Skip to main content
Demography logoLink to Demography
. 2010 Nov;47(4):895–921. doi: 10.1007/BF03213732

Divorce as Risky Behavior

AUDREY LIGHT 1, TAEHYUN AHN 2
PMCID: PMC3000036  PMID: 21308563

Abstract

Given that divorce often represents a high-stakes income gamble, we ask how individual levels of risk tolerance affect the decision to divorce. We extend the orthodox divorce model by assuming that individuals are risk averse, that marriage is risky, and that divorce is even riskier. The model predicts that conditional on the expected gains to marriage and divorce, the probability of divorce increases with relative risk tolerance because risk averse individuals require compensation for the additional risk that is inherent in divorce. To implement the model empirically, we use data for first-married women and men from the 1979 National Longitudinal Survey of Youth to estimate a probit model of divorce in which a measure of risk tolerance is among the covariates. The estimates reveal that a 1-point increase in risk tolerance raises the predicted probability of divorce by 4.3% for a representative man and by 11.4% for a representative woman. These findings are consistent with the notion that divorce entails a greater income gamble for women than for men.


“Better the devil you know than the devil you don’t.”

— English proverb

For many individuals, divorce is a high-stakes gamble. The gains that they receive by remaining married are far from certain, given that future income, asset values, and non-pecuniary rewards (including love) are susceptible to random shocks. Nonetheless, the value of a current marriage can appear to be a “sure bet” compared with the highly uncertain payoff associated with divorce. The financial well-being of divorced women in particular often depends on the generosity of property settlements, the availability of post-divorce transfers, growth of their own labor market earnings, and luck in the remarriage market—all of which are subject to considerable randomness. Although the inherently risky nature of divorce is widely acknowledged in the policy arena and social science literature, this article is the first to address the following question: How important are individual levels of risk aversion in determining who divorces?

We begin our analysis by recasting a simple model of divorce to highlight the role of individual risk preference. Following the seminal work of Becker, Landes, and Michael (1977), we assume that individuals compare the expected utilities associated with marriage and divorce on an ongoing basis in response to new information about current match quality, expected divorce costs, prospects for remarriage, and other factors. In contrast to existing studies, we assume individuals are risk averse. If divorce were the only alternative to involve risk, then an individual would not divorce unless the expected consumption associated with divorce exceeded the known consumption associated with marriage by an amount at least as large as the risk premium. In fact, we assume that both alternatives involve risk and that divorce is location-independent riskier (Jewitt 1989) than marriage. This particular definition of “riskier” ensures that the risk premium that an individual must receive in order to choose divorce instead of marriage increases monotonically in an Arrow-Pratt index of risk aversion. Simply put, a risk averse individual is predicted to be less likely to divorce than is a more risk tolerant counterpart.

To assess this prediction empirically, we use data from the 1979 National Longitudinal Survey of Youth (NLSY79) to estimate discrete choice models of married women’s and men’s divorce decisions. Our key regressor is a measure of each individual’s relative risk tolerance, which is derived from responses to questions about the willingness to accept alternative lifetime income gambles. We also control for an array of variables intended to measure the economic gains to marriage and divorce, including characteristics of marriage markets and U.S. state laws governing divorce.

Our estimates reveal that risk preference plays an important role in the decision to divorce, especially for women. For example, among representative women in their fourth year of marriage, a 1-point (1.8 standard deviation [SD]) increase in risk tolerance raises the predicted probability of divorce by 11.4%. Among representative men with the same marriage duration, an identical 1-point increase in risk tolerance (which equals 1 SD in the men’s distribution) is associated with a 4.3% increase in the predicted probability of divorce. When we consider identical men and women (for whom all characteristics equal grand means rather than gender-specific means), the marginal effects just described change to 16.7% for women and 4.0% for men. This gender comparison is consistent with the notion that risk aversion deters divorce and that divorce entails a greater income gamble for women than for men.

