recognized.
The production of overly vague words, agreement errors, and resumptive pronouns as well as children’s overextensions and regularizations all illustrate GN production.
GN production occurs when a language user accesses a nonoptimal albeit semantically relevant lexical or grammatical construction to express their intended message because a more-optimal construction is inaccessible at the moment of speaking (or signing).
Accessibility is increased by contextual cues, frequency, and priming and decreased by interference from competitors.
Communication is reasonably successful despite imperfect encoding or retrieval from memory because neither production nor comprehension is brittle.
The current work allows comprehension and production to be brought into closer alignment and encourages increased focus on accessibility from memory.
Acknowledgments
We are grateful to Kara Federmeier and two anonymous reviewers for comments on an earlier draft. We have been fortunate to work with excellent colleagues and collaborators on issues discussed here, including Vic Ferreira, Crystal Lee, Casey Lew-Williams, Jessica Schwab, and Benjamin Swets. We acknowledge support from National Science Foundation grant BCS-1650888 and National Institutes of Health/National Institute of Child Health and Child Development grant 1R01HD100516 awarded to F.F.
Footnotes
Declaration of interests
No interests are declared.
References
- 1.Ferreira F The misinterpretation of noncanonical sentences Cogn. Psychol, 47 (2003), pp. 164–203 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Ferreira F, Lowder MW Prediction, information structure, and good-enough language processing Psychol. Learn. Motiv, 65 (2016), pp. 217–247 [Google Scholar]
- 3.Tanenhaus MK, et al. Integration of visual and linguistic information in spoken language comprehension Science, 268 (1995), pp. 1632–1634 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.McClelland JL, et al. Parallel Distributed Processing Vol. 2, MIT Press; (1986), pp. 20–21 [Google Scholar]
- 5.MacDonald MC, et al. The lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution Psychol. Rev, 101 (1994), p. 676. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Garnsey SM, et al. The contributions of verb bias and plausibility to the comprehension of temporarily ambiguous sentences J. Mem. Lang, 37 (1997), pp. 58–93 [Google Scholar]
- 7.Erickson TD, Mattson ME From words to meaning: a semantic illusion J. Verbal Learn. Verbal Behav, 20 (1981), pp. 540–551 [Google Scholar]
- 8.Swets B, et al. Effects of conversational pressures on speech planning Discourse Process, 50 (2013), pp. 23–51 [Google Scholar]
- 9.Ferreira VS, Griffin ZM Phonological influences on lexical (mis) selection Psychol. Sci, 14 (2003), pp. 86–90 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Koranda M, et al. Word frequency can affect what you choose to say Cogn. Sci, 40 (2018), pp. 629–634 [Google Scholar]
- 11.Bock JK Toward a cognitive psychology of syntax: information processing contributions to sentence formulation Psychol. Rev, 89 (1982), pp. 1–47 [Google Scholar]
- 12.Gibson E, Fedorenko E The need for quantitative methods in syntax and semantics research Lang. Cogn. Process, 28 (2013), pp. 88–124 [Google Scholar]
- 13.Robenalt C, Goldberg AE Judgment evidence for statistical preemption Cogn. Linguist, 26 (2015), pp. 467–503 [Google Scholar]
- 14.Tachihara K, Goldberg AE Reduced competition effects and noisier representations in a second language Lang. Learn, 70 (2020), pp. 219–265 [Google Scholar]
- 15.Gibson E, et al. Don’t underestimate the benefits of being misunderstood Psychol. Sci, 28 (2017), pp. 703–712 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Mollica F, et al. Composition is the core driver of the language-selective network Neurobiol. Lang, 1 (2020), pp. 104–134 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Gibson E, et al. Rational integration of noisy evidence and prior semantic expectations in sentence interpretation Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A, 110 (2013), pp. 8051–8056 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Cutter MG, et al. Online representations of non-canonical sentences are more than good-enough Quart. J. Exp. Psychol, 75 (2022), pp. 30–42 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Russell AW, Schober MF How beliefs about a partner’s goals affect referring in goal-discrepant conversations Discourse Process, 27 (1999), pp. 1–33 [Google Scholar]
