Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2022 Aug 22.
Published in final edited form as: Psychol Bull. 2021 Nov;147(11):1159–1183. doi: 10.1037/bul0000327

Expertise in Emotion: A Scoping Review and Unifying Framework for Individual Differences in the Mental Representation of Emotional Experience

Katie Hoemann 1, Catie Nielson 2, Ashley Yuen 3, J W Gurera 2, Karen S Quigley 2,4, Lisa Feldman Barrett 2,5,6
PMCID: PMC9393910  NIHMSID: NIHMS1818540  PMID: 35238584

Abstract

Expertise refers to outstanding skill or ability in a particular domain. In the domain of emotion, expertise refers to the observation that some people are better at a range of competencies related to understanding and experiencing emotions, and these competencies may help them lead healthier lives. These individual differences are represented by multiple constructs including emotional awareness, emotional clarity, emotional complexity, emotional granularity, and emotional intelligence. These constructs derive from different theoretical perspectives, highlight different competencies, and are operationalized and measured in different ways. The full set of relationships between these constructs has not yet been considered, hindering scientific progress and the translation of findings to aid mental and physical well-being. In this article, we use a scoping review procedure to integrate these constructs within a shared conceptual space. Scoping reviews provide a principled means of synthesizing large and diverse literature in a transparent fashion, enabling the identification of similarities as well as gaps and inconsistencies across constructs. Using domain-general accounts of expertise as a guide, we build a unifying framework for expertise in emotion and apply this to constructs that describe how people understand and experience their own emotions. Our approach offers opportunities to identify potential mechanisms of expertise in emotion, encouraging future research on those mechanisms and on educational or clinical interventions.

Keywords: alexithymia, emotional awareness, emotional creativity, emotional granularity, emotional intelligence


Remember the old story about the blind men and the elephant? Each touching a different part of an elephant to learn what it is like, they proclaim it to have different properties. The blind men analogy illustrates how important constructs in psychology are rediscovered, defined in slightly different ways, and labeled with slightly different words. The domain of emotion has an example of one of these situations, represented by constructs including emotional awareness, emotional clarity, emotional complexity, emotional granularity, and emotional intelligence. These constructs share the observation that some people are better than others at a range of competencies related to understanding and experiencing emotions, and these competencies may help them lead healthier lives. There are differences in how these constructs are operationalized and measured, and in the theoretical perspectives that inform them. There have been calls to directly compare and integrate these constructs and their measures (e.g., Gohm & Clore, 2000; Grossmann et al., 2016; Grühn et al., 2013; Ivcevic et al., 2007; Joseph & Newman, 2010; Kang & Shaver, 2004; Kashdan et al., 2015; Lindquist & Barrett, 2008; Lumley et al., 2005; Maroti et al., 2018; Schimmack et al., 2000). In response, we collected them under the term “expertise” for its reference to outstanding skill or ability in a particular domain (Ericsson et al., 2018). Our goal is to craft a unifying framework to evaluate findings, offering an opportunity to accumulate knowledge with clear ties to mental and physical well-being.

To create this framework, we use domain-general accounts of expertise to deductively articulate a set of core features. We then use this framework to structure the findings from a scoping review of constructs that describe individual differences in emotional competencies. Scoping reviews provide a principled means of synthesizing large and diverse literatures in a transparent fashion, allowing scientists to identify similarities as well as gaps and inconsistencies across constructs (Pham et al., 2014). We use the results of our scoping review to evaluate an integrative framework for structuring future work, with implications for the conceptual model that may best guide that work. This approach, we suggest, organizes scientific knowledge, and reveals potential mechanisms to motivate programs of research and intervention. As proof of concept, we focus this article on the mental representation of one’s own emotional experience. Future work can expand this framework to include, for example, constructs related to the representation of others’ emotional experiences, or to the regulation of emotion.

We begin this article by briefly reviewing the history of individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience, illustrating the proliferation of constructs in this domain and its consequences for scientific research and clinical practice. Next, we introduce the construct of expertise and the features of our unifying framework. In the Method section, we provide details on the scoping review procedure that we used to integrate included constructs (noted in italics throughout) within a shared conceptual space. In the Results section, we illustrate this conceptual space using a series of networks that allow us to visualize and describe the relationships between constructs. We then remap the included constructs onto a common expertise framework, through this process interrogating the theoretical perspectives associated with different constructs, as well as the relationship between construct and measurement. Finally, in the Discussion, we consider the conceptual and methodological advances suggested by our unifying framework, including their potential impacts on future work.

Individual Differences in the Mental Representation of Emotional Experience

There is a growing number of constructs that describe how people understand and experience their own emotions. A brief history of this domain provides a sense of its scope and complexity. Interest in individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience is found within the psychoanalytic tradition around the beginning of the 20th century (e.g., Freud, 1891, 1895). With few exceptions (e.g., Meltzoff & Litwin, 1956; Saul, 1947; Wessman & Ricks, 1966), early scientific study was focused on clinical diagnosis and treatment (e.g., Freedman & Sweet, 1954; Henry & Shlien, 1958; Ruesch, 1948).1 This research often centered on patients with psychosomatic disorders (e.g., Alexander, 1950; MacLean, 1949; Marty & de M’Uzan, 1963), leading to the formalization of the construct of alexithymia in the 1970s (e.g., Nemiah, 1970; Nemiah et al., 1976; Sifneos, 1972). (Construct definitions can be found in Table 2; for more in-depth construct summaries, see Supplemental Materials.)

Table 2.

Summary of Constructs for the Mental Representation of Emotional Experience

Construct Definition Common measure(s) Measure type Dominant theoretical perspective(s)a Publications reviewedb Publications included Example publication(s)
Alexithymiaf The inability to identify, describe, and introspect about one’s emotional experiences (Aaron et al., 2018); the inability to mentally represent one’s emotional experiences (Lane et al., 2015) Toronto Alexithymia Scale, 20-item version (TAS-20; Bagby et al., 1994)c Global self-report Psychoanalytic (historical) 164 43 Nemiah and Sifneos (1970); Taylor et al. (1985)
Awareness The extent to which one understands, describes, and attends to one’s emotional experiences (Mankus et al., 2016) Levels of Emotional Awareness Scale (LEAS; Lane et al., 1990); Trait Meta-Mood Scales (TMMS) for Clarity, Attention (Salovey et al., 1995) Task performance; Global self-report Cognitive-developmental; Appraisal 148 13 Lane and Schwartz (1987); Thompson et al. (2009)
Clarity The extent to which one unambiguously identifies, labels, and describes one’s own emotional experiences (Boden & Thompson, 2017) TMMS, Clarity subscale (Salovey et al., 1995); TAS-20, Difficulty Identifying Feelings subscale (TAS-20, DIF; Bagby et al., 1994) Global self-report Appraisal 148 12 Salovey et al. (1995); Boden and Berenbaum (2011)
Competenceg The extent to which one identifies, expresses, understands, regulates, and uses one’s own emotions and those of others (Brasseur et al., 2013) to facilitate appropriate actions (Izard, 2009) Emotional Competence Inventory (ECI; Boyatzis et al., 2000); Profile of Emotional Competence (PEC; Brasseur et al., 2013)d Multirater assessment; Global self-report Basic emotion; Appraisal (causal) 44 5 Boyatzis et al. (2000); Brasseur et al.(2013)
Complexity The extent to which one simultaneously experiences different(ly valenced) emotions, and/or differentiates between a varied and nuanced set of emotions (Grühn et al., 2013) Range and Differentiation of Emotional Experiences Scale (RDEES; Kang & Shaver, 2004); Empirically derived indices from emotion intensity ratings Global self-report; Experience samplinge Cognitive-developmental; Appraisal 126 18 Kang and Shaver (2004); Grühn et al. (2013)
Creativity The ability to produce emotional responses that are novel, authentic, and effective, as well as one’s preparedness to use this ability (Averill, 1999) Emotional Creativity Inventory (Averill, 1999); Emotional Consequences, Emotional Triads (Averill & Thomas-Knowles, 1991) Global self-report; Task performance Constructionist (social) 33 6 Averill and Thomas-Knowles (1991); Averill (1999)
Diversityh The variety and relative abundance of the emotions one experiences (Quoidbach et al., 2014); the breadth of emotions one experiences (Kang & Shaver, 2004) Empirically derived index across emotion frequency ratings; RDEES, Range subscale (Kang & Shaver, 2004) Experience samplinge; Global self-report Appraisal; Constructionist (psychological) 53 4 Quoidbach et al. (2014); Sommers (1981)
Flexibility The ability to adapt one’s emotional experiences in a situation-specific manner (Fu et al., 2018) Changes in emotion intensity ratings after mood induction; Emotional Flexibility Scale (Fu et al., 2018) Mood induction; Global self-report Appraisal 54 4 Waugh et al. (2011); Zhu and Bonanno (2017)
Granularityi The ability to represent one’s emotional experience in a nuanced and specific manner, often (but not always) marked through language (Lee et al., 2017; Tugade et al., 2004) Within-person correlations (e.g., intraclass correlations) across emotion intensity ratings; RDEES, Differentiation subscale (Kang & Shaver, 2004) Experience samplinge; Global self-report Constructionist 153 24 Barrett (2017a); Barrett et al. (2001); Tugade et al. (2004)
Intelligencej The ability to perceive and express emotion, understand and reason with emotion, and regulate emotion in the self and others (Mayer et al., 2000) Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT; Mayer et al., 2002)c Task performance Basic emotion; Appraisal (causal) 353 44 Mayer and Salovey (1997); Bar-On (1997); Siegling et al. (2015)
a

Without modifiers, names of theoretical perspectives are inclusive of all variants (e.g., “appraisal” includes “descriptive” and “causal” perspectives; “constructionist” includes “psychological,” “neural,” “developmental,” etc.). Research on alexithymia is historically derived from the psychoanalytic tradition, with contemporary accounts departing from this theoretical perspective.

b

Number of publications identified through database searching and/or key reviews.

c

Other common measures are discussed in the Supplemental Materials.

d

Also assessed as intelligence.

e

Experience sampling measures are analyzed to produce behavioral indices.

f

Includes agnosia.

g

Includes utilization.

h

Includes range.

i

Includes differentiation.

j

Includes quotient.

In the 1980s and 1990s, an explosion of emotion-related research produced constructs such as emotional intelligence (e.g., Goleman, 1995; Salovey & Mayer, 1990), emotional awareness (Lane et al., 1990; Lane & Schwartz, 1987), emotional complexity (e.g., Larsen & Cutler, 1996; Tobacyk, 1980), emotional creativity (Averill & Thomas-Knowles, 1991), emotional literacy (e.g., Steiner, 1984), and emotional fitness (Cooper & Sawaf, 1997). Emotional intelligence, especially, became a hotspot of activity in both the academy (e.g., Bar-On, 1997; Mayer & Salovey, 1997; Schutte et al., 1998) and industry (e.g., Cooper & Sawaf, 1997; Grandey, 2000; Law et al., 2004). Constructs continued to proliferate, such as emotion differentiation (Barrett et al., 2001) and its synonym emotional granularity (Tugade et al., 2004), emotional clarity (e.g., Palmieri et al., 2009), and emotional flexibility (Waugh et al., 2011). Today, a quick Internet search turns up additional constructs, such as emotional agility (David, 2016), emodiversity (Quoidbach et al., 2014), and affective agnosia (Lane et al., 2015). To make matters more complex, most constructs are associated with multiple measures (e.g., there are nine measures for alexithymia in adults reviewed in Bermond et al., 2015), and some measures are used to assess more than one construct. For example, the Toronto Alexithymia Scale (TAS; e.g., Bagby et al., 1994) has been used as an index of emotional clarity (e.g., Erbas et al., 2018) and the Levels of Emotional Awareness Scale (LEAS; Lane et al., 1990) has been used as a measure of alexithymia (e.g., Lane et al., 1996).

When a phenomenon is important in psychological science, it is discovered again and again, each time with a different name and emphasizing different features. There are many reasons for this state of affairs (e.g., “Psychologists treat other peoples’ theories like toothbrushes—no self-respecting person wants to use anyone else’s.”; Mischel, 2008). Nonetheless, this construct proliferation comes with a cost: It slows the accumulation of knowledge, causes problems with reproducibility, and obscures common mechanisms. Construct proliferation also limits the applied potential of research in this domain. Each construct purports to—and often does—predict indicators of mental and physical health, among other real-world outcomes. This overlap is problematic if scientists and clinicians do not understand why a construct confers protection. For example, alexithymia is (positively) associated with mental health disorders, substance abuse and eating disorders, chronic pain and functional gastrointestinal disorders, and coronary heart disease (see Bermond et al., 2015; Lumley et al., 2007; Taylor, 2000, for reviews). However, emotional intelligence is also (negatively) associated with depression and anxiety symptoms, substance abuse, and physical health complaints (see Bar-On, 2000; Mayer et al., 2008; Salovey et al., 2002; Zeidner et al., 2012, for reviews).

Many constructs for how people understand and experience their own emotions have in common the idea that mentally representing emotional experience is an ability or skill that can be learned, practiced, and honed, making these constructs particularly compelling targets for research and intervention. Improvement in ability over time provides insight into developmental pathways and means by which skills can be harnessed for well-being. Viewing the mental representation of emotional experience as an ability or skill also connects these constructs with the concept of expertise. In the next section, we expand upon this connection and use it to motivate our unifying framework.

What Is Expertise?

Expertise has previously been mentioned with regard to emotion-related abilities (e.g., Mayer et al., 2001; McBrien et al., 2020; Pistoia et al., 2018; von Salisch, 2001), but has not been used as a framework for systematic investigation and synthesis. Expertise has several defining characteristics that are relevant to the domain of emotion, as it is: (a) supported by extensive and specific domain knowledge, (b) characterized by enhanced information-processing capacities, (c) demonstrated through reliable task performance, and (d) developed through awareness and deliberate practice (e.g., Bédard & Chi, 1992; Steels, 1990; Sternberg, 1998; Ullén et al., 2016). To create a framework that can be flexibly applied to constructs for individual differences in emotional competencies, we distilled these defining characteristics into a set of 12 core features (Table 1). We identified these features deductively, based on prior literature on expertise and findings in domain-general psychological science. We briefly review each of these features (noted in bold throughout), use it to describe a quality of experts in contrast to novices, and pose a hypothesis about its role in the domain of emotion.

Table 1.

Features of Expertise

Feature Description
Structure of knowledge Differentiated, efficiently organized concepts
Breadth of knowledge Diverse, elaborated concepts
Type of knowledge Specialized, domain-relevant concepts
Mental representation Sophisticated, relational processing
Verbal representation Specific labeling, description
Ability or skill Reliable, task-based performance
Adaptive responses Effective actions, outcomes
Context-specificity Situation-dependent flexibility
Awareness Conscious access
Attention Reflective monitoring
Deliberate practice Intentional improvement, expansion
Prediction Proactive planning, adjustment

Extensive and Specific Domain Knowledge

Expertise requires a broad and efficiently structured body of specialized domain knowledge (Bédard & Chi, 1992). This knowledge includes both explicit, declarative knowledge of domain-relevant concepts, as well as implicit, functional knowledge of how those concepts might be deployed (Sternberg, 1998; Sternberg et al., 1995; see also the distinction between deep and surface knowledge by Steels, 1990). In other words, there are types of knowledge that experts must possess. Experts’ concepts are organized into highly interconnected networks, as opposed to novices who have fewer and weaker links between concepts (Bédard & Chi, 1992; Sternberg, 1998). Experts’ concepts are also more specific and lead to a subordinate-level shift in categorization (e.g., Bukach et al., 2006). For novices, categorization proceeds according to boundaries established as “cognitively basic” in a given cultural context (Rosch et al., 1976). In contrast, experts are able to differentiate between more specific categories (Tanaka & Taylor, 1991; see also Schyns, 1991; Schyns et al., 1998). While novices might see only yellow versus green, color experts such as painters might distinguish lime, olive, and chartreuse. This differentiation extends to how experts verbally represent their experience by using language to label specific categories or describe specific properties (Tanaka & Taylor, 1991; Tversky & Hemenway, 1984).

In the domain of emotion, these features suggest that experts possess concepts for emotion that are varied and precise. We hypothesize that these concepts build upon functional knowledge of the domain: what emotions can and typically mean, when they are helpful or appropriate, how to smoothly navigate transitions, etc. We further hypothesize that experts can easily name the experiences that correspond with these concepts, going beyond conventional levels of description (e.g., “angry”) to pinpoint their feelings more exactly (e.g., “livid,” “resentful,” “amped up”).