Although risk and uncertainty are central to many analyses of marriage and divorce, surprisingly little attention has been paid to individual heterogeneity in risk preference. The role of risk aversion is featured prominently in studies that view marriage as a mechanism for insuring against income risk (Chiappori and Reny 2006; Chiappori and Weiss 2007; Hess 2004; Kotlikoff and Spivak 1981; Rosenzweig and Stark 1989). However, Chiappori and Reny (2006) are the first contributors to this literature to have considered how individual variation in risk aversion comes into play; they argued that risk sharing motives lead to negative assortative matching on risk preference. Studies that take a search-theoretic approach to marital matching (Burdett and Coles 1999; Mortensen 1988) are, by their very nature, concerned with decision-making under uncertainty. Despite this focus, the assumption of risk aversion—let alone heterogeneity in risk preference—has been introduced into search models only recently. Sahib and Gu (2002) argued that unmarried, risk averse individuals establish a higher reservation level for marital partners than for cohabiting partners if marriage is the riskier of the two alternatives. In the only empirical studies to use a measure of individual risk preference as a determinant of marital transitions, Schmidt (2008) and Spivey (2010) found that the waiting time to marriage decreases with risk aversion, presumably because risk averse individuals attach less value to continued search and/or place more value on the risk pooling gains to marriage.

A lack of data can be blamed for the relative inattention paid to the influence of individual risk preference on marital transitions. The NLSY79 is the only large-scale, U.S. survey to elicit information on all respondents’ risk preferences while also supporting detailed analyses of transitions into and out of marriage. During three of the 22 interviews conducted through 2006, NLSY79 respondents were asked whether they would accept two hypothetical, lifetime income gambles of varying riskiness.1 We use multiple responses to these questions to estimate an Arrow-Pratt index of relative risk tolerance that accounts for both measurement error and aging effects. Although identical income gamble questions were included in multiple rounds of the Health and Retirement Study, that survey’s focus on older individuals makes it less appropriate for an analysis of divorce. The questions were also included in the Panel Study of Income Dynamics but were asked only of employed respondents in a single interview year. In 2004, the German Socio-Economic Panel Study (GSOEP) asked respondents to rate their willingness to take risks in a number of specific contexts, while also asking about their willingness to participate in a particular, hypothetical lottery. Because the GSOEP has followed a large, representative sample of individuals for more than 20 years—and collected detailed information on labor market activities and family formation—it is a viable non-U.S. alternative to the NLSY79 for an analysis of the effects of risk preference on marital dissolution.2

THE DECISION TO DIVORCE

We rely on the simple, canonical discrete choice model that is often used to identify determinants of divorce (Becker et al. 1977; Charles and Stephens 2004; Hoffman and Duncan 1995; Weiss and Willis 1997). The model is based on the assumption that couples marry because they expect marriage to bring them higher utility than the alternative states, and subsequently divorce when new information causes them to change their assessment of the relative gains to marriage. This view of the decision process leads to the estimation of a sequential, discrete choice model with proxies for the expected gains to marriage and divorce as regressors. Analysts have relied on a range of theoretical ideas (e.g., intra-household specialization, consumption smoothing, bargaining, and marital search) to justify their choice of covariates, but they have only considered the case where decision makers are risk neutral.3

In this section, we demonstrate how risk aversion is likely to affect the divorce decision. In the unrealistic case in which the value of continued marriage is known with certainty and only divorce entails a risk, well-known principles of utility theory apply: whereas risk neutral individuals divorce whenever the expected utility of divorce exceeds the known utility of continued marriage, risk averse individuals require the expected utility of divorce to exceed the utility of marriage by “enough” to compensate for the risk (Pratt 1964). We devote the first subsection to formalizing the choice model and showing that this well-known risk premium argument also applies to the case in which marriage is risky but divorce is riskier.

Although the risk premium argument provides an intuitive interpretation of the effect of risk tolerance on the decision to divorce, in the second subsection of this article, we consider alternative interpretations. Specifically, we discuss ways in which an individual’s level of risk tolerance might be determined by, or otherwise related to, expected gains to marriage and divorce. If we fail to control fully for these gains, then a positive link between risk tolerance and divorce could reflect the fact that highly risk tolerant individuals gain relatively less from marriage than do their more risk averse counterparts.

Effects of Risk Tolerance on the Choice Between Two Risky Options

Let Mit=M(Xit,Xith,Xitc,φitc) be the lifetime consumption that individual i receives if she remains married from time t until the end of her horizon. The woman’s gain to marriage depends on current and future values of her own characteristics (Xit); her husband’s characteristics ( Xith); tangible factors, such as joint financial assets that characterize the couple ( Xitc); and intangible characteristics of the marriage, such as love ( φitc). The lifetime consumption that the woman receives if she instead divorces at time t is Dit=D(Xit,Xith,Xitc,Zit), where Zit represents current and future divorce costs and characteristics of the marriage market. The value of divorce includes Xith and Xitc insofar as financial components of these vectors affect property settlements, alimony, and child support, while components such as children affect the indirect costs of divorce.