- 20.Galantucci B, Roberts G Do we notice when communication goes awry? An investigation of people’s sensitivity to coherence in spontaneous conversation PLoS One, 9 (2014), Article e103182. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Levy R A noisy-channel model of human sentence comprehension under uncertain input Proceedings of the 2008 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, Association for Computational Linguistics (2008), pp. 234–243 [Google Scholar]
- 22.Baayen RH, et al. Frequency in lexical processing Aphasiology, 30 (2016), pp. 1174–1220 [Google Scholar]
- 23.Christianson K, Ferreira F Conceptual accessibility and sentence production in a free word order language (Odawa) Cognition, 98 (2005), pp. 105–135 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Brown-Schmidt S Partner-specific interpretation of maintained referential precedents during interactive dialog J. Mem. Lang, 61 (2009), pp. 171–190 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Christiansen MH, Chater N The now-or-never bottleneck: a fundamental constraint on language Behav. Brain Sci, 39 (2016), Article e62. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Goldberg AE, Lee C Accessibility and historical change: an emergent cluster led uncles and aunts to become aunts and uncles Front. Psychol, 12 (2021), pp. 1418–1437 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Tachihara K, Goldberg AE Cognitive accessibility predicts word order of couples’ names in English and Japanese Cogn. Linguist, 31 (2020), pp. 231–249 [Google Scholar]
- 28.Jacobs CL, et al. Phrase frequency effects in free recall: evidence for redintegration J. Mem. Lang, 97 (2017), pp. 1–16 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Freeman MR, et al. First-language influence on second language speech perception depends on task demands Lang. Speech (2021) Published online January 6, 2021 10.1177/0023830920983368 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Bader M, Meng M The misinterpretation of noncanonical sentences revisited J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn, 44 (2018), p. 1286. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Brashier NM, et al. An initial accuracy focus prevents illusory truth Cognition, 194 (2020), Article 104054. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Davies M The 385+ million word Corpus of Contemporary American English (1990–2008+): design, architecture, and linguistic insights Int. J. Corpus Linguist, 14 (2009), pp. 159–190 [Google Scholar]
- 33.Kapatsinski V Changing Minds Changing Tools: From Learning Theory to Language Acquisition to Language Change MIT Press; (2018) [Google Scholar]
- 34.Harmon Z, Kapatsinski V Putting old tools to novel uses: the role of form accessibility in semantic extension Cogn. Psychol, 98 (2017), pp. 22–44 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Hartsuiker RJ, Barkhuysen PN Language production and working memory: the case of subject–verb agreement Lang. Cogn. Process, 21 (2006), pp. 181–204 [Google Scholar]
- 36.Laurinavichyute A, von der Malsburg T Semantic attraction in sentence processing Cogn. Sci, 46 (2022), p. e13086 Published online February 5, 2020 10.31234/osf.io/hk9nc [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Smith G, et al. A self-organizing approach to subject–verb number agreement Cogn. Sci, 42 (2018), pp. 1043–1074 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Konieczny L, et al. An activation-based model of agreement errors in production and comprehension Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Cognitive Science Society (2014), pp. 276–281 [Google Scholar]
- 39.Slevc LR, Martin R Syntactic agreement attraction reflects working memory processes J. Cogn. Psychol, 28 (2016), pp. 773–790 [Google Scholar]
- 40.Hwang H, Kaiser E Accessibility effects on production vary cross-linguistically: evidence from English and Korean J. Mem. Lang, 84 (2015), pp. 190–204 [Google Scholar]
- 41.Chaves RP Unbounded Dependency Constructions: Theoretical and Experimental Perspectives Vol. 10, Oxford University Press; (2021) [Google Scholar]
- 42.Sprouse J, Hornstein N (Eds.), Experimental Syntax and Island Effects, Cambridge University Press; (2013) [Google Scholar]
- 43.Brooks D The New York Times 18 March (2016), p. 18
- 44.Ackerman L, et al. Resumptive pronouns can ameliorate island extractions Linguist. Inq, 49 (2018), pp. 847–859 [Google Scholar]