Enhanced Information-Processing Capacities

Experts also differ from novices in how they implement domain-relevant knowledge (Steels, 1990), and exhibit enhanced information-processing capacities (Bédard & Chi, 1992; Sternberg, 1998; Ullén et al., 2016). Whereas novices rely on surface-level perceptual features to make decisions and predictions, experts harness abstract, functional features to optimally address task demands (Bédard & Chi, 1992; Schyns et al., 1998). For example, a novice may believe olive and chartreuse work equally well for painting a wall “green,” whereas an expert would consider the impacts of undertone and lighting on perceived color—and may ultimately suggest emerald to create a balanced calm (e.g., Goldstone, 1995). Experts can differentiate between categories that seem equivalent to novices (e.g., olive and chartreuse) because they employ more precise features to encode similarities and contrasts (e.g., breaking down “color” into the properties of hue, saturation, and brightness; Burns & Shepp, 1988; Goldstone, 1994; see also Schyns et al., 1998; Tanaka, 1998; Williams et al., 1998). In this way, experts easily construct sophisticated mental representations, and use nonobvious properties (e.g., the mood associated with a color) to determine which action is maximally effective at achieving a given goal (Sternberg, 1998). This type of holistic and relational processing is a hallmark of expertise and impacts how new knowledge is acquired. While novices learn by rote, experts can efficiently generalize to new exemplars using abstract, functional similarities (Bukach et al., 2006).

In the domain of emotion, “mental representation” suggests, at its most fundamental level, that individuals can process information from the body (e.g., visceral sense data) and/or from the world (e.g., vocal tones of others) as features of emotional experience. We hypothesize that experts in emotion build on this ability by identifying the psychological features that are most functionally salient and disregarding perceptual similarities or contrasts that are functionally irrelevant (e.g., by understanding that heart palpitations and fatigue can both signal anxiety in the context of an upcoming deadline).

Reliable Task Performance

Expertise is not only a matter of having domain-relevant knowledge and enhanced information-processing capacities; these must also be demonstrated through measurable behavioral outcomes. Experts are distinguished from nonexperts on the basis of ability or skill in task performance that is reliable and replicable (Ericsson & Lehmann, 1996; Ericsson & Ward, 2007). For example, an expert painter produces works of art that consistently exemplify color theory; an expert interior designer is highly recommended by satisfied customers. This suggests that individual differences in expertise should be derived from a series of adaptive responses, observed over time or across contexts, and judged according to their context-specific efficacy (Ericsson & Lehmann, 1996; Ericsson & Smith, 1991). In contrast to novices, experts flexibly adapt their actions to the situation at hand. Multiple methods can be used to assess expertise depending on the ability or skill in question. Different aspects of color expertise might be demonstrated via perceptual discrimination, verbal fluency, or practical application (e.g., interior design that leads to shorter recovery time, reduced pain medication, and increased satisfaction in hospital patients; Rubin et al., 1998).

In the domain of emotion, these features suggest that expertise is best assessed using tasks that require individuals to “perform” mental representation of emotional experience—in other words, to document or communicate their thoughts and feelings. We hypothesize that these tasks vary in the amount of constraint placed on the response (e.g., endorsing a set of emotion adjectives vs. freely describing an emotional episode), but in principle should be unconstrained enough to allow for variation across contexts (i.e., flexibility). We further hypothesize that these tasks should be repeated to assess patterns of behavior over time (i.e., reliability).

Awareness and Deliberate Practice

Scientists debate the extent to which expertise in a particular domain is due to trait-level dispositions or genetic factors (e.g., Ericsson, 2014; Plomin et al., 2014a, 2014b). There is overall consensus, however, that substantial training is critical to developing expertise and that expertise can be enhanced through deliberate practice (Ullén et al., 2016). Deliberate practice involves both improving existing skills and expanding the set and scope of skills. This is done by updating knowledge, identifying alternative solutions, and encountering novel experiences (Ericsson, 2006; Ericsson & Charness, 1994). An expert painter might seek out opportunities to work with new colors, subject matter, or materials, and might spend time learning about pigments and application techniques to create particular impressions (Ford, 2016; Protter, 1997). These processes require awareness and sustained attention (Ericsson, 2007; Ullén et al., 2016). Experts engage in reflective and careful monitoring of their domain understanding and abilities (Sternberg, 1998). This regular evaluation leads to more effective resource allocation (Sternberg, 1984; Sternberg & Kagan, 1986), such that experts are better at determining what information to attend to and how to prepare for upcoming demands. That is, experts are better at predicting what will happen next and planning their actions accordingly, thereby minimizing error and meeting situation-specific needs more efficiently.

In the domain of emotion, these features suggest that experts continue to hone their ability to mentally represent emotional experiences. We hypothesize that they do so by actively attending to their experiences of emotion, and by receiving repetitive, unambiguous feedback from social others (Laland, 2017). By “practicing” emotion in these ways, we hypothesize that experts become better equipped for future events and challenges.

The features in Table 1, when taken together, describe expertise as skilled performance within a given domain and relative to situation-specific needs. Experts must possess the “basic” domain knowledge shared by other culture members (e.g., a color expert must learn primary and secondary color categories, their prototypical hues, boundaries, and names) as well as specialized knowledge shared by other domain experts (e.g., the difference between hue, saturation, and brightness). Experts can also flexibly deploy this knowledge, depending on context-driven goals or functions: For example, an expert uses different language when describing the color of a toy apple to an American toddler (“red”) than when suggesting a pigment for painting a stormy night sky (“Pantone 7545c”). These become important points as we return to the discussion of expertise in the domain of emotion and use the above features to build an organizational framework. To inform this process, we conducted a scoping review of individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience, which we describe next.

Method

Scoping Review Overview

Scoping reviews are a rigorous and transparent process for surveying the literature on broad topics (Pham et al., 2014) that aim to map key constructs and sources and types of data (Mays et al., 2001), as well as to depict the interrelations among these constructs. As such, scoping reviews can be particularly useful when the topic is complex or heterogeneous because they can identify gaps and assess the value of undertaking further research (Daudt et al., 2013). The most common scoping review procedure is the iterative process proposed by Arksey and O’Malley (2005), which involves identifying the research question; identifying relevant studies; selecting studies; charting the data; and collating, summarizing, and reporting the results.

In the present article, we followed this approach to synthesizing research. After formulating our research question, we (a) identified relevant constructs; (b) selected relevant publications; (c) extracted and (d) organized the data; and (e) summarized, illustrated, and synthesized the results. Throughout this process, we were guided by the materials from the Preferred Reporting Items for Systematic Reviews and Meta-Analyses (PRISMA) workgroup (Liberati et al., 2009; Moher et al., 2009). We also looked to qualitative synthesis methods to inform our use of expertise as an a priori framework for situating and remapping the included constructs. Framework synthesis (Pope et al., 2000), for example, offers a deductive approach to extract and synthesize a large volume of data from qualitative research, and suggests the use of feature-based charts to visually interrogate the nature of constructs under study (for details, see Data Organization section, below; see also Kastner et al., 2012).

Construct Identification

We identified potential constructs to include in the review via several sources, with the goal of being as inclusive as possible. The constructs included in Kashdan et al. (2015)alexithymia, awareness, clarity, complexity, and differentiation/granularity2—served as an initial base, as this review provided a comprehensive recent starting point. To these, we added other constructs for individual differences in emotional knowledge, repertoire, or skill (i.e., those that describe how people understand and experience their own emotions). The first and senior authors developed a preliminary list of constructs based on their knowledge of the literature, frequent Google Scholar search terms (e.g., which words are suggested after typing “emotion[al]”), and popular science pieces on emotional health. Constructs were iteratively added to the list during publication selection, screening, and full-text review, as described below.

We excluded constructs from further consideration if they dealt exclusively with the perception, expression, or regulation of emotion. These domains were out of scope for the present review due to concerns with size and feasibility. The decision to omit constructs related to emotion regulation was also based on the ontological debate of whether the regulation of emotion is fundamentally different from its mental representation or experience (Gross & Barrett, 2011). However, the close relationship between emotion representation and regulation also meant that it was impossible to draw a clean line for construct inclusion. Some constructs, such as intelligence and competence, include the ability to regulate emotion (among other core aspects). We have retained these constructs because of their prominence in the literature on emotion-related abilities and their previous ties to expertise (e.g., Mayer et al., 2001).

Constructs were also excluded if they: were not specific to emotion (e.g., social skill; Riggio, 1986 or resilience; Connor & Davidson, 2003); had strictly interpersonal meanings (e.g., affective sensitivity; Kagan & Schneider, 1987 or emotional literacy; Steiner, 1984); were formulated only within a developmental, lifespan, or industrial/organizational context (e.g., affective social competence; Halberstadt et al., 2001 or emotional fitness; Cooper & Sawaf, 1997). Because our focus is on the mental representation of emotional experience, we excluded constructs dealing with general affect (i.e., pleasant vs. unpleasant mood) and the dynamics therein (e.g., affect intensity; Larsen & Diener, 1987, affective instability; Trull et al., 2008, or trait affect; Watson & Walker, 1996). We were interested in constructs with impacts for health and well-being; however, this was not a formalized criterion.

The first author reviewed example publications for each potential construct to determine if it met criteria for inclusion. Final decisions regarding inclusion were made through discussion with the senior author. In cases of uncertainty or disagreement, we erred on the side of inclusion. In total, we considered 133 constructs, of which 40 were included. For a full list of included constructs and corresponding publication search results, see Table S1. For a full list of excluded constructs, example publications, and reasons for exclusion, see Table S2.

Publication Selection

The American Psychological Association’s PsycINFO database was used to locate literature published up to the date of search; primary searches were conducted between May and October of 2018, going back to the earliest print date of 1927. Literature for each construct was searched separately, with the construct name as the keyword for the search (e.g., “alexithymia”). Multiword constructs were searched using several keyword phrases to ensure all possible variants were included in review: “emotional [CONSTRUCT]” (e.g., “emotional awareness”), “emotion [CONSTRUCT]” (e.g., “emotion awareness”), “affective [CONSTRUCT]” (e.g., “affective awareness”), and “affect [CONSTRUCT]” (e.g., “affect awareness”).3 Only literature written in English and in peer-reviewed journals or edited volumes was included; gray literature (e.g., dissertations or theses) was not considered. Results were further filtered to include only publications in which the keyword (phrase) was included in the title or abstract. See Figure 1 for a flowchart of publication identification, screening, and review. For a full list of search terms, dates, and hits, see Table S1.

Figure 1. Flowchart Describing Identification, Abstract Screening, and Full Review of Publications, Based on PRISMA Guidelines by Moher et al. (2009).

Figure 1

Note. PRISMA = Preferred Reporting Items for Systematic Reviews and Meta-Analyses.

Four search terms generated more than 500 hits in PsycINFO, even after filters were applied: “alexithymia” (2,529 records), “emotional awareness” (548 records), “emotional competence” (681 records), and “emotional intelligence” (3,428 records). Because the volume of results for these four constructs far out-weighed that of the others (which together yielded 1,316 records), and would have been unfeasible to review, we followed a two-part procedure to select relevant literature. First, we entered these search terms in Clarivate’s Web of Science database (which covers publications from 1900), where we could sort search results based on the number of citations. As before, we searched only for phrases appearing in the publication “topic,” with publications limited to articles, reviews, and book chapters written in English. In this case, however, we only selected those publications with at least 100 citations. This resulted in a much-reduced set of 382 records to be screened across the four constructs (Table S1). Second, to ensure we captured all key publications, we consulted a set of reviews for each construct (Table S3). Based on and including these reviews, we identified 66 publications potentially related to construct definition and measurement. These records were individually added to the list for further screening. Altogether, this process yielded 1,764 publications; 95 duplicates were removed, leaving 1,669 unique records.

Two trained undergraduate research assistants screened abstracts for identified publications to confirm they met the criteria for inclusion. Publications were excluded from further review if they: (a) described the construct or measure in relation to a specific domain (e.g., art appreciation, romantic relationships); (b) assessed the construct using only biological measures (e.g., fMRI or EEG); or (c) merely applied an existing measure to a sample of participants, without modifying that measure or directly comparing it to another (Table S4). Throughout this screening process, our goal was to identify publications that introduced, reformulated, critiqued, or compared the constructs of interest and their corresponding measures. We focused on these publications because they are especially likely to provide clear construct definitions and direct information on interrelationships between multiple constructs or measures. Of note, comparisons between constructs or measures could be either conceptual or empirical. All abstracts were screened independently by both research assistants, with the first and/or senior author adjudicating difficult or ambiguous cases. Of the 1,669 publications screened, 1,473 were excluded (i.e., 196 were retained at this stage).

Data Extraction

Data from publications were extracted following a coding procedure designed to capture each construct’s definition, measurement, validity, and relationships with other psychological and health variables, as well as theoretical background. For each publication, we recorded the information provided in Figure 2. Because publications could describe more than one construct, construct-specific items could be repeated until all constructs were documented.

Figure 2. Data Extraction Template Completed for Each Fully Reviewed Publication.

Figure 2

Note. Questions regarding a specific construct (“Construct Information” box) were repeated until all included constructs had been documented.

Publications were randomly assigned to a team of two reviewers. Both members of the team independently read and coded the publication and resolved any discrepancies through discussion to produce a consensus record.4 Difficult or ambiguous cases were addressed in meetings with all reviewers. As part of data extraction, reviewers were asked to identify, from the works cited, any additional publications that may be relevant. This iterative identification method extended our previous search and selection steps, as it was not constrained by the presence of specific keywords. Ninety-six publications were added in this way, 27 of which passed screening for further review, bringing the total to 223 publications. Full print or online versions could not be located for 13 records (e.g., they were published in books only held by European libraries), such that data were extracted for 210 publications.

Reviewers could recommend that a publication be excluded from analysis. For example, the full version of an article might have clarified that one or more of the inclusion criteria had not been met (see Figure 1, for list of reasons for exclusion). Through reading and discussion, we also decided to exclude all publications related to affective/emotional style, as well as those related to affective/emotional variability. We found that style (e.g., Davidson, 1992, 1998, 2000) did not provide sufficient treatment of the mental representation and behavioral measurement of specific emotional experiences (instead focusing on tendencies to approach vs. withdraw and underlying brain systems). Variability was initially included because it can refer to range, diversity, or context-specificity in experienced emotion (e.g., Barrett, 2009; Waugh et al., 2011). However, the publications that met our selection criteria dealt exclusively with affective dynamics.5 With these records removed, 141 publications remained. See Table 2 for a final list of included constructs and the number of publications representing each. The final database of publications, including key data extracted for each, is available via our online data repository (https://osf.io/a6vzk/).

Data Organization

We approached our goal of mapping the selected domain of research, individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience, in three ways. First, we summarized the definition, common measures, and dominant theoretical perspective of each included construct. To do this, we reviewed the definitions extracted for a given construct and selected a representative (and typically recent) definition based on one or two of the included publications. We also used the extracted data to identify commonly used measures for the construct and their corresponding measurement type. For example, we identified two commonly used measures for awareness. Most of the publications we reviewed used the LEAS(Lane et al., 1990), which is a performance-based measure, but there were also publications that used the Clarity and Attention subscales of the Trait Meta-Mood Scales (TMMS; Salovey et al., 1995), which is a global self-report measure. Similarly, we identified the dominant theoretical approaches or perspectives adopted in publications about the construct. We summarize these data in a Table 2 to provide a high-level overview of the constructs pertaining to the mental representation of emotional experience and to illustrate key commonalities and differences among constructs.

Second, we illustrated the interrelationships between constructs, considering both conceptual and empirical connections. To determine conceptual connections, we reviewed all definitions extracted for a given construct, and any notes made from the included publications’ discussion sections. Constructs were often comprised of multiple facets (i.e., subordinate constructs). For example, Kang and Shaver (2004) define complexity as comprised of range and differentiation; as such, we documented “range” and “differentiation” as facets of “complexity”, as well as links between each facet and the superordinate construct.6 Furthermore, publications often referred to relationships between the constructs in our review. For example, Kang and Shaver (2004) also discuss the relationship between complexity and intelligence, which we documented. In this way, we compiled a list of all the constructs and their facets, and a matrix of the conceptual connections between them.

Using a similar procedure, we built a matrix of empirical connections between constructs, with connections established whenever publications reported correlations between two or more of our included constructs. For each empirical connection, we documented the average effect size of the relationship (i.e., the r value) and the specific measures used. We used the matrices of conceptual connections and empirical connections (available via our online data repository) to build networks that allowed us to examine the relationships between constructs that are hypothesized as well as those that are apparent in the literature.