Each individual has an increasing, concave utility function U(Cit) defined over consumption that implies an Arrow-Pratt measure of relative risk tolerance, ρit = –U′ / CitU ″. We assume that relative risk tolerance (the inverse of relative risk aversion) varies across individuals and ranges from zero to infinity. Although we assume that everyone is risk averse, the limiting case is an individual who is neutral toward risk and would need no premium to accept the riskier of two options with equal expected payoffs.

Before turning to the case in which both marriage and divorce involve risk, we consider the decision-rules that maximize (expected) utility in two simpler scenarios. If the lifetime consumption associated with marriage and divorce are both known with certainty, the woman chooses to divorce whenever U(Dit) > U(Mit); empirical implementation of this model simply requires that we have data for the determinants of Mit and Dit. Alternatively, if Mit is known with certainty but divorce is risky, the woman divorces whenever EU(Dit) > U(Mit)—that is, whenever U[E(Dit) – πit] > U(Mit), where πit ≥ 0 is the risk premium that the woman is willing to pay to receive E(Dit) – πit with certainty rather than face the uncertain outcome of divorce. Pratt (1964) established that under this scenario, πit decreases monotonically with the index of relative risk tolerance, ρit. Because this particular model predicts that the probability of divorce increases in ρit, its empirical analog should include a control for ρit in addition to controls for the determinants of Mit and Dit.

Having established the role of risk preference when divorce is the only risky option, we turn to the scenario that more accurately describes the divorce decision: marriage is risky, and divorce is even riskier. We assume that divorce is the riskier option for two reasons. First, the woman’s consumption while married (Mit) depends on the evolution of her current husband’s characteristics, but her consumption while divorced (Dit) depends on the current and future attributes of a potential new husband; thus, Dit is riskier than Mit because it depends on which second husband (if any) is selected as well as realizations of his characteristics over time. Second, while Xith and Xitc are determinants of both Mit and Dit, their contribution to Dit depends on how they will change over time and how they will be distributed after the divorce.

Women are typically more dependent than men on spousal income, alimony, child support, and other income sources that become more uncertain upon divorce (Bianchi, Subaiya, and Kahn 1999; Cancian, Danziger, and Gottschalk 1993; Light 2004). Thus, the arguments in the preceding paragraph imply that divorce entails a greater income gamble for women than for men.4 Although it seems noncontroversial to assume that divorce is riskier for women than for men, on average, we expect the risk to differ among individuals of a given gender. For example, women with high earnings potential, no children, and/or explicit prenuptial agreements are likely to face relatively little uncertainty about their consumption if they divorce. Our empirical model identifies the effects of Mit, Dit, and ρit on the probability of divorce at the mean level of unobserved risk.

To demonstrate that the risk premium argument continues to apply when both options are risky, we must be explicit about the sense in which divorce is riskier than marriage. Rather than describe a stochastic process by which Xit, Xith, Xitc, ϕit, and Zit evolve over time, we simply assume that both Mit and Dit are random variables with cumulative distribution functions FM and FD, respectively. We further assume that FD is location-independent riskier than FM as defined by Jewitt (1989). This condition holds if and only if

FD1(p)FD(c)dcFM1(p)FM(c)dcp(0,1). (1)

As Chateauneuf, Cohen, and Meilijson (2004) demonstrated, an alternative definition is that FD single-crosses FM such that the (negative) horizontal distance FD1(c)FM1(c) is nondecreasing in every interval below the crossing point.

Location-independent risk is the most general stochastic order to guarantee that the premium a risk averse individual will pay for partial insurance is monotonically decreasing in her Arrow-Pratt coefficient of risk tolerance (Chateauneuf et al. 2004; Jewitt 1989; Landsberger and Meilijson 1994).5 Location-independence is a plausible distributional assumption, but it does not have to hold for the risk premium argument to apply. Alternative definitions of “riskier” might entail deviations from monotonicity yet still yield a negative correlation between πit and ρit.