- 45.Morgan AM, et al. Shared syntax between comprehension and production: multi-paradigm evidence that resumptive pronouns hinder comprehension Cognition, 205 (2020), Article 104417. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Ferreira F, Swets B The production and comprehension of resumptive pronouns in relative clause “island” contexts Cutler A (Ed.), Twenty-First Century Psycholinguistics: Four Cornerstones, Routledge; (2005), pp. 263–278 [Google Scholar]
- 47.D’Amico S, et al. Picture naming and lexical access in Italian children and adults J. Cogn. Dev, 2 (2001), pp. 71–105 [Google Scholar]
- 48.Goldberg AE Explain Me This: Creativity, Competition, and the Partial Productivity of Constructions Princeton University Press; (2019) [Google Scholar]
- 49.Kuczaj SA Young children’s overextensions of object words in comprehension and/or production: support for a prototype theory of early object word meaning First Lang, 3 (1982), pp. 93–105 [Google Scholar]
- 50.Naigles L, Gelman SA Overextensions in production and comprehension, revisited: a study of dog, cat, and cow J. Child Lang, 22 (1995), pp. 19–46 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.P. RF Junior, Xu Y Children’s overextension as communication by multimodal chaining CogSci 2019, Cognitive Science Society; (2019), pp. 295–301 [Google Scholar]
- 52.Kidd E, Holler J Children’s use of gesture to resolve lexical ambiguity Dev. Sci, 12 (2009), pp. 903–913 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Köymen B, et al. Preschoolers refer to direct and indirect evidence in their collaborative reasoning J. Exp. Child Psychol, 193 (2020), Article 104806. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Berko J The child’s learning of English morphology WORD, 14 (1958), pp. 150–177 [Google Scholar]
- 55.Plunkett K, Marchman V U-shaped learning and frequency effects in a multi-layered perception: implications for child language acquisition Cognition, 38 (1991), pp. 43–102 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Arnon I, Clark EV Why brush your teeth is better than teeth - children’s word production is facilitated in familiar sentence-frames Lang. Learn. Dev, 7 (2011), pp. 107–129 [Google Scholar]
- 57.Kuczaj SA Why do children fail to overgeneralize the progressive inflection? J. Child Lang, 5 (1978), pp. 167–171 [Google Scholar]
- 58.Hudson Kam CL, Newport EL Regularizing unpredictable variation: the roles of adult and child learners in language formation and change Lang. Learn. Dev, 1 (2005), pp. 151–195 [Google Scholar]
- 59.Kam CLH, Newport EL Getting it right by getting it wrong: when learners change languages Cogn. Psychol, 59 (2009), pp. 30–66 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Perfors A When do memory limitations lead to regularization? An experimental and computational investigation J. Mem. Lang, 67 (2012), pp. 486–506 [Google Scholar]
- 61.Trudgill P Sociolinguistic Typology: Social Determinants of Linguistic Complexity Oxford University Press; (2011) [Google Scholar]
- 62.Schwab J, et al. When regularization gets it wrong: children over-simplify language input only in production J. Child. Lang, 45 (2018), pp. 1054–1072 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.Brown H, et al. Semantic cues in language learning: an artificial language study with adult and child learners Lang. Cogn. Neurosci (2021) Published online November 10, 2021 10.1080/23273798.2021.1995612 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 64.Guo R, Ellis NC Language usage and second language morphosyntax: effects of availability, reliability, and formulaicity Front. Psychol, 12 (2021), Article 582259. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Sarkis JT, Montag JL The effect of lexical accessibility on Spanish-English intra-sentential codeswitching Mem. Cogn, 49 (2021), pp. 163–180 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 66.Mickan A, et al. Electrophysiological evidence for cross-language interference in foreign-language attrition Neuropsychologia, 155 (2021), Article 107795. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67.MacDonald MC How language production shapes language form and comprehension Front. Psychol, 4 (2013), p. 226. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.Casasanto D, Lupyan G All concepts are ad hoc concepts Margolis E, Laurence S (Eds.), The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts, MIT Press; (2015), pp. 543–566 [Google Scholar]
- 69.Dąbrowska E Experience, aptitude, and individual differences in linguistic attainment: a comparison of native and nonnative speakers Lang. Learn, 69 (2019), pp. 72–100 [Google Scholar]