Third, we inductively generated a list of the features of expertise represented by each construct. To do this, we reviewed the definitions, measurement information, and notes extracted from each publication and noted salient characteristics about the construct in question. We then compared these characteristics to the features of domain-general expertise described in Table 1. For example, awareness stresses the role of conscious cognition in emotional experience (Lane et al., 1990; Lane & Schwartz, 1987), and so it fulfills the feature of awareness. Likewise, granularity stresses the need for differentiated emotion concepts (Barrett, 2004, 2017a), and so it fulfills the feature of structure of knowledge. In this way, we used constructs’ key characteristics to map them onto an integrated framework. We present the results of this synthesis as a polar plot illustrating the distribution of features across constructs for the mental representation of emotional experience.

Results

Summarizing Constructs for the Mental Representation of Emotional Experience

Table 2 presents the final list of included constructs along with their definitions, common measures, dominant theoretical perspectives, number of reviewed publications, and key publications (for individual construct summaries, see pages 11–20 of the Supplemental Materials). Ignoring modifiers (e.g., “emotion[al],” “affect[ive]”), there were 15 constructs represented in the extracted data. Two pairs of constructs were synonymous: differentiation and granularity (Kashdan et al., 2015; Smidt & Suvak, 2015),7 and intelligence and quotient (e.g., Bar-On, 1997, 2000). For the present analyses, we adopted the labels “granularity” and “intelligence.” Four constructs—agnosia, diversity, utilization, and range—were represented by only one or two publications each. Based on this small literature size and the constructs’ definitions, we (a) merged diversity and range, (b) subsumed agnosia under alexithymia, and (c) subsumed utilization under competence. Together, these decisions produced a final total of 10 constructs.

Two constructs—alexithymia and intelligence—had particularly large literatures to summarize, with 43 and 44 included publications, respectively. In each case, there are several competing definitions and measures, the history and details of which were out of scope for the present review.8 For current purposes, we focused on the work of Taylor, Bagby, and Parker for alexithymia (e.g., Bagby et al., 1994; Taylor et al., 1985) and the work of Mayer, Salovey, and Caruso for intelligence (e.g., Mayer et al., 2002; Salovey & Mayer, 1990). The definitions and measures introduced by these research groups are the most widely used and/or psychometrically validated in their respective literatures (alexithymia: Lumley et al., 2007; but see Kooiman et al., 2002; intelligence: Cherniss, 2010; Joseph & Newman, 2010; Livingstone & Day, 2005; but see Maul, 2012; Roberts et al., 2010). Other prominent definitions and measures are presented in the Supplemental Materials (e.g., the Emotional Quotient Inventory [EQ-i]; Bar-On, 1997; the Bermond-Vorst Alexithymia Questionnaire [BVAQ]; Bermond & Oosterveld, 1994).

The first trend made clear by this summary is a similarity in how these constructs are typically measured. In the research shown in Table 2, nine of the 10 constructs were measured using global self-report instruments (e.g., the Toronto Alexithymia Scale, 20-item version [TAS-20]; Bagby et al., 1994). Seven of the 10 constructs were (also) measured using indices/scores derived from performance-based tasks (e.g., the LEAS; Lane et al., 1990), retrospective emotion frequency ratings (e.g., for calculating diversity; Quoidbach et al., 2014), or in-the-moment emotion intensity ratings (e.g., intraclass correlations for granularity; e.g., Tugade et al., 2004). In-the-moment intensity ratings, which are typically gathered via experience sampling procedures, have been described as a behavioral measure of emotion because they do not rely on memory or aggregation over time (Barrett & Barrett, 2001; Robinson & Clore, 2002). It has been argued that behavioral measures are more appropriate for measuring the skills or abilities represented by the present constructs (Joseph & Newman, 2010; Kashdan et al., 2015; Siegling et al., 2015), whereas global self-report instruments may capture individuals’ beliefs about themselves and other biases (e.g., Barrett, 1997; Mayer et al., 2001; Robinson & Clore, 2002). Notwithstanding, all of the measures reviewed evidenced construct validity and had predictive utility for outcomes of interest (e.g., Bagby et al., 2020).

Another key take-away from Table 2 is the role played by various theoretical perspectives on emotion. Across all 10 constructs, appraisal-theoretic influences appeared most often. These influences included both “causal” appraisal perspectives (e.g., Frijda, 1986; Lazarus, 1991; Plutchik, 1980; Roseman, 1991; Scherer, 1984), which hold that appraisals are mental processes that give rise to the experience of emotion, as well as “descriptive” appraisal perspectives (e.g., Clore & Ortony, 2000, 2008; Moors et al., 2013; Scherer, 2009a, 2009b), which hold that appraisals capture the content or meaning of emotional experience (for the distinction between these approaches, see Barrett, 2016; Barrett et al., 2007; Gross & Barrett, 2011). Work on clarity, diversity, and flexibility has been mostly influenced by appraisal perspectives, whereas work on intelligence and competence has also been shaped by basic emotion perspectives (e.g., Ekman, 1972; Izard, 1993; Tomkins, 1962, 1963) and work on awareness and complexity has also been shaped by cognitive-developmental perspectives (e.g., Labouvie-Vief & Medler, 2002; Lane & Schwartz, 1987; Piaget, 1937; Werner & Kaplan, 1963).

Work on alexithymia has been historically situated within a psychoanalytic or psychodynamic tradition (e.g., Freud, 1891; Marty & de M’Uzan, 1963; Ruesch, 1948), which understands emotional experience as a way of symbolizing or processing internal or unconscious conflicts (e.g., Krystal, 1979; Lesser, 1981; Nemiah & Sifneos, 1970; Taylor, 1984). Contemporary accounts of alexithymia, however, understand it as deficits in the processing of emotional information (e.g., Lane et al., 2000; Lumley et al., 2007). Work on creativity and granularity has been anchored in a (social) constructionist framework (e.g., Averill, 1980; Barrett, 2009; James, 1884; Russell, 2003), which emphasizes the influence of individual history, cultural background, and physical and situational context on the experience of emotion. Each of these theoretical perspectives has implications for understanding individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience, how they can be measured, and whether they can be improved. We return to this point in the construct synthesis section, below.

Illustrating Relationships Between Constructs

Conceptual Relationships

Figure 3 provides a descriptive network illustration of the conceptual interrelationships between constructs and their facets as they are defined in the published literature. Nodes corresponding to constructs are teal, while nodes corresponding to facets are light gray; for clarity of viewing (and in keeping with Table 2), all nodes are labeled without modifiers (e.g., “emotion[al]”). Nodes and their labels are sized according to their number of connections. Connections linking a facet to a broader construct are indicated with an arrow directed at the construct; connections linking two “peer” constructs are indicated with an arrow at either end. Connections are weighted by the number of publications represented, from a scale of one (a single publication; thinnest lines) to five (five or more publications; thickest lines). Weights were capped at five to provide a representative sense of endorsement rates, while accounting for differences in publication selection for high-volume constructs such as alexithymia and intelligence. Finally, facets have been renamed to facilitate integration in the network. For example, source clarity (Boden & Berenbaum, 2011; Boden & Thompson, 2015; Cameron et al., 2013; Lischetzke & Eid, 2017) is referred to as “appraisal” to highlight connections to appraisal-theoretic perspectives as well as to other constructs such as competence (Scherer, 2007) and intelligence (Salovey & Mayer, 1990). Furthermore, constructs and facets defined as inabilities have been conceptually inverted. For example, alexithymia is defined as “the inability to identify, describe, and introspect about one’s emotional experiences” (Aaron et al., 2018); when inverted as “(a)lexithymia”, these facets became the abilities of identification, description, and introspection.9 As identification was also a facet of awareness (Bagby et al., 2006; Boden & Thompson, 2015), clarity (Boden & Berenbaum, 2011; Lischetzke & Eid, 2017), and competence (Brasseur et al., 2013), this node could be connected accordingly.

Figure 3. Network Based on Conceptual Interrelationships Documented Between Constructs and Their Facets.

Figure 3

Note. Node color distinguishes constructs summarized in Table 2 (teal) from facets added during data extraction (light gray). Only publications by Taylor, Bagby, and colleagues (e.g., Bagby et al., 1994; Taylor et al., 1985) and Mayer, Salovey, and colleagues (e.g., Mayer et al., 2002; Salovey & Mayer, 1990) are represented for alexithymia and intelligence, respectively. For a version of this network including other definitions of these constructs, see Figure S1. Nodes and their labels are sized according to their number of connections (i.e., degree). Facets are connected to broader constructs with an arrow directed at the construct; constructs are connected to each other with an arrow at both ends. Connections are weighted counts of the number of publications represented, such that the thinnest lines represent a single publication, and the thickest lines represent five or more publications. Nodes renamed from the original publications to facilitate integration: “granularity” also refers to differentiation (e.g., Barrett et al., 2001); “covariation” also refers to dialecticism (e.g., Grossmann et al., 2016); “regulation” also refers to repair (Salovey et al., 1995); “appraisal” also refers to source clarity (e.g., Boden & Berenbaum, 2011); “identification” also refers to type clarity (e.g., Boden & Berenbaum, 2011); “voluntary attention” (e.g., Boden & Thompson, 2015) also refers to redirected attention (Salovey & Mayer, 1990). Facets noting the use of language to verbalize emotion (e.g., labeling; Swinkels & Giuliano, 1995) are referred to as “description” (following Bagby et al., 1994). Nodes conceptually inverted: “(a)gnosia”; “(a)lexithymia” and its facets identification, description, introspection (vs. externally oriented thinking), and imagination (vs. reduced fantasy). Network visualization created in Gephi (Bastian et al., 2009) using the Yifan Hu Proportional layout (Hu, 2005).

Across the network, connections between constructs reflect underlying relationships between subdomains, research groups, and theoretical perspectives. Missing connections between constructs at the periphery reflect, then, opportunities for conceptual integration. For example, we observed that the constructs of flexibility and diversity shared fewer connections with their neighboring constructs (i.e., their nodes were smaller): flexibility was indirectly connected to competence (via the facets of regulation and expression), and diversity was only directly connected to complexity. In contrast, the constructs of intelligence, (a)lexithymia, awareness, and clarity had many complex connections (i.e., their nodes were larger and connected by thick lines to multiple other nodes). These constructs were directly linked to each other and indirectly linked via the facets of appraisal, attention, and identification. In other words, these constructs were often described as separate but related and were conceptualized with overlapping features.

Broadly, we interpret the network in Figure 3 as depicting several interrelated clusters of constructs with intelligence, (a)lexithymia, and awareness/clarity as hubs. The intelligence cluster was the largest and included constructs oriented toward applied contexts, such as competence and flexibility. Creativity also formed a part of this cluster, although as a satellite of intelligence; this relationship reflects the theoretical context in which creativity was introduced as a constructionist alternative to intelligence (e.g., Averill, 2004; Ivcevic et al., 2007). The (a)lexithymia cluster, the second largest, evidenced its clinical origins through the neurological construct of (a)gnosia (Lane et al., 2015), and facets derived from the psychoanalytic tradition such as introspection (i.e., the inverse of externally oriented thinking) and imagination (i.e., the inverse of reduced fantasy). Still, this cluster had many nodes in common with the awareness/clarity cluster, which bridges clinical application with a basic science interest in describing the mental representation of emotional experience (e.g., voluntary vs. involuntary attention; Huang et al., 2013; source vs. type clarity; Boden & Berenbaum, 2011). This descriptive emphasis is shared by the complexity cluster, whose constructs additionally seek to capture individual differences across the lifespan (e.g., Grühn et al., 2013) and across cultures (e.g., Grossmann et al., 2016). Granularity did not have a clear cluster membership; it shared a strong connection with complexity but was also situated between (a)lexithymia and awareness.

Empirical Relationships

Figure 4 provides a descriptive network illustration of the empirical interrelationships between constructs. As in Figure 3, constructs are represented by teal nodes, facets by light gray nodes, and nodes are sized by their number of connections. In this network, however, connections between nodes represent statistical relationships (i.e., correlations) between the constructs/facets, regardless of the measure used to collect these data. The connections represent mean effect sizes (r) of all reported correlations and are colored according to the direction of correlation (blue for positive, purple for negative). Importantly, because (a)lexthymia and its facets were conceptually inverted, so were corresponding connections: publications documenting negative correlations between alexithymia and intelligence (e.g., Parker et al., 2001), for example, are displayed as positive (blue) connections between the two nodes. Additionally, the network layout was structured using the strength of the mean effect sizes. Connections are undirected (i.e., there are no arrows), denoting bidirectional relationships.

Figure 4. Network Based on Empirical Interrelationships Documented Between Constructs and Their Facets.

Figure 4

Note. Node color distinguishes constructs summarized in Table 2 (teal) from facets added during data extraction (light gray). Connection color distinguishes direction of correlation (blue for positive, purple for negative). Only publications by Taylor, Bagby, and colleagues (e.g., Bagby et al., 1994; Taylor et al., 1985) and Mayer, Salovey, and colleagues (e.g., Mayer et al., 2002; Salovey & Mayer, 1990) are represented for alexithymia and intelligence, respectively. For a version of this network including other definitions and measures of these constructs, see Figure S2. Connections are undirected. The network is structured according to the strength of the mean effect sizes. Nodes renamed from the original publications to facilitate integration: “granularity” also refers to differentiation (e.g., Barrett et al., 2001); “covariation” also refers to dialecticism (e.g., Grossmann et al., 2016); “regulation” also refers to repair (Salovey et al., 1995); “appraisal” also refers to source clarity (e.g., Boden & Berenbaum, 2011); “identification” also refers to type clarity (e.g., Boden & Berenbaum, 2011); “voluntary attention” (e.g., Boden & Thompson, 2015) also refers to redirected attention (Salovey & Mayer, 1990). Facets noting the use of language to verbalize emotion (e.g., labeling; Swinkels & Giuliano, 1995) are referred to as “description” (following Bagby et al., 1994). Nodes conceptually inverted: “(a)gnosia”; “(a)lexithymia” and its facets identification, description, introspection (vs. externally oriented thinking), and imagination (vs. reduced fantasy). Network visualization created in Gephi (Bastian et al., 2009) using the Yifan Hu Proportional layout (Hu, 2005).

This network provides a high-level snapshot of how data are collected and analyzed in relation to the constructs reviewed. In Figure 3, conceptual connections between constructs were sparser and organized into several interrelated but distinguishable clusters. In Figure 4, empirical connections between constructs are numerous. Constructs were frequently compared against each other, even if they were not considered to be conceptually related. There were also a variety of comparisons made, although it was rare for more than two constructs to be compared within a single publication (cf. Lumley et al., 2005). Facets of (a)lexithymia and intelligence were dominant in this network, reflecting the ubiquity of their corresponding measures (e.g., TAS-20; Bagby et al., 1994: Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test [MSCEIT]; Mayer et al., 2002). The most common comparison (i.e., largest node) was with the facet of identification (shared by (a)lexithymia, awareness, clarity, and competence), emphasizing how important the ability to categorize emotional experience is for measuring multiple constructs. Several nodes—(a)gnosia, context-sensitivity, and flexibility—remained unconnected and therefore are not represented in this network. Also, note, however, that because our goal was to review a representative rather than comprehensive set of publications, it is likely that there are missing comparisons—particularly for the high-volume constructs of alexithymia and intelligence.

This network suggests overlap in what constructs measure and, from this perspective, lends credibility to our proposal to integrate these constructs within a unifying framework. The overall relationship, after inverting (a)lexithymia, is positive; negative correlations are few and generally weak. Nodes generally form one cluster, except for constructs such as diversity and competence whose measures were less often compared in the publications we reviewed. This observation builds on prior meta-analytic comparisons of common measures for (a)lexithymia (TAS-20) and awareness (LEAS; Maroti et al., 2018) and on studies comparing multiple constructs and measures for each (e.g., Gohm & Clore, 2002; Ivcevic et al., 2007; Kang & Shaver, 2004; Lumley et al., 2005). These studies have found positive, small effect-size relationships between measures, which researchers have typically interpreted as discriminant validity for the constructs in question. For example, a significant but weak meta-analytic correlation of r = .12 was used to argue that (a)lexithymia and awareness were separate but related (Maroti et al., 2018). Figure 4 situates these findings with respect to a larger network, emphasizing the similarity of these constructs when viewed from a higher level. Nonetheless, the interpretation of correlation strength also depends upon the conceptual model used to structure a given domain (Bollen & Lennox, 1991), a point to which we return in the discussion.

Synthesizing Constructs Based on Features of Expertise

Figure 5 presents the set of 12 features hypothesized to constitute expertise in emotion, as determined deductively from accounts of domain-general expertise. These features are presented in the same order as in Table 1. The polar plot summarizes which features are represented by the constructs included in this review, as determined inductively from definitions, measures, and notes extracted from the selected publications. Features are plotted along radial lines, with constructs plotted along concentric circles in alphabetical order from (a)lexithymia (the innermost circle) to intelligence (the outermost circle). Data points indicate where a feature is present; in cases of disagreement or conflicting accounts within the literature, the data point is not filled (see Table S5 for example publications in support of each point).