When both divorce and marriage are risky, the woman divorces whenever EDU(Dit) > EMU(Mit), where the expectations are formed over FD and FM. This condition is met whenever EMU(Dit – πit) > EMU(Mit), where πit > 0 is now the risk premium that the woman is willing to pay to draw Dit – πit from the less-risky distribution FM rather than face the riskier divorce outcome. Because the assumption of location-independent risk assures that πit decreases monotonically in ρit, we continue to predict that, all else equal, the probability of divorce rises with a woman’s level of relative risk tolerance.

Effects of Risk Tolerance on the Gains to Marriage and Divorce

The preceding discussion provides a familiar rationale for including a measure of relative risk tolerance among the determinants of divorce: ρit is inversely related to the risk premium needed to compensate women for the extra risk associated with divorce. A woman’s risk preference can also affect (or be correlated with) her search for a husband both before and after her current marriage, the extent to which she engages in within-household risk sharing, and her bargaining power. Matching, risk sharing, and bargaining contribute to the relative gain associated with marriage which, in turn, affects the probability of divorce. In this subsection, we consider how risk preference might affect the probability of divorce through these additional channels.

Consider a situation in which single women search for marriage partners; for now, we set aside the option to cohabit rather than marry, as well as the ability to engage in assortative matching on risk preference. Given this simple scenario, we expect the value of search—and, therefore, the reservation level for an acceptable husband—to increase with the woman’s degree of relative risk tolerance. This argument, which originated in the job search literature (Pissarides 1974) and has been applied to marital search (Schmidt 2008; Spivey 2010), suggests that components of Mit increase in ρit. In contrast to the prediction emerging from the risk premium framework, we might find that the probability of divorce decreases in ρit to the extent that ρit is positively correlated with unmeasured components of Mit.

This naive prediction does not necessarily hold after we acknowledge that cohabitation is another option available to single women. As shown by Sahib and Gu (2002), a risk averse woman can mitigate the risk inherent in marriage by forming a cohabiting union with her potential mate. Thus, match quality might be higher among relatively low-ρ women who cohabit before marriage than among relatively high-ρ women who transition directly from single to married. Moreover, because women can expect to relaunch the search process after a divorce, any relationship between risk preference and Mit can also exist between risk preference and Dit. In short, search models suggest ways in which ρit might be correlated with Mit and Dit but do not yield an unambiguous prediction about the effect of risk tolerance on divorce.

Risk sharing provides another mechanism by which a woman’s risk preference can affect the gains associated with marriage and divorce and, in turn, the probability of divorce. Given the consumption-smoothing opportunities inherent in a two-adult household (Weiss 1997), one prediction is that a highly risk averse woman derives a higher level of expected utility from marriage than does a more risk tolerant woman (Schmidt 2008; Spivey 2010). However, Chiappori and Reny (2006) argued that the desire to share risk leads to negative assortative matching on risk preference. If high-ρ women are matched with low-ρ husbands and vice versa, then the additional marital consumption accruing to the couple as a result of risk sharing behavior is unlikely to be tied to the woman’s risk preference. Only to the extent that couples fail to sort on risk preference would we expect unobserved elements of Mit that represent intrahousehold risk sharing to be correlated with ρit. 6

More generally, any factor that (1) affects the probability of divorce, (2) is left unmeasured in our empirical choice model, and (3) is correlated with ρit can affect our inferences about the relationship between risk tolerance and divorce decisions. Many “errors in variables” interpretations are immediately undermined by the fact that we estimate markedly different relationships for women than for men; although this fact is consistent with the risk premium argument, an alternative interpretation requires a gender difference in the omitted variable’s effect on divorce decisions and/or correlation with risk tolerance. By invoking bargaining models of marriage (Lundberg and Pollak 1994, 1996; Manser and Brown 1980; McElroy and Horney 1981), for example, we could argue that highly risk tolerant women (but not men) succeed in allocating marital gains toward themselves. Although we have no a priori reason to believe that bargaining power is systematically related to risk preference, bargaining power is a prime example of a factor that affects divorce decisions and is controlled for imperfectly.