- 70.Gibson E, et al. How efficiency shapes human language Trends Cogn. Sci, 23 (2019), pp. 389–407 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71.Rubio-Fernandez P, et al. Speakers and listeners exploit word order for communicative efficiency: a cross-linguistic investigation J. Exp. Psychol. Gen, 150 (2021), p. 583. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72.Hawkins RD, et al. Generalizing meanings from partners to populations: hierarchical inference supports convention formation on networks arXiv (2020) Published online February 4, 2020 https://arxiv.org/abs/2002.01510 [Google Scholar]
- 73.Schuster S, Degen J Speaker-specific adaptation to variable use of uncertainty expressions CogSci 2019, Cognitive Science Society; (2019), pp. 2769–2775 [Google Scholar]
- 74.Xu Y, et al. Numeral systems across languages support efficient communication: from approximate numerosity to recursion Open Mind, 4 (2020), pp. 57–70 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 75.Rodd JM Settling into semantic space: an ambiguity-focused account of word-meaning access Perspect. Psychol. Sci, 15 (2020), pp. 411–427 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 76.Clark HH Common ground The International Encyclopedia of Linguistic Anthropology, John Wiley & Sons; (2020), pp. 1–5 [Google Scholar]
- 77.Samuel AG Does lexical information influence the perceptual restoration of phonemes? J. Exp. Psychol. Gen, 125 (1996), p. 28 [Google Scholar]
- 78.Ryskin RA, et al. Agreement errors are predicted by rational inference in sentence processing PsyArXiv (2021) Published online October 9, 2021 10.31234/osf.io/uaxsq [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 79.Bohn M, Frank MC The pervasive role of pragmatics in early language Annu. Rev. Dev. Psychol, 1 (2019), pp. 223–249 [Google Scholar]
- 80.Yurovsky D, et al. Preschoolers flexibly adapt to linguistic input in a noisy channel Psychol. Sci, 28 (2017), pp. 132–140 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 81.Sedivy JC Invoking discourse-based contrast sets and resolving syntactic ambiguities J. Mem. Lang, 46 (2002), pp. 341–370 [Google Scholar]
- 82.Altarriba J, Gianico JL Lexical ambiguity resolution across languages: a theorical and empirical review Exp. Psychol, 50 (2003), pp. 159–170 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 83.Griffiths TL, et al. Rational use of cognitive resources: levels of analysis between the computational and the algorithmic Top. Cogn. Sci, 7 (2015), pp. 217–229 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 84.Gernsbacher MA, Givón T (Eds.), Coherence in Spontaneous Text, Vol. 31, John Benjamins; (1995) [Google Scholar]
- 85.Park H, Reder LM Moses illusion Cognitive Illusions, Psychology Press; (2012), pp. 287–304 [Google Scholar]
- 86.Barton SB, Sanford AJ A case study of anomaly detection: shallow semantic processing and cohesion establishment Mem. Cogn, 21 (1993), pp. 477–487 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 87.Dick F, et al. Language deficits, localization, and grammar: evidence for a distributive model of language breakdown in aphasic patients and neurologically intact individuals Psychol. Rev, 108 (2001), p. 759. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 88.Gibson E, Thomas J Memory limitations and structural forgetting: the perception of complex ungrammatical sentences as grammatical Lang. Cogn. Process, 14 (1999), pp. 225–248 [Google Scholar]
- 89.Futrell R, et al. Lossy-context surprisal: an information-theoretic model of memory effects in sentence processing Cogn. Sci, 44 (2020), Article el2814. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 90.Fujita H, Cunnings I Reanalysis and lingering misinterpretation of linguistic dependencies in native and nonnative sentence comprehension J. Mem. Lang, 115 (2020), Article 104154 [Google Scholar]
- 91.Häussler J, Bader M An interference account of the missing-VP effect Front. Psychol, 6 (2015), p. 766. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 92.Christianson K, et al. Thematic roles assigned along the garden path linger Cogn. Psychol, 42 (2001), pp. 368–407 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 93.Tabor W, et al. Effects of merely local syntactic coherence on sentence processing J. Mem. Lang, 50 (2004), pp. 355–370 [Google Scholar]
- 94.Duffy SA, et al. Semantic facilitation of lexical access during sentence processing J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn, 15 (1989), pp. 791–801 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]