Figure 5. Features of Expertise in Emotion, as Determined Deductively From Accounts of Domain-General Expertise.

Figure 5

Note. For an alternative presentation of these data, see Table S5. Features are plotted along radial lines, with constructs plotted along concentric circles in alphabetical order from (a)lexithymia (the innermost circle) to intelligence (the outermost circle). Data points indicate where a feature is present; in cases of disagreement or conflicting accounts within the literature, the data point is not filled.

Overall, in Figure 5 we see a many-to-many (rather than one-to-one) mapping between constructs and features. Two things are especially noteworthy. First, features varied in the number of constructs in which they were present. Every construct satisfied the feature of mental representation. This is by design, as this feature was a conceptual prerequisite for inclusion in our review. Other than the criterion, however, there is no single feature that is present in all constructs. Some aspects of the feature space are underrepresented. Second, constructs varied in the number of features they covered. Intelligence, granularity, and creativity were the most comprehensive, while flexibility and diversity were the least. However, more comprehensive constructs were not necessarily consistent in the features they covered. Moreover, the number of features covered by a construct is not intended as an index of quality or utility: As we discuss next, the presence of features was largely driven by underlying theoretical assumptions about the nature of emotions and methods of measurement.

One of the primary dimensions on which constructs differed is the nature of the conceptual knowledge underlying the mental representation of emotional experience. Most construct definitions explicitly acknowledged that knowledge or “mental content” is a central feature of expertise. The majority of constructs specified something about the structure (i.e., quality) of knowledge: granularity, for example, required emotion concepts (i.e., accrued knowledge and experience) to be nuanced and precise (e.g., Barrett et al., 2001; Tugade et al., 2004), while complexity emphasized high-dimensionality (e.g., Carstensen et al., 2000; Ong et al., 2017) and creativity underscored person-specificity (e.g., Averill, 1999; Fuchs et al., 2007). Creativity and granularity—along with diversity and complexity—also highlighted the breadth of knowledge supporting emotional experience. In the case of diversity and complexity, this could be seen in the emphasis on range (e.g., Kang & Shaver, 2004; Quoidbach et al., 2014). For creativity, breadth was captured by an emphasis on novelty (e.g., Averill, 1999; Ivcevic et al., 2017), whereas for granularity breadth was implied by having emotion concepts that are specific rather than overlapping (thereby covering more conceptual “space”; Barrett, 2017a).

Instead of speaking to the structure or breadth of knowledge, work on intelligence and competence focused on the type of knowledge. That is, these constructs followed the assumption (from basic and/or causal appraisal accounts of emotion) that one could be “correct” or “incorrect” in one’s knowledge—and that accuracy was critical for expertise (e.g., Izard et al., 2011; Mayer & Salovey, 1997; Scherer, 2007). By these accounts, having more, or differently structured, knowledge does not necessarily enhance expertise, if one does not already know the specific things one should know about emotions, such as their (evolutionarily endowed) forms and functions (e.g., Izard, 2009; Salovey & Mayer, 1990; Scherer, 2007).

Another primary dimension of expertise in emotion was whether it was considered an ability or skill versus a trait. Four of the 10 constructs we reviewed were conceptualized predominantly as abilities or skills: competence (e.g., Brasseur et al., 2013), creativity (e.g., Averill, 1999), granularity (e.g., Kashdan et al., 2015), and intelligence (e.g., Mayer et al., 2000).10 Ability models broadly assumed that expertise is not a latent capacity, but something that is continually acquired throughout the lifespan and can be actively improved (e.g., Kashdan et al., 2015; Mayer et al., 2016). In contrast, five constructs were described, either implicitly or explicitly, as traits: (a)lexithymia, awareness, clarity, complexity, and diversity. Awareness (e.g., Lane & Schwartz, 1992) and complexity (e.g., Lindquist & Barrett, 2008) have alternatively been conceptualized as abilities or skills.

Three features captured the types of behaviors that indicate expertise. By most accounts, verbal representation of emotional experience provides key—if not unparalleled—insight into mental representation. “Verbal representation” included the identification (i.e., labeling) and description of emotion, and formed a central part of (a)lexithymia (e.g., Bermond et al., 1999; Sifneos, 1973; Taylor, 1984), awareness (e.g., Lane & Schwartz, 1987; Swinkels & Giuliano, 1995; Thompson et al., 2009), clarity (e.g., Boden & Thompson, 2017; Lischetzke & Eid, 2017), and granularity (e.g., Barrett, 2004; Lee et al., 2017). The appropriate (i.e., normative) use of language was also included in some conceptualizations of competence (e.g., Scherer, 2007) and intelligence (e.g., Ivcevic et al., 2007).

Adaptive responses were a further concomitant of competence, creativity, granularity, and intelligence, although these constructs differed in their understanding of “adaptive.” As noted above, measures of competence and intelligence tended to assume universal or at least strongly normative operationalizations of emotional behaviors (e.g., Izard, 2009; Mayer et al., 2000). These constructs also assumed that expertise should meet criteria that are more-or-less context-invariant (e.g., Averill, 2004; Petrides, 2010), with these criteria taken from hypotheses about evolutionarily endowed forms and functions (e.g., Izard, 2009; Scherer, 2007), established by a panel of emotion researchers (Mayer et al., 2000), or derived from a sample of U.S. participants (Mayer et al., 2000). In all cases, there was an assumption of a single “best” way to respond, with individual variability in response considered an undesirable deviation from this norm.11

By comparison, constructs such as complexity, creativity, and granularity stressed context-sensitivity in assessment and interpretation (e.g., Averill, 1999; Kashdan et al., 2015; Lindquist & Barrett, 2008). The cross-cutting assumption—based largely on constructionist and descriptive appraisal perspectives—was that expertise is a relative rather than absolute measure, and varies naturally as a function of culturally, personally, and situationally relevant goals and constraints (e.g., Averill, 1999; Barrett, 2017a).

Two features related to how expertise shapes emotional experience. Most constructs specified that expertise included awareness of emotion—that individuals consciously represent and navigate emotional experience (e.g., Lane & Schwartz, 1987; Subic-Wrana et al., 2005; Thompson et al., 2009). Granularity was a notable exception to this trend. Although the measurement of granularity invokes the use of verbal representation (which requires conscious access), the experience of granular emotions does not per se require subjective awareness (Barrett, 2017a, 2017b; see also Lambie & Marcel, 2002). Constructs such as (a)lexithymia and awareness expanded subjective awareness further to include attention to emotions. This attention can take the form of active scanning or monitoring (e.g., Coffey et al., 2003; Gohm & Clore, 2002; Salovey et al., 1995; Swinkels & Giuliano, 1995) or of introspection or internally oriented thought (e.g., Marty & de M’Uzan, 1963; Taylor et al., 1985), and can be voluntary or involuntary (e.g., Boden & Thompson, 2015; Elfenbein & MacCann, 2017).12

Two final features related to how expertise is acquired and implemented. Many accounts of domain-general expertise speak to its acquisition via deliberate practice (e.g., Ullén et al., 2016). The only constructs to explicitly advocate for such an approach to emotion were creativity and granularity. With its facet of “preparedness,” creativity directly tapped the intuition that individuals develop expertise through intentional engagement with and reflection upon their emotions (Averill, 1999). Similarly, individuals can improve their granularity by being “collectors of experience” (Barrett, 2017a), seeking out new ways to expand their perspective and gain new, more nuanced concepts. Granularity further emphasized that these new concepts lead to improved prediction (Barrett, 2017a). Individuals with greater expertise are more skilled at using their knowledge and can better anticipate and adjust to upcoming challenges. While constructs such as creativity and flexibility did emphasize context-sensitivity, as discussed above, they did not capture the proactive planning accounted for by prediction. Prediction was also discussed in some accounts of (a)lexithymia (Lane et al., 2015) and complexity (Lindquist & Barrett, 2008).

Discussion

The idea that some people are better or worse than others at understanding and experiencing emotions is widely held. Decades of research support the existence of individual differences in emotional competencies, with thousands of studies demonstrating the various ways in which individuals can excel or be deficient, and the downstream consequences of these individual differences for mental health, physical health, and other real-world outcomes. Yet, the volume of research and variety of individual differences can also be a hindrance to scientific discovery and practical application. There are dozens of psychological constructs (and an even greater number of measures) pertaining to individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience, and research on these constructs is often found in separate literature with separate audiences, research goals, and theoretical assumptions.

In the present article, we have proposed a means to integrate these constructs within a unifying framework based on features of domain-general expertise. Through a scoping review procedure, we conducted an iterative and systematic review of the literature. We identified 10 core constructs: alexithymia, awareness, clarity, complexity, competence, creativity, diversity, flexibility, granularity, and intelligence. For each construct, we interrogated a representative set of publications to determine the features of expertise represented, the primary methods of measurement, and their underlying theoretical perspectives. We also situated constructs with respect to each other in terms of definition and measurement, illustrating conceptual and empirical relationships using networks. Finally, we remapped constructs to a set of deductively generated features for expertise so that we could compare them. Throughout this process, we observed overlaps, gaps, and inconsistencies in construct definition and measurement that provide insight into the nature of expertise in emotion as it pertains to the mental representation of emotional experience. These findings provide a framework for interpreting a broader set of emotion-related individual differences and have implications for future research.

Scoping Review Summary

We created an expertise framework for emotion as a means of querying and comparing constructs in this domain. Returning to the opening analogy of the blind men and the elephant, our intention was to integrate a diverse set of individual differences so that we could describe the different parts and examine how (and if) they all fit together. We explored the nomological network for the mental representation of emotional experience by illustrating the relationships between constructs. The conceptual network, based primarily on construct definitions, reflected the motivations of theorists. The connections in this network revealed a body of research with several interrelated clusters of constructs, anchored by intelligence, alexithymia, and awareness and clarity. We interpret these clusters as evidence of the conceptual splintering or rediscovery that has produced the different “parts of the elephant.” This splintering was not as evident, however, when we examined the empirical connections between constructs as measured. Instead, the web of correlations between these constructs and their facets suggested broad overlap across the network—that these constructs may be part of the same elephant, even if they do differ in some way or another.

We explored the nature of these conceptual differences by analyzing the features of expertise represented by each construct. We identified several features that were shared by many of the surveyed constructs, beyond the feature that served as an inclusion criterion (i.e., mental representation). Among the major commonalities were that experts are consciously aware of their experiences and that experts use specific language to verbally represent them. In line with domain-general accounts, expertise in emotion was often seen as an ability or skill. There were also clear distinctions. Perhaps the most notable was between constructs that focus on types of knowledge and normative or stipulated responses in determining expertise, such as competence and intelligence, and those that focus on the structure of the knowledge and context-sensitivity of the response, such as creativity and granularity. These differences were often rooted in theoretical assumptions about emotion—such as the contrast we highlighted between the basic emotion and causal appraisal accounts that ground competence and intelligence and constructionist accounts that ground creativity and granularity. Differences between constructs were also influenced by other motivating factors, such as the goals of a program of research (e.g., to help managers work with personnel, to help clinicians treat patients, to better understand underlying mechanisms).

There are some useful general observations that we can make from this work. In both our network- and feature-based analyses, we observed that certain constructs are more central to this domain than others. Flexibility and diversity, for instance, may be peripheral constructs. It is possible that these constructs have less support because they are backed by less literature. It is also possible that these constructs are less representative of expertise in emotion. Likewise, we “zoomed in on” only one portion of a much larger nomological network of constructs related to individual differences in emotional competencies. As such, the connections between our subnetwork and its neighboring networks are not visible. For example, we excluded constructs that dealt exclusively with the perception, expression, and regulation of emotion. Yet, these processes emerged as facets of competence (e.g., Brasseur et al., 2013), flexibility (e.g., Fu et al., 2018), and intelligence (e.g., Mayer & Salovey, 1997). We interpret this as an indication of the overlap between a set of interrelated bodies of research.

Limitations

Although we sought to integrate across many different emotional competencies, there are necessary limits on the scope of this work. A more comprehensive account of expertise in emotion would also include constructs related to the regulation of emotion in oneself (e.g., coping, control), those related to the representation of others’ emotional experiences (e.g., recognition, empathy), and those related to the management of emotion in others (e.g., capital, attunement; see Table S2). It may further include research on affective dynamics, changes across the lifespan, and disordered emotional health. We conceptualize the understanding and management of emotions as an umbrella, the exact structure of which should be determined through systematic review and synthesis of relevant constructs. In this regard, we echo prior work that has conceptualized emotional intelligence as a broad, multifaceted domain (e.g., Bar-On, 1997; Elfenbein & MacCann, 2017; Palmer et al., 2008; Tett et al., 2005). In their initial 1990 publication, Salovey and Mayer proposed a taxonomic framework for emotional intelligence as a set of skills related to emotion in oneself and others. Here, we have built upon this framework by introducing a set of domain-general features that provide a basis for interpretation of expertise in emotion writ broadly.

Another consideration is whether our scoping review has sufficiently sampled the included constructs. For constructs with large literatures—alexithymia, awareness, competence, and intelligence —we certainly did not sample all possible results, intentionally limiting our review to a set of representative publications. For all constructs, we excluded publications that did not introduce, reformulate, critique, or compare constructs or their measures. These decisions could have influenced our conclusions if excluded publications contained new constructs or measures or documented new definitions or interrelationships. This seems relatively unlikely given our goal of representative rather than comprehensive sampling and the conceptual focus of our review. Even so, these conceptual limitations should be addressed by future research.

There are also important methodological limitations to note. We excluded gray literature and non-English sources. These decisions are likely to have inadvertently perpetuated biases in which research gets published and which cultural viewpoints are represented (Arnett, 2009; Medin et al., 2017; Rad et al., 2018), tempering the universality of our conclusions. This possibility is particularly relevant given widely documented sociocultural variation in emotion-related processes (e.g., Boiger et al., 2018; Gendron et al., 2018; Niedenthal et al., 2019; Tamir et al., 2016) and must be dealt with to ensure the generalizability of our proposed framework. The databases we used may have likewise limited our results (e.g., Mongeon & Paul-Hus, 2016). We propose that PsycINFO, our primary database, was a reasonable starting place given that we sought to survey constructs for the mental representation of emotional experience. However, emotion research is highly inter-disciplinary, spanning anthropology, computer science, linguistics, philosophy, and more. PsycINFO does not cover all historical publications from these fields (Burman, 2018). Nevertheless, an advantage to using PsycINFO as our starting point was that it allowed us to seed an expertise framework within a more targeted literature. Indeed, one purpose of our scoping review was to gauge whether our approach merits further research, including detailed reviews that incorporate (unpublished) sources in a variety of languages, and databases with more multidisciplinary coverage (e.g., Walters, 2007). We believe that it does.

What Is Expertise in Emotion?

Fundamentally, our approach of bringing constructs into a common feature space defined by expertise is an ontological pursuit. We selected a set of constructs with family resemblance; our goal was, at least in part, to assess whether these constructs are related. The results of our scoping review suggest that they are. Yet, we observed that the constructs were not fully overlapping and that some were more central to this domain than others. In other words, there does not appear to be support for an underlying construct of “emotional expertise” that gives rise to alexithymia, awareness, intelligence, etc. We are unable to formally test this possibility, however, because we have only theoretical suggestions (conceptual network), correlational evidence (empirical network), and inductive properties (feature synthesis). Moreover, such a test would presume that constructs for expertise in emotion follow a latent variable model, where indicators (i.e., the constructs we have surveyed) are explained by a given construct, are highly correlated with each other, and can be considered independent to the extent that they reliably stand in for one another (Bollen & Lennox, 1991). This conceptual model is dominant in psychological science (Borsboom et al., 2003; Coan, 2010) and corresponds with classical measurement theory in which construct validity is established through internal consistency and reliability (Spearman, 1904a, 1904b). It also has historical connections with expertise in emotion, as the best-known latent variable model, intelligence (Borsboom et al., 2003), is echoed in work on emotional intelligence (e.g., Mayer et al., 2008; but see Salovey & Mayer, 1990). However, it carries with it the overall assumption that indicators are manifestations of, and can be reduced to, a single causal entity. The results of our scoping review do not support this assumption.