ESTIMATION OF THE DIVORCE MODEL

To implement our model empirically, we assume that Sit = EDU(Dit) – EMU(Mit) is linear in factors that determine the gains to marriage and divorce. That is,

Sit=β1ρit+β2Xit+β3Xith+β4Xitc+β5φitc+β3Zit+ɛit, (2)

where ρit continues to represent the Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk tolerance, and Xit, Xith, Xitc, φitc, and Zit represent the factors described earlier. The risk premium argument predicts that β1 is positive: holding constant the determinants of Mit and Dit, we expect the probability of divorce to increase in ρit because ρit is negatively correlated with the premium needed to accept the greater risk associated with divorce. As discussed, correlations between ρit and unmeasured components of Mit and Dit can also affect our estimate of β1. We do not expect these indirect effects to be systematically positive or negative, but they exist if our detailed set of covariates fails to control adequately for the gains to marriage.

In Eq. (2), ɛit represents unobserved factors that influence the probability of divorce. We assume that ɛit is a normally distributed random variable and that, conditional on the control variables, ɛit has a zero mean and constant variance. Given these assumptions, we estimate the probability of divorce (the probability that Sit > 0) as a probit model. We compute standard errors that account for nonindependence of ɛit across observations for a given individual.

DATA

Sample Selection

Our primary data source is the 1979 National Longitudinal Survey of Youth (NLSY79). The original NLSY79 sample consists of a nationally representative subsample of 6,111 individuals born between 1957 and 1964; an oversample of 5,295 blacks, Hispanics, and disadvantaged nonblacks/non-Hispanics born between 1957 and 1964; and a sample of 1,280 individuals born between 1957 and 1961 who enlisted in the military. All 12,686 sample members were interviewed in 1979, and subsequent interviews were conducted every year through 1994 and biennially thereafter. We use data from survey years 1979–2004. The military subsample was dropped from the survey in 1985, and the disadvantaged oversample was dropped in 1991. Thus, none of these respondents appear in our sample because we require valid responses to income gamble questions asked in 1993 and beyond.

We construct separate samples of men and women. Of the 6,283 female and 6,403 male respondents in the NLSY79, we omit 1,093 women and 512 men because they marry prior to their first interview in 1979. We impose this selection rule because a subset of covariates cannot be identified for in-progress marriages. We eliminate 1,108 (1,704) of the remaining women (men) because they remained “never married” at the time of their last interview date. This leaves us with 4,082 women and 4,187 men whose first marriages are observed from their beginning to their dissolution or to the respondent’s last interview date.7 We omit 850 of these women and 866 men from our samples because we lack responses to at least one series of income gamble questions asked in 1993, 2002, and 2004; 811 of these women and 824 of these men left the survey prior to 1993. Finally, we omit 18 women and 23 men because their marriage began the same year as their last interview, which prevents us from observing the marriage over at least one 12-month interval. These selection rules leave us with samples of first marriages for 3,214 women and 3,298 men.

In modeling the decision to divorce, we use a sample of 38,733 person-year observations for women and 37,662 person-year observations for men. Each marriage contributes one observation per year from its onset until the time it ends in divorce or the individual is last interviewed. We include annual observations for those years (e.g., 1995, 1997) when NLSY79 respondents were not interviewed by imputing values for select time-varying covariates from information reported during adjacent interviews. Each marriage contributes between 1 and 24 observations to the sample, with a mean of 12.1 observations per marriage (SD = 6.9).

Measuring Risk Tolerance

In 1993, 2002, and 2004, NLSY79 respondents were asked the following question about their willingness to accept lifetime income risk:

Suppose that you are the only income earner in the family, and you have a good job guaranteed to give you your current (family) income every year for life. You are given the opportunity to take a new and equally good job, with a 50-50 chance that it will double your (family) income and a 50-50 chance that it will cut your (family) income by a third. Would you take the new job?

Respondents who answered “yes” were asked as a follow-up whether they would still take the new job if the chances were 50-50 that it would double their income and 50-50 that it would cut their income by one-half. Respondents who answered “no” to the initial question were asked a follow-up question in which the gamble was changed to a 50-50 chance of doubling income and a 50-50 chance of cutting it by 20%.

We form a four-way, ordinal ranking based on individuals’ direct responses to the income gamble questions. The first category identifies the least risk tolerant individuals who decline gambles that could cut their income by one-third and one-fifth. Category 2 identifies individuals who decline the gamble with a downside risk of one-third but accept the downside risk of one-fifth. Individuals who decline the gamble with a downside risk of one-half but accept the one-third gamble are in Category 3, and Category 4 represents the most risk tolerant individuals who accept gambles that entail a potential loss of both one-third and one-half of their income.