Instead, our observations are more consistent with an emergent variable model, in which the indicators explain the construct and, in this sense, are formative (Barrett, 2000, 2011; Bollen & Lennox, 1991; Coan, 2010). In an emergent variable model, indicators jointly constitute the construct, and so no one can substitute for any other—just as socioeconomic status (SES) cannot be explained by occupation, income, or education alone (Bollen & Lennox, 1991). The construct is a product of the interaction of the indicators, rather than an underlying essence. This conceptual model also has implications for measurement: a consensus of indicators is necessary to fully understand the construct (Bollen & Lennox, 1991)—indicators are neither interchangeable nor sufficient in isolation (Coan, 2010). Each has separate value, and there is no requirement that they should be highly correlated. Because an emergent variable model cannot rely on internal consistency and reliability, however, it is psychologically uninterpretable in isolation: Its validity is determined via its effects on extrinsic criteria (Bollen & Lennox, 1991; see also Barrett, 2000). In the domain of emotion, these criteria are the clinical and real-world impacts of having more or less expertise.

An emergent variable approach is particularly apt for the analogy of the blind men and the elephant because it explains why we cannot understand the trunk from touching the toes: only together do they describe what an elephant is (i.e., they contribute different information to the model). The elephant cannot be explained by its trunk alone but, because its features are jointly constitutive, would also not be an elephant without it. An emergent variable approach values the parts because it is only through understanding their relationship to the larger whole that we can assess their contribution (Barrett, 2000, 2011). This approach still implies the existence of a “larger whole,” or an inferred construct, but can more flexibly accommodate different types of indicators and the relationships between them (Coan, 2010). For example, it could be that some of the constructs we surveyed in the present review can be merged, whereas others have utility for sampling separate parts of the expertise feature space. These are questions for future research. Understanding expertise in emotion as an emergent variable provides a roadmap for the theoretical and empirical tasks that comprise this research, as we discuss next.

Implications for Future Research

An emergent variable model suggests that multiple indicators combine to give rise to expertise in emotion. This approach has two main implications for future research. First, it implies the need for multiple measurements and methods as often as possible because one indicator cannot stand in for another (Barrett, 2000, 2011; Coan, 2010). This emphasis on multimethod assessment builds on previous recommendations (e.g., Bagby et al., 2006; Lumley et al., 2005; Scollon et al., 2003; Smith, Killgore, & Lane, 2018) with new insights from an expertise framework. Domain-general accounts of expertise recommend measures that allow individuals to demonstrate expert performance as an ability or skill, so that this performance can be related to situation-specific goals and needs. Expertise in emotion also emphasizes facility of verbal representation, such that individuals’ use of language to describe emotions can be considered a key aspect of performance. Taken together, these criteria promote the use of performance-based tasks (e.g., responses to scenarios gathered using the LEAS; Lane et al., 1990) and momentary reports repeated over time (e.g., data gathered using experience sampling methods; Barrett & Barrett, 2001). These measures can be complemented by global self-report instruments that capture individuals’ aggregate understandings and experiences, but may also reflect their self-concept (e.g., Robinson & Clore, 2002).

An emergent variable approach also implies a focus on the mechanisms that link indicators to each other as well as to expertise in emotion (Barrett, 2000, 2011; Coan, 2010). Broadly speaking, the mental representation of emotional experience is supported by both biological and interpersonal processes (Barrett et al., 2007). Several contemporary models of emotional experience offer hypotheses for how these processes relate to the present set of individual difference constructs. For example, emotional awareness (Smith, Killgore, & Lane, 2018; see also Smith et al., 2017), emotional granularity (Barrett, 2017a, 2017b), and emotional intelligence (Smith, Killgore, Alkozei, & Lane, 2018) are supported by brain-based and mechanistic models that may be used to anchor future research. In the present review, we excluded constructs and publications that used only neural or physiological measures, as well as those that relied solely on perceptual or dyadic measures, as these were not necessary for describing the mental representation of one’s own emotional experience as a set of behaviors. Moving forward, there is a need to integrate the constructs identified here with research on the biological processes supporting the implementation of expertise and research on the interpersonal processes guiding its development. This integration is necessary to connect expertise in emotion with consequences for health and well-being.

Biological measures can provide insight into the nature and implementation of expertise in emotion. Brain-based models of emotion (e.g., Barrett, 2017b; Smith, Killgore, & Lane, 2018) suggest that measures of neural structure and function can provide a window onto the mental representation of emotional experience. One potential path forward is represented by recent work demonstrating that differences in emotion knowledge are reflected in the neural representation of categories of emotional facial configurations (Brooks et al., 2019). Future research can use this approach to investigate how individual differences in neural representation are associated with the breadth and structure of other types of emotion knowledge and whether they vary according to situation-specific goals. Using expertise to make adaptive, context-sensitive responses may also be reflected in measures of peripheral physiological activity. Prior research suggests that respiratory sinus arrhythmia (RSA; also known as high-frequency heart rate variability) is associated with flexible responding and emotional health. Individuals with lower resting RSA and blunted or excessive RSA reactivity demonstrate poorer emotion regulation and higher incidence of psychopathology (e.g., Beauchaine, 2015), whereas individuals with higher resting RSA report greater subjective well-being supported by adaptive regulation (e.g., Geisler et al., 2010). Models that explicitly connect RSA with neural (i.e., central) measures (e.g., Thayer & Lane, 2000, 2009; see also Smith et al., 2017) may provide a way to link potential physiological correlates of expertise in emotion.

To address social mechanisms, research is needed that can provide insight into how expertise in emotion is developed and practiced as a form of cultural learning. Here, computational models can be used to leverage data from experiments to simulate and predict the spread and maintenance of emotion knowledge, as has been done for language (e.g., Kirby et al., 2008). To ground these models, future research can look to work in discursive psychology and sociolinguistics to examine how emotional knowledge is represented in interactions (e.g., Edwards, 1999; Parkinson, 1996). Language provides a means to efficiently transmit and build knowledge about emotion (Bamberg, 1997; Gelman & Roberts, 2017), and plays a role in both typical (e.g., Nook et al., 2017, 2019) and atypical (e.g., Hobson et al., 2019) emotional development (see also Hoemann et al., 2019). Culture likewise shapes expertise in emotion by provisioning individuals with a set of relevant concepts (Gendron et al., 2020), including values for which emotions should be experienced (Tamir et al., 2016; Tsai et al., 2006) and which aspects should be emphasized (Dere et al., 2012; Dzokoto, 2010). Research has also found that individuals’ fit with the prevailing emotional patterns of their cultural context is associated with well-being and sense of belonging (e.g., De Leersnyder et al., 2011, 2014). A better understanding of these interpersonal processes is therefore critical to charting the development of expertise in emotion and understanding how it translates into observable skills.

Another way to expand research on expertise in emotion is to measure it within as well as between persons. Momentary estimates of the mental representation of emotional experience can capture fluctuations over time as individuals navigate context-specific goals. Such estimates have recently been introduced for emotional awareness (Versluis et al., 2021) and emotional granularity (Erbas et al., 2021; see also Grossmann et al., 2016; Tomko et al., 2015). Another possibility is to use network analysis to model temporal dynamics of expertise in emotion (e.g., Howe et al., 2020; Lange et al., 2020; Pe et al., 2015). Network analysis allows for multiple properties of the overall construct of interest to be characterized, while simultaneously modeling the relationships between features or facets, and quantifying variation in all of these over time (Epskamp et al., 2018). Future research can integrate within-person measures with ambulatory peripheral physiological monitoring (e.g., Hoemann et al., 2021; Wilhelm & Grossman, 2010) and other forms of in-the-world recording and observation (e.g., Mehl et al., 2012) to examine how the biology and behavior of expertise predict one another.

Finally, and perhaps most critically, research is needed that can link specific features of expertise with aspects of mental and physical health. All the constructs we reviewed are associated with real-world outcomes in one or more domains. However, it is premature to recommend a particular path forward for clinical applications because we do not yet know how constructs and mechanisms link together to support outcomes. Taking an emergent variable approach, one way to assess the contribution of different constructs is to adopt ways of modeling that do not require strong correlations between them. For example, clustering analyses could be used to look for differences in how measured constructs—and the features of expertise they represent—group together, via linear or nonlinear relationships, within or across individuals (e.g., Hoemann et al., 2020; Wormwood et al., 2019). Such analyses would allow future research to examine which clusters of constructs or features have the most predictive utility for outcomes of interest, for which individuals, and in which contexts. Ultimately, the approach we have outlined in this discussion positions future research to not only apply state-of-the-art measurement and analytical techniques to the study of expertise in emotion, but also to integrate and interpret these findings within a unified conceptual framework based on features of expertise. These empirical and theoretical advancements place the science of emotion on a better footing to systematically answer questions about expertise in emotion and their relationship to health and well-being in everyday life.

Supplementary Material

Supplemental Materials

Public Significance Statement.

This scoping review clarifies the relationship between constructs for the mental representation of emotional experience, which are used in both scientific inquiry and clinical practice. The introduction of a unifying framework for expertise in emotion provides a roadmap for future research with maximum impact.

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful to Maria Gendron and Judy Hall for their input on review design, to Chloe David for her assistance with abstract review, and to Erik Nook and Batja Mesquita for their feedback on earlier versions of the manuscript.

This work was performed at Northeastern University in partial fulfillment of a Doctor of Philosophy Degree in Psychology awarded to Katie Hoemann. Portions of this work were presented at the 2018 annual meeting of the Society for Affective Science. This work was supported by funding from the National Cancer Institute (U01CA193632), the National Institute of Mental Health (R01MH113234, R01MH109464), the National Institute of Aging (R56AG058745), and the National Science Foundation (BCS1947972) to Lisa Feldman Barrett, the U.S. Army Research Institute for the Behavioral and Social Sciences (W911NF-16-1-019) to Karen S. Quigley, and the National Heart, Lung, and Blood Institute (1F31HL140943-01) and a P.E.O. International Scholar Award to Katie Hoemann. The views, opinions, and/or findings contained in this paper are those of the authors and shall not be construed as an official Department of the Army position, policy, or decision, unless so designated by other documents.

Footnotes

A database of all publications reviewed in this article, as well as data underlying network visualizations, are available via a repository hosted by the Center for Open Science at https://osf.io/a6vzk/.

1

The idea of individual differences in social intelligence also originated around the beginning of the 20th century (e.g., Thorndike, 1920). This idea later came to be regarded as the foundation of emotional intelligence (e.g., Bar-On, 2000; Mayer & Salovey, 1993; see Landy, 2005, 2006, for review and discussion).

2

From now on, we refer to constructs (e.g., emotional awareness, emotional granularity) as awareness, granularity, etc. for ease of reading.

3

The phrase “affect [CONSTRUCT]” (e.g., “affect awareness”) often did not include any publications relevant to the present research because “affect” can be used as a verb. If a given search yielded no relevant publications (as determined by visual inspection by the first author), the search results were excluded from further review.

4

Because our primary variables of interest were free-text responses, we were not able to compute meaningful measures of interrater reliability such as intraclass correlations or kappa coefficients.

5

To the authors’ knowledge, only two publications discuss emotional variability as the range, diversity, or context-specificity of experienced emotion. Barrett (2009) was excluded from the present review as it is a theory piece that discusses emotional experience more generally, rather than an individual difference construct. Waugh et al. (2011) is ostensibly about emotional flexibility (which those authors relate to variation in both the type and intensity of emotion), but was excluded because flexibility is measured using only biological measures (i.e., electromyography [EMG]).

6

We made the a priori decision to exclude constructs that exclusively dealt with the perception, expression, and regulation of emotion. However, some constructs that met our criteria included perception, expression, or regulation as facets (e.g., the model of intelligence proposed by Mayer & Salovey, 1997). We incorporated these facets into our network to avoid discarding data from the publications in our review.

7

We also included “emotional heterogeneity” (e.g., Charles, 2005) in our list of search terms. None of the resulting publications were selected for inclusion because they described the construct strictly within a lifespan development context. However, based on the definition of heterogeneity as the simultaneous experience of multiple negative emotions, we would have also considered it a type of (low) granularity. See Table S1 for further details.

8

Interested readers are referred to the following reviews: for alexithymia (Bar-On, 2004; Bermond et al., 2015; Sifneos, 1996); for intelligence (Akerjordet & Severinsson, 2007; Conte, 2005; Siegling et al., 2015).

9

There is precedent for interpreting alexithymia as the conceptual inverse of emotion-related abilities (e.g., Lumley et al., 2005), and the term “lexithymics” has also been used to describe emotionally intelligent individuals (Moormann et al., 2008). However, the most common measure of alexithymia—the TAS-20 (Bagby et al., 1994)—only assesses the presence or absence of impairment, not the degree of skill at the other end of the continuum. In this sense, alexithymia, as measured, does not capture expertise.

10

Outside of Mayer and colleagues’ “ability model” of intelligence, there were also several competing “trait” or “mixed model” accounts (e.g., Bar-On, 1997; Petrides et al., 2007).

11

The need for normative criteria for assessing adaptive responses (i.e., behaviors) is specifically a problem for ability models of intelligence and competence. Trait or mixed-model accounts of intelligence and competence do not suffer these same criticisms because they are predominantly assessed using global self-report measures (e.g., Bar-On, 1997; Petrides et al., 2007), which capture individuals’ beliefs about themselves rather than (directly measuring) abilities or skills. For further reading on the debate between ability and mixed or trait models of intelligence with regard to measurement, the interested reader is referred to Averill (2004), Conte (2005), Petrides (2010), and Roberts et al. (2010).

12

Involuntary attention to emotion is itself negatively associated with other facets of awareness, clarity, and overall expertise (Boden & Thompson, 2015; Huang et al., 2013; Mankus et al., 2016).

References

  1. Aaron RV, Snodgress MA, Blain SD, & Park S (2018). Affect labeling and other aspects of emotional experiences in relation to alexithymia following standardized emotion inductions. Psychiatry Research, 262, 115–123. 10.1016/j.psychres.2018.02.014 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  2. Akerjordet K, & Severinsson E (2007). Emotional intelligence: A review of the literature with specific focus on empirical and epistemological perspectives. Journal of Clinical Nursing, 16(8), 1405–1416. 10.1111/j.1365-2702.2006.01749.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Alexander F (1950). Psychosomatic medicine: Its principles and applications. W.W. Norton. [Google Scholar]
  4. Arksey H, & O’Malley L (2005). Scoping studies: Towards a methodological framework. International Journal of Social Research Methodology, 8(1), 19–32. 10.1080/1364557032000119616 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  5. Arnett JJ (2009). The neglected 95%, a challenge to psychology’s philosophy of science. American Psychologist, 64(6), 571–574. 10.1037/a0016723 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  6. Averill JR (1980). A constructivist view of emotion. In Plutchik R & Kellerman H (Eds.), Emotion: Vol. 1. Theory, research, and experience (pp. 305–340). Academic Press. 10.1016/B978-0-12-558701-3.50018-1 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  7. Averill JR (1999). Individual differences in emotional creativity: Structure and correlates. Journal of Personality, 67(2), 331–371. 10.1111/1467-6494.00058 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  8. Averill JR (2004). A tale of two snarks: Emotional intelligence and emotional creativity compared. Psychological Inquiry, 15(3), 228–233. 10.1207/s15327965pli1503_03 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  9. Averill JR, & Thomas-Knowles C (1991). Emotional creativity. In Strongman KT (Ed.), International review of studies on emotion (Vol. 1, pp. 269–299). Wiley. [Google Scholar]
  10. Bagby RM, Parker JDA, & Taylor GJ (1994). The twenty-item Toronto Alexithymia Scale—I. Item selection and cross-validation of the factor structure. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 38(1), 23–32. 10.1016/0022-3999(94)90005-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Bagby RM, Parker JDA, & Taylor GJ (2020). Twenty-five years with the 20-item Toronto Alexithymia Scale. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 131, Article 109940. 10.1016/j.jpsychores.2020.109940 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  12. Bagby RM, Taylor GJ, Parker JDA, & Dickens SE (2006). The development of the Toronto Structured Interview for Alexithymia: Item selection, factor structure, reliability and concurrent validity. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 75(1), 25–39. 10.1159/000089224 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Bamberg M (1997). Language, concepts and emotions: The role of language in the construction of emotions. Language Sciences, 19(4), 309–340. 10.1016/S0388-0001(97)00004-1 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  14. Bar-On R (1997). The Bar-On Emotional Quotient-Inventory (EQ-i®). Multi-Health Systems, Inc. [Google Scholar]
  15. Bar-On R (2000). Emotional and social intelligence: Insights from the Emotional Quotient Inventory. In Bar-On R & Parker JDA (Eds.), The handbook of emotional intelligence: Theory, development, assessment, and application at home, school, and in the workplace (pp. 363–388). Jossey-Bass. [Google Scholar]
  16. Bar-On R (2004). The Bar-On Emotional Quotient Inventory (EQ-i): Rationale, description and summary of psychometric properties. In Geher G (Ed.), Measuring emotional intelligence: Common ground and controversy (pp. 115–145). Nova Science Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  17. Barrett LF (1997). The relationships among momentary emotion experiences, personality descriptions, and retrospective ratings of emotion. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 23(10), 1100–1110. 10.1177/01461672972310010 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  18. Barrett LF (2000, February). Modeling emotion as an emergent phenomenon: A causal indicator analysis [Conference session]. Annual Meeting of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Nashville, Tennessee, United States. [Google Scholar]
  19. Barrett LF (2004). Feelings or words? Understanding the content in self-report ratings of experienced emotion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87(2), 266–281. 10.1037/0022-3514.87.2.266 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Barrett LF (2009). Variety is the spice of life: A psychological construction approach to understanding variability in emotion. Cognition and Emotion, 23(7), 1284–1306. 10.1080/02699930902985894 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  21. Barrett LF (2011). Bridging token identity theory and supervenience theory through psychological construction. Psychological Inquiry, 22(2), 115–127. 10.1080/1047840X.2011.555216 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Barrett LF (2016). Navigating the science of emotion. In Meisselman HL (Ed.), Emotion measurement (pp. 31–63). Elsevier. 10.1016/B978-0-08-100508-8.00002-3 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  23. Barrett LF (2017a). How emotions are made: The secret life of the brain. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. [Google Scholar]
  24. Barrett LF (2017b). The theory of constructed emotion: An active inference account of interoception and categorization. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(11), 1–23. 10.1093/scan/nsx060 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Barrett LF, & Barrett DJ (2001). An introduction to computerized experience sampling in psychology. Social Science Computer Review, 19(2), 175–185. 10.1177/089443930101900204 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  26. Barrett LF, Gross J, Christensen TC, & Benvenuto M (2001). Knowing what you’re feeling and knowing what to do about it: Mapping the relation between emotion differentiation and emotion regulation. Cognition and Emotion, 15(6), 713–724. 10.1080/02699930143000239 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  27. Barrett LF, Mesquita B, Ochsner KN, & Gross JJ (2007). The experience of emotion. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 373–403. 10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085709 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  28. Bastian M, Heymann S, & Jacomy M (2009). Gephi: An open source software for exploring and manipulating networks [Conference session]. Third International AAAI Conference on Weblogs and Social Media, San Jose, California, United States. [Google Scholar]
  29. Beauchaine TP (2015). Respiratory sinus arrhythmia: A transdiagnostic biomarker of emotion dysregulation and psychopathology. Current Opinion in Psychology, 3, 43–47. 10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.01.017 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Bédard J, & Chi MTH (1992). Expertise. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 1(4), 135–139. 10.1111/1467-8721.ep10769799 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  31. Bermond B, & Oosterveld P (1994). Bermond-Vorst Alexithymia Questionnaire: Construction, reliability, validity and uni-dimensionality. University of Amsterdam [Google Scholar]
  32. Bermond B, Oosterveld P, & Vorst HCM (2015). Measures of alexithymia. In Boyle GJ, Saklofske DH, & Matthews G (Eds.), Measures of personality and social psychological constructs (pp. 227–256). Academic Press. 10.1016/B978-0-12-386915-9.00009-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  33. Bermond B, Vorst HCM, Vingerhoets AJ, & Gerritsen W (1999). The Amsterdam Alexithymia Scale: Its psychometric values and correlations with other personality traits. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 68(5), 241–251. 10.1159/000012340 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Boden MT, & Berenbaum H (2011). What you are feeling and why: Two distinct types of emotional clarity. Personality and Individual Differences, 51(5), 652–656. 10.1016/j.paid.2011.06.009 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  35. Boden MT, & Thompson RJ (2015). Facets of emotional awareness and associations with emotion regulation and depression. Emotion, 15(3), 399–410. 10.1037/emo0000057 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Boden MT, & Thompson RJ (2017). Meta-analysis of the association between emotional clarity and attention to emotions. Emotion Review, 9(1), 79–85. 10.1177/1754073915610640 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  37. Boiger M, Ceulemans E, De Leersnyder J, Uchida Y, Norasakkunkit V, & Mesquita B (2018). Beyond essentialism: Cultural differences in emotions revisited. Emotion, 18(8), 1142–1162. 10.1037/emo0000390 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Bollen K, & Lennox R (1991). Conventional wisdom on measurement: A structural equation perspective. Psychological Bulletin, 110(2), 305–314. 10.1037/0033-2909.110.2.305 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  39. Borsboom D, Mellenbergh GJ, & van Heerden J (2003). The theoretical status of latent variables. Psychological Review, 110(2), 203–219. 10.1037/0033-295X.110.2.203 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. Boyatzis RE, Goleman D, & Rhee KS (2000). Clustering competence in emotional intelligence: Insights from the Emotional Competence Inventory. In Bar-On R & Parker JDA (Eds.), The handbook of emotional intelligence: Theory, development, assessment, and application at home, school, and in the workplace (pp. 343–362). Jossey-Bass. [Google Scholar]
  41. Brasseur S, Grégoire J, Bourdu R, & Mikolajczak M (2013). The Profile of Emotional Competence (PEC): Development and validation of a self-reported measure that fits dimensions of emotional competence theory. PLOS ONE, 8(5), Article e62635. 10.1371/journal.pone.0062635 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  42. Brooks JA, Chikazoe J, Sadato N, & Freeman JB (2019). The neural representation of facial-emotion categories reflects conceptual structure. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 116(32), 15861–15870. 10.1073/pnas.1816408116 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  43. Bukach CM, Gauthier I, & Tarr MJ (2006). Beyond faces and modularity: The power of an expertise framework. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(4), 159–166. 10.1016/j.tics.2006.02.004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Burman JT (2018). Through the looking-glass: PsycINFO as an historical archive of trends in psychology. History of Psychology, 21(4), 302–333. 10.1037/hop0000082 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Burns B, & Shepp BE (1988). Dimensional interactions and the structure of psychological space: The representation of hue, saturation, and brightness. Perception & Psychophysics, 43(5), 494–507. 10.3758/BF03207885 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  46. Cameron CD, Payne BK, & Doris JM (2013). Morality in high definition: Emotion differentiation calibrates the influence of incidental disgust on moral judgments. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49(4), 719–725. 10.1016/j.jesp.2013.02.014 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  47. Carstensen LL, Pasupathi M, Mayr U, & Nesselroade JR (2000). Emotional experience in everyday life across the adult life span. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(4), 644–655. 10.1037/0022-3514.79.4.644 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  48. Charles ST (2005). Viewing injustice: Greater emotion heterogeneity with age. Psychology and Aging, 20(1), 159–164. 10.1037/0882-7974.20.1.159 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Cherniss C (2010). Emotional intelligence: Toward clarification of a concept. Industrial and Organizational Psychology: Perspectives on Science and Practice, 3(2), 110–126. 10.1111/j.1754-9434.2010.01231.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  50. Clore GL, & Ortony A (2000). Cognition in emotion: Always, sometimes, or never. In Lane RD & Nadel L (Eds.), Cognitive neuroscience of emotion (pp. 24–61). Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  51. Clore GL, & Ortony A (2008). Appraisal theories: How cognition shapes affect into emotion. In Lewis M, Haviland-Jones JM, & Barrett LF (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (3rd ed., pp. 628–642). Guilford Press. [Google Scholar]
  52. Coan JA (2010). Emergent ghosts of the emotion machine. Emotion Review, 2(3), 274–285. 10.1177/1754073910361978 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  53. Coffey E, Berenbaum H, & Kerns J (2003). Brief report. Cognition and Emotion, 17(4), 671–679. 10.1080/02699930302304 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  54. Connor KM, & Davidson JR (2003). Development of a new resilience scale: The Connor-Davidson Resilience Scale (CD-RISC). Depression and Anxiety, 18(2), 76–82. 10.1002/da.10113 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Conte JM (2005). A review and critique of emotional intelligence measures. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 26(4), 433–440. 10.1002/job.319 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  56. Cooper RK, & Sawaf A (1997). Executive EQ: Emotional intelligence in leadership and organizations (Vol. 4). Grosset/Putnam. [Google Scholar]
  57. Daudt HM, van Mossel C, & Scott SJ (2013). Enhancing the scoping study methodology: A large, inter-professional team’s experience with Arksey and O’Malley’s framework. BMC Medical Research Methodology, 13(1), Article 48. 10.1186/1471-2288-13-48 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. David S (2016). Emotional agility: Get unstuck, embrace change, and thrive in work and life. Penguin. [Google Scholar]
  59. Davidson RJ (1992). Emotion and affective style: Hemispheric substrates. Psychological Science, 3(1), 39–43. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.1992.tb00254.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  60. Davidson RJ (1998). Affective style and affective disorders: Perspectives from affective neuroscience. Cognition and Emotion, 12(3), 307–330. 10.1080/026999398379628 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  61. Davidson RJ (2000). Affective style, psychopathology, and resilience: Brain mechanisms and plasticity. American Psychologist, 55(11), 1196–1214. 10.1037/0003-066X.55.11.1196 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  62. De Leersnyder J, Mesquita B, Kim H, Eom K, & Choi H (2014). Emotional fit with culture: A predictor of individual differences in relational well-being. Emotion, 14(2), 241–245. 10.1037/a0035296 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  63. De Leersnyder J, Mesquita B, & Kim HS (2011). Where do my emotions belong? A study of immigrants’ emotional acculturation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 37(4), 451–463. 10.1177/0146167211399103 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  64. Dere J, Falk CF, & Ryder AG (2012). Unpacking cultural differences in alexithymia: The role of cultural values among Euro-Canadian and Chinese-Canadian students. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 43(8), 1297–1312. 10.1177/0022022111430254 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  65. Dzokoto V (2010). Different ways of feeling: Emotion and somatic awareness in Ghanaians and Euro-Americans. Journal of Social, Evolutionary, & Cultural Psychology, 4(2), 68–78. 10.1037/h0099299 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  66. Edwards D (1999). Emotion discourse. Culture and Psychology, 5(3), 271–291. 10.1177/1354067X9953001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  67. Ekman P (1972). Universals and cultural differences in facial expressions of emotion (Cole J, Ed., Vol. 19, pp. 207–282). University of Nebraska Press. [Google Scholar]
  68. Elfenbein HA, & MacCann C (2017). A closer look at ability emotional intelligence (EI): What are its component parts, and how do they relate to each other? Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 11(7), Article e12324. 10.1111/spc3.12324 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  69. Epskamp S, Borsboom D, & Fried EI (2018). Estimating psychological networks and their accuracy: A tutorial paper. Behavior Research Methods, 50(1), 195–212. 10.3758/s13428-017-0862-1 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  70. Erbas Y, Ceulemans E, Kalokerinos EK, Houben M, Koval P, Pe ML, & Kuppens P (2018). Why I don’t always know what I’m feeling: The role of stress in within-person fluctuations in emotion differentiation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 115(2), 179–191. 10.1037/pspa0000126 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Erbas Y, Kalokerinos E, Kuppens P, van Halem S, & Ceulemans E (2021). Momentary Emotion Differentiation: The derivation and validation of a framework to study within-person fluctuations in emotion differentiation. Assessment. Adavance online publication. 10.1177/1073191121990089 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Ericsson KA (2006). The influence of experience and deliberate practice on the development of superior expert performance. In Ericsson KA, Charness N, Feltovich PJ & Hoffman RR (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance (Vol. 38, pp. 685–705). Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  73. Ericsson KA (2007). Deliberate practice and the modifiability of body and mind: Toward a science of the structure and acquisition of expert and elite performance. International Journal of Sport Psychology, 38(1), 4–34. [Google Scholar]
  74. Ericsson KA (2014). Why expert performance is special and cannot be extrapolated from studies of performance in the general population: A response to criticisms. Intelligence, 45, 81–103. 10.1016/j.intell.2013.12.001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  75. Ericsson KA, & Charness N (1994). Expert performance: Its structure and acquisition. American Psychologist, 49(8), 725–747. 10.1037/0003-066X.49.8.725 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  76. Ericsson KA, Hoffman RR, & Kozbelt A (2018). The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/9781316480748 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  77. Ericsson KA, & Lehmann AC (1996). Expert and exceptional performance: Evidence of maximal adaptation to task constraints. Annual Review of Psychology, 47(1), 273–305. 10.1146/annurev.psych.47.1.273 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  78. Ericsson KA, & Smith J (1991). Toward a general theory of expertise: Prospects and limits. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  79. Ericsson KA, & Ward P (2007). Capturing the naturally occurring superior performance of experts in the laboratory: Toward a science of expert and exceptional performance. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 16(6), 346–350. 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00533.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  80. Ford A (2016, December 16). How artists use color. Head for Art. http://headforart.com/2016/12/16/how-artists-use-colour/
  81. Freedman MB, & Sweet BS (1954). Some specific features of group psychotherapy and their implications for selection of patients. International Journal of Group Psychotherapy, 4(4), 355–368. 10.1080/00207284.1954.11508548 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  82. Freud S (1891). On aphasia: A critical study. International Universities Press. [Google Scholar]
  83. Freud S (1895). Project for a scientific psychology. International Universities Press. [Google Scholar]
  84. Frijda NH (1986). The emotions. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  85. Fu F, Chow A, Li J, & Cong Z (2018). Emotional flexibility: Development and application of a scale in adolescent earthquake survivors. Psychological Trauma: Theory, Research, Practice, and Policy, 10(2), 246–252. 10.1037/tra0000278 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  86. Fuchs GL, Kumar VK, & Porter J (2007). Emotional creativity, alexithymia, and styles of creativity. Creativity Research Journal, 19(2–3), 233–245. 10.1080/10400410701397313 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  87. Geisler FC, Vennewald N, Kubiak T, & Weber H (2010). The impact of heart rate variability on subjective well-being is mediated by emotion regulation. Personality and Individual Differences, 49(7), 723–728. 10.1016/j.paid.2010.06.015 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  88. Gelman SA, & Roberts SO (2017). How language shapes the cultural inheritance of categories. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 114(30), 7900–7907. 10.1073/pnas.1621073114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  89. Gendron M, Crivelli C, & Barrett LF (2018). Universality reconsidered: Diversity in making meaning of facial expressions. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 27(4), 211–219. 10.1177/0963721417746794 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  90. Gendron M, Mesquita B, & Barrett LF (2020). The brain as a cultural artifact: Concepts, actions, and experiences within the human affective niche. In Kirmayer LJ, Worthman CM, Kitayama S, Lemelson R, & Cummings C (Eds.), Culture, mind, and brain: Emerging concepts, models, and applications. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/9781108695374.010 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  91. Gohm CL, & Clore GL (2000). Individual differences in emotional experience: Mapping available scales to processes. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26(6), 679–697. 10.1177/0146167200268004 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  92. Gohm CL, & Clore GL (2002). Four latent traits of emotional experience and their involvement in well-being, coping, and attributional style. Cognition and Emotion, 16(4), 495–518. 10.1080/02699930143000374 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  93. Goldstone R (1994). Influences of categorization on perceptual discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 123(2), 178–200. 10.1037/0096-3445.123.2.178 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  94. Goldstone RL (1995). Effects of categorization on color perception. Psychological Science, 6(5), 298–304. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.1995.tb00514.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  95. Goleman D (1995). Emotional intelligence. Bantam Books. [Google Scholar]
  96. Grandey AA (2000). Emotion regulation in the workplace: A new way to conceptualize emotional labor. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 5(1), 95–110. 10.1037/1076-8998.5.1.95 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  97. Gross JJ, & Barrett LF (2011). Emotion generation and emotion regulation: One or two depends on your point of view. Emotion Review, 3(1), 8–16. 10.1177/1754073910380974 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  98. Grossmann I, Huynh AC, & Ellsworth PC (2016). Emotional complexity: Clarifying definitions and cultural correlates. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 111(6), 895–916. 10.1037/pspp0000084 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  99. Grühn D, Lumley MA, Diehl M, & Labouvie-Vief G (2013). Time-based indicators of emotional complexity: Interrelations and correlates. Emotion, 13(2), 226–237. 10.1037/a0030363 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  100. Halberstadt AG, Denham SA, & Dunsmore JC (2001). Affective social competence. Social Development, 10(1), 79–119. 10.1111/1467-9507.00150 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  101. Henry WE, & Shlien JM (1958). Affective complexity and psychotherapy: Some comparisons of time-limited and unlimited treatment. Journal of Projective Techniques, 22, 153–162. 10.1080/08853126.1958.10380837 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  102. Hobson H, Brewer R, Catmur C, & Bird G (2019). The role of language in alexithymia: Moving towards a multiroute model of alexithymia. Emotion Review, 11(3), 247–261. 10.1177/1754073919838528 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  103. Hoemann K, Khan Z, Feldman MJ, Nielson C, Devlin M, Dy J, Barrett LF, Wormwood JB, & Quigley KS (2020). Context-aware experience sampling reveals the scale of variation in affective experience. Scientific Reports, 10, Article 12459. 10.1038/s41598-020-69180-y [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  104. Hoemann K, Khan Z, Kamona N, Dy J, Barrett LF, & Quigley KS (2021). Investigating the relationship between emotional granularity and cardiorespiratory physiological activity in daily life. Psychophysiology, 58, Article e13818. 10.1111/psyp.13818 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  105. Hoemann K, Xu F, & Barrett LF (2019). Emotion words, emotion concepts, and emotional development in children: A constructionist hypothesis. Developmental Psychology, 55(9), 1830–1849. 10.1037/dev0000686 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  106. Howe E, Bosley HG, & Fisher AJ (2020). Idiographic network analysis of discrete mood states prior to treatment. Counselling and Psychotherapy Research, 20(3), 470–478 10.1002/capr.12295 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  107. Hu Y (2005). Efficient, high-quality force-directed graph drawing. The Mathematica Journal, 10(1), 37–71. [Google Scholar]
  108. Huang S, Berenbaum H, & Chow PI (2013). Distinguishing voluntary from involuntary attention to emotion. Personality and Individual Differences, 54(8), 894–898. 10.1016/j.paid.2012.12.025 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  109. Ivcevic Z, Bazhydai M, Hoffmann JD, & Brackett MA (2017). Creativity in the domain of emotions. In Kaufman JC, Glăveanu VP, Baer J, Kaufman JC, Glăveanu VP, & Baer J (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of creativity across domains (pp. 525–548). Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/9781316274385.029 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  110. Ivcevic Z, Brackett MA, & Mayer JD (2007). Emotional intelligence and emotional creativity. Journal of Personality, 75(2), 199–236. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.2007.00437.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  111. Izard CE (1993). Four systems for emotion activation: Cognitive and noncognitive processes. Psychological Review, 100(1), 68–90. 10.1037/0033-295X.100.1.68 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  112. Izard CE (2009). Emotion theory and research: Highlights, unanswered questions, and emerging issues. Annual Review of Psychology, 60, 1–25. 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163539 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  113. Izard CE, Woodburn EM, Finlon KJ, Krauthamer-Ewing ES, Grossman SR, & Seidenfeld A (2011). Emotion knowledge, emotion utilization, and emotion regulation. Emotion Review, 3(1), 44–52. 10.1177/1754073910380972 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  114. James W (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, os-IX(34), 188–205. 10.1093/mind/os-IX.34.188 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  115. Joseph DL, & Newman DA (2010). Emotional intelligence: An integrative meta-analysis and cascading model. Journal of Applied Psychology, 95(1), 54–78. 10.1037/a0017286 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  116. Kagan N, & Schneider J (1987). Toward the measurement of affective sensitivity. Journal of Counseling and Development, 65(9), 459–464. 10.1002/j.1556-6676.1987.tb00755.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  117. Kang S-M, & Shaver PR (2004). Individual differences in emotional complexity: Their psychological implications. Journal of Personality, 72(4), 687–726. 10.1111/j.0022-3506.2004.00277.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  118. Kashdan TB, Barrett LF, & McKnight PE (2015). Unpacking emotion differentiation: Transforming unpleasant experience by perceiving distinctions in negativity. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 24(1), 10–16. 10.1177/0963721414550708 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  119. Kastner M, Tricco AC, Soobiah C, Lillie E, Perrier L, Horsley T, Welch V, Cogo E, Antony J, & Straus SE (2012). What is the most appropriate knowledge synthesis method to conduct a review? Protocol for a scoping review. BMC Medical Research Methodology, 12(1), Article 114. 10.1186/1471-2288-12-114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  120. Kirby S, Cornish H, & Smith K (2008). Cumulative cultural evolution in the laboratory: An experimental approach to the origins of structure in human language. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 105(31), 10681–10686. 10.1073/pnas.0707835105 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  121. Kooiman CG, Spinhoven P, & Trijsburg RW (2002). The assessment of alexithymia: A critical review of the literature and a psychometric study of the Toronto Alexithymia Scale-20. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 53(6), 1083–1090. 10.1016/S0022-3999(02)00348-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  122. Krystal H (1979). Alexithymia and psychotherapy. American Journal of Psychotherapy, 33(1), 17–31. 10.1176/appi.psychotherapy.1979.33.1.17 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  123. Labouvie-Vief G, & Medler M (2002). Affect optimization and affect complexity: Modes and styles of regulation in adulthood. Psychology and Aging, 17(4), 571–588. 10.1037/0882-7974.17.4.571 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  124. Laland K (2017). Darwin’s unfinished symphony: How culture made the human mind. Princeton University Press. 10.1515/9781400884872 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  125. Lambie JA, & Marcel AJ (2002). Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: A theoretical framework. Psychological Review, 109(2), 219–259. 10.1037/0033-295X.109.2.219 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  126. Landy FJ (2005). Some historical and scientific issues related to research on emotional intelligence. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 26(4), 411–424. 10.1002/job.317 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  127. Landy FJ (2006). The long, frustrating, and fruitless search for social intelligence: A cautionary tale. In Murphy KR (Ed.), A critique of emotional intelligence: What are the problems and how can they be fixed? (pp. 81–123). Lawrence Erlbaum. [Google Scholar]
  128. Lane RD, Sechrest L, Reidel R, Weldon V, Kaszniak A, & Schwartz GE (1996). Impaired verbal and nonverbal emotion recognition in alexithymia. Psychosomatic Medicine, 58(3), 203–210. 10.1097/00006842-199605000-00002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  129. Lane RD, Quinlan DM, Schwartz GE, Walker PA, & Zeitlin SB (1990). The Levels of Emotional Awareness Scale: A cognitive-developmental measure of emotion. Journal of Personality Assessment, 55(1–2), 124–134. 10.1080/00223891.1990.9674052 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  130. Lane RD, & Schwartz GE (1987). Levels of emotional awareness: A cognitive-developmental theory and its application to psychopathology. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 144(2), 133–143. 10.1176/ajp.144.2.133 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  131. Lane RD, & Schwartz GE (1992). Levels of emotional awareness: Implications for psychotherapeutic integration. Journal of Psychotherapy Integration, 2(1), 1–18. 10.1037/h0101238 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  132. Lane RD, Sechrest L, Riedel R, Shapiro DE, & Kaszniak AW (2000). Pervasive emotion recognition deficit common to alexithymia and the repressive coping style. Psychosomatic Medicine, 62(4), 492–501. 10.1097/00006842-200007000-00007 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  133. Lane RD, Weihs KL, Herring A, Hishaw A, & Smith R (2015). Affective agnosia: Expansion of the alexithymia construct and a new opportunity to integrate and extend Freud’s legacy. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 55, 594–611. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2015.06.007 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  134. Lange J, Dalege J, Borsboom D, van Kleef GA, & Fischer AH (2020). Toward an integrative psychometric model of emotions. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 15(2), 444–468. 10.1177/1745691619895057 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  135. Larsen RJ, & Cutler SE (1996). The complexity of individual emotional lives: A within-subject analysis of affect structure. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 15(2), 206–230. 10.1521/jscp.1996.15.2.206 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  136. Larsen RJ, & Diener E (1987). Affect intensity as an individual difference characteristic: A review. Journal of Research in Personality, 21(1), 1–39. 10.1016/0092-6566(87)90023-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  137. Law KS, Wong CS, & Song LJ (2004). The construct and criterion validity of emotional intelligence and its potential utility for management studies. Journal of Applied Psychology, 89(3), 483–496. 10.1037/0021-9010.89.3.483 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  138. Lazarus RS (1991). Cognition and motivation in emotion. American Psychologist, 46(4), 352–367. 10.1037/0003-066X.46.4.352 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  139. Lee JY, Lindquist KA, & Nam CS (2017). Emotional granularity effects on event-related brain potentials during affective picture processing. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 11, Article 133. 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00133 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  140. Lesser IM (1981). A review of the alexithymia concept. Psychosomatic Medicine, 43(6), 531–543. 10.1097/00006842-198112000-00009 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  141. Liberati A, Altman DG, Tetzlaff J, Mulrow C, Gøtzsche PC, Ioannidis JP, Clarke M, Devereaux PJ, Kleijnen J, & Moher D (2009). The PRISMA statement for reporting systematic reviews and meta-analyses of studies that evaluate health care interventions: Explanation and elaboration. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 62(10), e1–e34. 10.1016/j.jclinepi.2009.06.006 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. Lindquist KA, & Barrett LF (2008). Emotional complexity. In Lewis M, Haviland-Jones JM, & Barrett LF (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (3rd ed., pp. 513–530). Guilford Press. [Google Scholar]
  143. Lischetzke T, & Eid M (2017). The functionality of emotional clarity: A process-oriented approach to understanding the relation between emotional clarity and well-being. In Robinson MD, Eid M, Robinson MD, & Eid M (Eds.), The happy mind: Cognitive contributions to well-being (pp. 371–388). Springer. 10.1007/978-3-319-58763-9_20 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  144. Livingstone HA, & Day AL (2005). Comparing the construct and criterion-related validity of ability-based and mixed-model measures of emotional intelligence. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 65(5), 757–779. 10.1177/0013164405275663 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  145. Lumley MA, Gustavson BJ, Partridge RT, & Labouvie-Vief G (2005). Assessing alexithymia and related emotional ability constructs using multiple methods: Interrelationships among measures. Emotion, 5(3), 329–342. 10.1037/1528-3542.5.3.329 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  146. Lumley MA, Neely LC, & Burger AJ (2007). The assessment of alexithymia in medical settings: Implications for understanding and treating health problems. Journal of Personality Assessment, 89(3), 230–246. 10.1080/00223890701629698 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  147. MacLean PD (1949). Psychosomatic disease and the visceral brain; recent developments bearing on the Papez theory of emotion. Psychosomatic Medicine, 11(6), 338–353. 10.1097/00006842-194911000-00003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  148. Mankus AM, Boden MT, & Thompson RJ (2016). Sources of variation in emotional awareness: Age, gender, and socioeconomic status. Personality and Individual Differences, 89, 28–33. 10.1016/j.paid.2015.09.043 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  149. Maroti D, Lilliengren P, & Bileviciute-Ljungar I (2018). The relationship between alexithymia and emotional awareness: A meta-analytic review of the correlation between TAS-20 and LEAS. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, Article 453. 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00453 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  150. Marty P, & de M’Uzan M (1963). La pensée opératoire. Revue Française de Psychanalyse, 27, 1345–1356. 10.3917/rfps.006.0197 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  151. Maul A (2012). The validity of the Mayer-Salovey–Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT) as a measure of emotional intelligence. Emotion Review, 4(4), 394–402. 10.1177/1754073912445811 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  152. Mayer JD, Caruso DR, & Salovey P (2000). Selecting a measure of emotional intelligence: The case for ability scales. In Bar-On R & Parker JDA (Eds.), The handbook of emotional intelligence: Theory, development, assessment, and application at home, school, and in the workplace (pp. 320–342). Jossey-Bass. [Google Scholar]
  153. Mayer JD, Caruso DR, & Salovey P (2016). The ability model of emotional intelligence: Principles and updates. Emotion Review, 8(4), 290–300. 10.1177/1754073916639667 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  154. Mayer JD, Roberts RD, & Barsade SG (2008). Human abilities: Emotional intelligence. Annual Review of Psychology, 59(1), 507–536. 10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093646 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  155. Mayer JD, & Salovey P (1993). The intelligence of emotional intelligence. Intelligence, 17(4), 433–442. 10.1016/0160-2896(93)90010-3 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  156. Mayer JD, & Salovey P (1997). What is emotional intelligence? In Salovey P & Sluyter DJ (Eds.), Emotional development and emotional intelligence: Educational implications (pp. 3–34). Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
  157. Mayer JD, Salovey P, & Caruso DR (2002). Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT) item booklet. [Google Scholar]
  158. Mayer JD, Salovey P, Caruso DR, & Sitarenios G (2001). Emotional intelligence as a standard intelligence. Emotion, 1(3), 232–242. 10.1037/1528-3542.1.3.232 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  159. Mays N, Roberts E, & Popay J (2001). Synthesising research evidence. In Fulop N, Allen P, Clarke A, & Black N (Eds.), Studying the organisation and delivery of health services: Research methods (pp. 188–219). Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  160. McBrien A, Wild M, & Bachorowski JA (2020). Social-Emotional Expertise (SEE) Scale: Development and initial validation. Assessment, 27(8), 1718–1730. 10.1177/1073191118794866 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  161. Medin D, Ojalehto B, Marin A, & Bang M (2017). Systems of (non-)diversity. Nature Human Behaviour, 1, Article 0088. 10.1038/s41562-017-0088 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  162. Mehl MR, Robbins ML, & Deters FG (2012). Naturalistic observation of health-relevant social processes: The electronically activated recorder methodology in psychosomatics. Psychosomatic Medicine, 74(4), 410–417. 10.1097/PSY.0b013e3182545470 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  163. Meltzoff J, & Litwin D (1956). Affective control and Rorschach human movement responses. Journal of Consulting Psychology, 20(6), 463–465. 10.1037/h0044916 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  164. Mischel W (2008, December 1). The toothbrush problem. Observer, 21(11). https://www.psychologicalscience.org/observer/the-toothbrush-problem [Google Scholar]
  165. Moher D, Liberati A, Tetzlaff J, Altman DG, & the PRISMA Group. (2009). Preferred reporting items for systematic reviews and meta-analy-es: The PRISMA statement. PLOS Medicine, 6(7), Article e1000097. 10.1371/journal.pmed.1000097 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  166. Mongeon P, & Paul-Hus A (2016). The journal coverage of web of science and scopus: A comparative analysis. Scientometrics, 106(1), 213–228. 10.1007/s11192-015-1765-5 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  167. Moormann PP, Bermond B, Vorst HC, Bloemendaal AF, Teijn SM, & Rood L (2008). New avenues in alexithymia research: The creation of alexithymia types. In Nyklíček I, Vingerhoets A & Zeelenberg M (Eds.), Emotion regulation: Conceptual and clinical issues (pp. 27–42). Springer. 10.1007/978-0-387-29986-0_3 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  168. Moors A, Ellsworth PC, Scherer KR, & Frijda NH (2013). Appraisal theories of emotion: State of the art and future development. Emotion Review, 5(2), 119–124. 10.1177/1754073912468165 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  169. Nemiah JC, & Sifneos PE (1970). Affect and fantasy in patients with psychosomatic disorders. In Hill OW (Ed.), Modern trends in psychosomatic medicine (Vol. 2, pp. 26–34). Butterworths. [Google Scholar]
  170. Nemiah JC, Freyberger H, & Sifneos PE (1976). Alexithymia: A view of the psychosomatic process. In Hill OW (Ed.), Modern trends in psychosomatic medicine (pp. 430–439). Butterworths. [Google Scholar]
  171. Nemiah JC, & Sifneos PE (1970). Psychosomatic illness: A problem in communication. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 18(1), 154–160. 10.1159/000286074 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  172. Niedenthal PM, Rychlowska M, Zhao F, & Wood A (2019). Historical migration patterns shape contemporary cultures of emotion. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 14(4), 560–573. 10.1177/1745691619849591 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  173. Nook EC, Sasse SF, Lambert HK, McLaughlin KA, & Somerville LH (2017). Increasing verbal knowledge mediates development of multidimensional emotion representations. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(12), 881–889. 10.1038/s41562-017-0238-7 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  174. Nook EC, Stavish CM, Sasse SF, Lambert HK, Mair P, McLaughlin KA, & Somerville LH (2019). Charting the development of emotion comprehension and abstraction from childhood to adulthood using observer-rated and linguistic measures. Emotion. Advance online publication. 10.1037/emo0000609 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  175. Ong AD, Zautra AJ, & Finan PH (2017). Inter- and intra-individual variation in emotional complexity: Methodological considerations and theoretical implications. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 15, 22–26. 10.1016/j.cobeha.2017.05.018 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  176. Palmer BR, Gignac G, Ekermans G, & Stough C (2008). A comprehensive framework for emotional intelligence. In Emmerling RJ & Shanwal VK (Eds.), Emotional intelligence: Theoretical and cultural perspectives (pp. 17–38). Nova Science Publishers. [Google Scholar]
  177. Palmieri PA, Boden MT, & Berenbaum H (2009). Measuring clarity of and attention to emotions. Journal of Personality Assessment, 91(6), 560–567. 10.1080/00223890903228539 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  178. Parker JDA, Taylor GJ, & Bagby RM (2001). The relationship between emotional intelligence and alexithymia. Personality and Individual Differences, 30(1), 107–115. 10.1016/S0191-8869(00)00014-3 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  179. Parkinson B (1996). Emotions are social. British Journal of Psychology, 87(4), 663–683. 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1996.tb02615.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  180. Pe ML, Kircanski K, Thompson RJ, Bringmann LF, Tuerlinckx F, Mestdagh M, Mata J, Jaeggi SM, Buschkuehl M, Jonides J, Kuppens P, & Gotlib IH (2015). Emotion-network density in major depressive disorder. Clinical Psychological Science, 3(2), 292–300. 10.1177/2167702614540645 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  181. Petrides KV (2010). Trait emotional intelligence theory. Industrial and Organizational Psychology: Perspectives on Science and Practice, 3(2), 136–139. 10.1111/j.1754-9434.2010.01213.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  182. Petrides KV, Perez-Gonzalez JC, & Furnham A (2007). On the criterion and incremental validity of trait emotional intelligence. Cognition and Emotion, 21(1), 26–55. 10.1080/02699930601038912 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  183. Pham MT, Rajić A, Greig JD, Sargeant JM, Papadopoulos A, & McEwen SA (2014). A scoping review of scoping reviews: Advancing the approach and enhancing the consistency. Research Synthesis Methods, 5(4), 371–385. 10.1002/jrsm.1123 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  184. Piaget J (1937). La construction du réel chez l’enfant. Delachaux et Niestlé. [Google Scholar]
  185. Pistoia F, Conson M, Carolei A, Dema MG, Splendiani A, Curcio G, & Sacco S (2018). Post-earthquake distress and development of emotional expertise in young adults. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience, 12, Article 91. 10.3389/fnbeh.2018.00091 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  186. Plomin R, Shakeshaft NG, McMillan A, & Trzaskowski M (2014a). Nature, nurture, and expertise. Intelligence, 45, 46–59. 10.1016/j.intell.2013.06.008 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  187. Plomin R, Shakeshaft NG, McMillan A, & Trzaskowski M (2014b). Nature, nurture, and expertise: Response to Ericsson. Intelligence, 45, 115–117. 10.1016/j.intell.2014.01.003 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  188. Plutchik R (1980). A general psychoevolutionary theory of emotion. In Theories of emotion (pp. 3–33). Elsevier. 10.1016/B978-0-12-558701-3.50007-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  189. Pope C, Ziebland S, & Mays N (2000). Qualitative research in health care. Analysing qualitative data. BMJ, 320(7227), 114–116. 10.1136/bmj.320.7227.114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  190. Protter E (1997). Painters on painting. Courier Corporation. [Google Scholar]
  191. Quoidbach J, Gruber J, Mikolajczak M, Kogan A, Kotsou I, & Norton MI (2014). Emodiversity and the emotional ecosystem. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143(6), 2057–2066. 10.1037/a0038025 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  192. Rad MS, Martingano AJ, & Ginges J (2018). Toward a psychology ofHomo sapiens: Making psychological science more representative of the human population. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 115(45), 11401–11405. 10.1073/pnas.1721165115 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  193. Riggio R (1986). Assessment of basic social skills. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51(3), 649–660. 10.1037/0022-3514.51.3.649 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  194. Roberts RD, Matthews G, & Zeidner M (2010). Emotional intelligence: Muddling through theory and measurement. Industrial and Organizational Psychology: Perspectives on Science and Practice, 3(2), 140–144. 10.1111/j.1754-9434.2010.01214.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  195. Robinson MD, & Clore GL (2002). Belief and feeling: Evidence for an accessibility model of emotional self-report. Psychological Bulletin, 128(6), 934–960. 10.1037/0033-2909.128.6.934 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  196. Rosch E, Mervis CB, Gray WD, Johnson DM, & Boyes-Braem P (1976). Basic objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8(3), 382–439. 10.1016/0010-0285(76)90013-X [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  197. Roseman IJ (1991). Appraisal determinants of discrete emotions. Cognition and Emotion, 5(3), 161–200. 10.1080/02699939108411034 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  198. Rubin HR, Owens AJ, & Golden G (1998). Status report (1998): An investigation to determine whether the built environment affects patients’ medical outcomes. Center for Health Design. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  199. Ruesch J (1948). The infantile personality. The core problem of psychosomatic medicine. Psychosomatic Medicine, 10(3), 134–144. 10.1097/00006842-194805000-00002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  200. Russell JA (2003). Core affect and the psychological construction of emotion. Psychological Review, 110(1), 145–172. 10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.145 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  201. Salovey P, & Mayer JD (1990). Emotional intelligence. Imagination, Cognition and Personality, 9(3), 185–211. 10.2190/DUGG-P24E-52WK-6CDG [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  202. Salovey P, Mayer JD, & Caruso D (2002). The positive psychology of emotional intelligence. In Lopez SJ & Snyder CR (Eds.), Handbook of positive psychology (Vol. 159, p. 171). Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  203. Salovey P, Mayer JD, Goldman SL, Turvey C, & Palfai TP (1995). Emotional attention, clarity, and repair: Exploring emotional intelligence using the Trait Meta-Mood Scale. In Pennebaker JW (Ed.), Emotion, disclosure, and health (pp. 125–154). American Psychological Association. 10.1037/10182-006 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  204. Saul LJ (1947). Emotional maturity: The development and dynamics of personality. Lippincott. [Google Scholar]
  205. Scherer KR (1984). On the nature and function of emotion: A component process approach. In Scherer KR & Ekman P (Eds.), Approaches to emotion (pp. 293–317). Lawrence Erlbaum. [Google Scholar]
  206. Scherer KR (2007). Componential emotion theory can inform models of emotional competence. In Matthews G, Zeidner M, & Roberts RD (Eds.), The science of emotional intelligence: Knowns and unknowns (pp. 101–126). Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  207. Scherer KR (2009a). Emotions are emergent processes: They require a dynamic computational architecture. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 364(1535), 3459–3474. 10.1098/rstb.2009.0141 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  208. Scherer KR (2009b). The dynamic architecture of emotion: Evidence for the component process model. Cognition and Emotion, 23(7), 1307–1351. 10.1080/02699930902928969 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  209. Schimmack U, Oishi S, Diener E, & Suh E (2000). Facets of affective experiences: A framework for investigations of trait affect. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26(6), 655–668. 10.1177/0146167200268002 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  210. Schutte NS, Malouff JM, Hall LE, Haggerty DJ, Cooper JT, Golden CJ, & Dornheim L (1998). Development and validation of a measure of emotional intelligence. Personality and Individual Differences, 25(2), 167–177. 10.1016/S0191-8869(98)00001-4 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  211. Schyns PG (1991). A modular neural network model of concept acquisition. Cognitive Science, 15(4), 461–508. 10.1207/s15516709cog1504_1 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  212. Schyns PG, Goldstone RL, & Thibaut JP (1998). The development of features in object concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(1), 1–17. 10.1017/S0140525X98000107 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  213. Scollon CN, Kim-Prieto C, & Scollon CN (2003). Experience sampling: Promises and pitfalls, strengths and weaknesses. Journal of Happiness Studies, 4(1), 5–34. 10.1023/A:1023605205115 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  214. Siegling AB, Saklofske DH, & Petrides KV (2015). Measures of ability and trait emotional intelligence. In Boyle GJ, Matthews G, & Saklofske DH (Eds.), Measures of personality and social psychological constructs (pp. 381–414) Elsevier. 10.1016/B978-0-12-386915-9.00014-0 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  215. Sifneos PE (1972). Short-term psychotherapy and emotional crisis. Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  216. Sifneos PE (1973). The prevalence of ‘alexithymic’ characteristics in psychosomatic patients. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 22(2), 255–262. 10.1159/000286529 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  217. Sifneos PE (1996). Alexithymia: Past and present. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 153(Suppl. 7), 137–142. 10.1176/ajp.153.7.137 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  218. Smidt KE, & Suvak MK (2015). A brief, but nuanced, review of emotional granularity and emotion differentiation research. Current Opinion in Psychology, 3, 48–51. 10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.02.007 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  219. Smith R, Killgore WDS, Alkozei A, & Lane RD (2018). A neuro-cognitive process model of emotional intelligence. Biological Psychology, 139, 131–151. 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2018.10.012 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  220. Smith R, Killgore WDS, & Lane RD (2018). The structure of emotional experience and its relation to trait emotional awareness: A theoretical review. Emotion, 18(5), 670–692. 10.1037/emo0000376 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  221. Smith R, Thayer JF, Khalsa SS, & Lane RD (2017). The hierarchical basis of neurovisceral integration. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 75, 274–296. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2017.02.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  222. Sommers S (1981). Emotionality reconsidered: The role of cognition in emotional responsiveness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41(3), 553–561. 10.1037/0022-3514.41.3.553 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  223. Spearman C (1904a). “General intelligence” objectively determined and measured. The American Journal of Psychology, 15(2), 201–292. 10.2307/1412107 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  224. Spearman C (1904b). The proof and measurement of association between two things. The American Journal of Psychology, 15(1), 72–101. 10.2307/1412159 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  225. Steels L (1990). Components of expertise. AI Magazine, 11(2), 22–28. 10.1609/aimag.v11i2.831 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  226. Steiner C (1984). Emotional literacy. Transactional Analysis Journal, 14(3), 162–173. 10.1177/036215378401400301 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  227. Sternberg RJ (1984). Toward a triarchic theory of human intelligence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 7(2), 269–287. 10.1017/S0140525X00044629 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  228. Sternberg RJ (1998). Abilities are forms of developing expertise. Educational Researcher, 27(3), 11–20. 10.3102/0013189X027003011 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  229. Sternberg RJ, & Kagan J (1986). Intelligence applied: Understanding and increasing your intellectual skills. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. [Google Scholar]
  230. Sternberg RJ, Wagner R, Williams W, & Horvath J (1995). Testing common sense. American Psychologist, 50(11), 912–927. 10.1037/0003-066X.50.11.912 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  231. Subic-Wrana C, Bruder S, Thomas W, Lane RD, & Köhle K (2005). Emotional awareness deficits in inpatients of a psychosomatic ward: A comparison of two different measures of alexithymia. Psychosomatic Medicine, 67(3), 483–489. 10.1097/01.psy.0000160461.19239.13 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  232. Swinkels A, & Giuliano TA (1995). The measurement and conceptualization of mood awareness—Monitoring and labeling ones mood states. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 21(9), 934–949. 10.1177/0146167295219008 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  233. Tamir M, Schwartz SH, Cieciuch J, Riediger M, Torres C, Scollon C, Dzokoto V, Zhou X, & Vishkin A (2016). Desired emotions across cultures: A value-based account. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 111(1), 67–82. 10.1037/pspp0000072 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  234. Tanaka JW (1998). Parts, features, and expertise. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(1), 37–38. 10.1017/S0140525X98480105 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  235. Tanaka JW, & Taylor M (1991). Object categories and expertise: Is the basic level in the eye of the beholder? Cognitive Psychology, 23(3), 457–482. 10.1016/0010-0285(91)90016-H [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  236. Taylor GJ (1984). Alexithymia: Concept, measurement, and implications for treatment. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 141(6), 725–732. 10.1176/ajp.141.6.725 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  237. Taylor GJ (2000). Recent developments in alexithymia theory and research. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 45(2), 134–142. 10.1177/070674370004500203 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  238. Taylor GJ, Ryan D, & Bagby RM (1985). Toward the development of a new self-report alexithymia scale. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 44(4), 191–199. 10.1159/000287912 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  239. Tett RP, Fox KE, & Wang A (2005). Development and validation of a self-report measure of emotional intelligence as a multidimensional trait domain. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 31(7), 859–888. 10.1177/0146167204272860 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  240. Thayer JF, & Lane RD (2000). A model of neurovisceral integration in emotion regulation and dysregulation. Journal of Affective Disorders, 61(3), 201–216. 10.1016/S0165-0327(00)00338-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  241. Thayer JF, & Lane RD (2009). Claude Bernard and the heart-brain connection: Further elaboration of a model of neurovisceral integration. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 33(2), 81–88. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2008.08.004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  242. Thompson RJ, Dizén M, & Berenbaum H (2009). The unique relations between emotional awareness and facets of affective instability. Journal of Research in Personality, 43(5), 875–879. 10.1016/j.jrp.2009.07.006 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  243. Thorndike RL (1920). Intelligence and its uses. Harper’s Magazine, 140, 227–235. [Google Scholar]
  244. Tobacyk JJ (1980). Comparison of five measures of affective complexity derived from P-technique factor analysis. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 50(2), 1259–1262. [Google Scholar]
  245. Tomkins SS (1962). Affect imagery consciousness: Vol. I. The positive affects. Springer. [Google Scholar]
  246. Tomkins SS (1963). Affect imagery consciousness: Vol. II. The negative affects. Springer. [Google Scholar]
  247. Tomko RL, Lane SP, Pronove LM, Treloar HR, Brown WC, Solhan MB, Wood PK, & Trull TJ (2015). Undifferentiated negative affect and impulsivity in borderline personality and depressive disorders: A momentary perspective. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 124(3), 740–753. 10.1037/abn0000064 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  248. Trull TJ, Solhan MB, Tragesser SL, Jahng S, Wood PK, Piasecki TM, & Watson D (2008). Affective instability: Measuring a core feature of borderline personality disorder with ecological momentary assessment. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 117(3), 647–661. 10.1037/a0012532 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  249. Tsai JL, Knutson B, & Fung HH (2006). Cultural variation in affect valuation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 90(2), 288–307. 10.1037/0022-3514.90.2.288 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  250. Tugade MM, Fredrickson BL, & Barrett LF (2004). Psychological resilience and positive emotional granularity: Examining the benefits of positive emotions on coping and health. Journal of Personality, 72(6), 1161–1190. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.2004.00294.x [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  251. Tversky B, & Hemenway K (1984). Objects, parts, and categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 113(2), 169–193. 10.1037/0096-3445.113.2.169 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  252. Ullén F, Hambrick DZ, & Mosing MA (2016). Rethinking expertise: A multifactorial gene-environment interaction model of expert performance. Psychological Bulletin, 142(4), 427–446. 10.1037/bul0000033 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  253. Versluis A, Verkuil B, Lane RD, Hagemann D, Thayer JF, & Brosschot JF (2021). Ecological momentary assessment of emotional awareness: Preliminary evaluation of psychometric properties. Current Psychology, 40(3), 1402–1410. 10.1007/s12144-018-0074-6 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  254. von Salisch M (2001). Children’s emotional development: Challenges in their relationships to parents, peers, and friends. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 25(4), 310–319. 10.1080/01650250143000058 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  255. Walters WH (2007). Google Scholar coverage of a multidisciplinary field. Information Processing & Management, 43(4), 1121–1132. 10.1016/j.ipm.2006.08.006 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  256. Watson D, & Walker LM (1996). The long-term stability and predictive validity of trait measures of affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 70(3), 567–577. 10.1037/0022-3514.70.3.567 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  257. Waugh CE, Thompson RJ, & Gotlib IH (2011). Flexible emotional responsiveness in trait resilience. Emotion, 11(5), 1059–1067. 10.1037/a0021786 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  258. Werner H, & Kaplan B (1963). Symbol formation: An organismic-developmental approach to language and the expression of thought. Wiley. [Google Scholar]
  259. Wessman AE, & Ricks DF (1966). Mood and personality. Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. [Google Scholar]
  260. Wilhelm FH, & Grossman P (2010). Emotions beyond the laboratory: Theoretical fundaments, study design, and analytic strategies for advanced ambulatory assessment. Biological Psychology, 84(3), 552–569. 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2010.01.017 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  261. Williams P, Gauthier I, & Tarr MJ (1998). Feature learning during the acquisition of perceptual expertise. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(1), 40–41. 10.1017/S0140525X98510102 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  262. Wormwood JB, Khan Z, Siegel E, Lynn SK, Dy J, Barrett LF, & Quigley KS (2019). Physiological indices of challenge and threat: A data-driven investigation of autonomic nervous system reactivity during an active coping stressor task. Psychophysiology, 56(12), Article e13454. 10.1111/psyp.13454 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  263. Zeidner M, Matthews G, & Roberts RD (2012). The emotional intelligence, health, and well-being nexus: What have we learned and what have we missed? Applied Psychology. Health and Well-Being, 4(1), 1–30. 10.1111/j.1758-0854.2011.01062.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  264. Zhu Z, & Bonanno GA (2017). Affective flexibility: Relations to expressive flexibility, feedback, and depression. Clinical Psychological Science, 5(6), 930–942. 10.1177/2167702617717337 [DOI] [Google Scholar]

Associated Data

This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

Supplementary Materials

Supplemental Materials

RESOURCES