We use these categorical variables to estimate each individual’s Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk tolerance in each year. The resulting variable RT is a cardinal measure of risk that can be compared in a meaningful fashion across individuals, and is inversely related to the risk premium described earlier. (We also use the four categorical variables as an alternative measure of risk tolerance.) To compute RT, we modify the estimation procedure proposed by Barsky et al. (1997) to incorporate the multiple responses to the income gamble questions available in the NLSY79; this allows us to attribute within-person variation in risk tolerance to both aging and measurement error or other time-varying shocks. Ahn (2010), Kimball et al. (2008), and Sahm (2007) described variants of the computational method.

The first step in the estimation procedure is to assume each individual’s utility over lifetime consumption (C) exhibits constant relative risk aversion:

U(Ci)=Ci11/ρit11/ρit, (3)

where ρit is the coefficient of relative risk tolerance for individual i at time t. We can infer lower and upper bounds for each individual’s ρit from categorical responses to the income gamble questions. For example, if a respondent accepts the first gamble (is willing to risk her current income for a 50-50 chance of doubling income or cutting income by one-third) but rejects the second (is unwilling to gamble on a 50-50 chance of doubling her income or cutting it in half), the following must hold:

12U(2I)+12U(23I)U(I)and12U(2I)+12U(12I)<U(I). (4)

Given our parameterization of the utility function, we infer that this individual’s ρit lies between 0.5 and 1.0.8

We further assume that an individual’s ρit can be modeled as

logρit=βAGEit+αi+uit, (5)

where αiN(α¯,σu2) and uitN(0,σu2). We allow variation in log ρit to depend on age and unobserved random effects that we decompose into person-specific factors (αi) and time-varying factors such as measurement error (uit). Although risk preference is often viewed as an innate, time-invariant characteristic, we include age in our model in light of evidence presented in Ahn (2010) and Sahm (2007) that individuals tend to grow more risk averse with age; we present our own evidence of this pattern in Table 2. Moreover, we estimate Eq. (5) separately for men and women in light of the evidence that women are more risk averse than men (Sahm 2007)

Table 2.

Distribution of Risk Category Based on Second Response by Risk Category Based on First Response

Risk Category, First Response Women: Risk Category, Second Response
Men: Risk Category, Second Response
1 2 3 4 All 1 2 3 4 All
1 67.5 10.1 11.7 10.6 [49.8] 64.1 8.8 12.6 14.6 [44.7]
2 53.0 18.9 16.5 11.6 [13.4] 47.3 16.9 17.8 18.1 [12.4]
3 49.5 11.7 21.5 17.3 [17.2] 48.6 13.4 21.5 16.5 [17.9]
4 46.6 11.9 17.0 24.5 [19.5] 43.2 9.8 19.3 27.7 [26.1]
All 58.4 11.9 15.1 14.6 [100.0] 53.9 10.8 16.5 18.7 [100.0]
Number of Individuals 1,686 334 435 422 2,887 1,573 316 482 547 2,918

Notes: Risk categories are based on responses to income gamble questions asked in 1993, 2002, and 2004. Samples exclude 327 women and 380 men who respond only once. Categories 1 and 4 consist, respectively, of the least and most risk tolerant individuals. Numbers in brackets are percentages of column totals, and all other numbers are percentages of row totals.

Given the parameterization shown in Eq. (5), we construct a log-likelihood function that depends on the data (age, risk category) and parameters β, ᾱ, σα, and σu. We compute gender-specific maximum likelihood estimates of each parameter—using data for all men and women in the NLSY79 who answer the income gamble questions, regardless of whether they appear in our sample—and use these estimates to calculate each individual’s expected ρit at each age that her marriage is observed. The maximum likelihood estimates appear in Table 1; details on the procedure appear in the appendix. These conditional expectations form the variable RT, which represents each individual’s coefficient of relative risk tolerance in each year.9

Table 1.

Maximum Likelihood Estimates of Risk Preference Parameters

Parameter Women
Men
Estimate SE Estimate SE
β −0.035 0.003 −0.047 0.003
−0.178 0.104 0.525 0.114
σα 1.277 0.029 1.390 0.032
σu 1.131 0.019 1.222 0.021
Log-Likelihood −13,746.41 −13,599.71
Number of Individuals 4,618 4,577
Number of Observations 12,481 11,903

Note: Parameters are for Eq. (5).

To substantiate our claim that risk preferences change over time, in Table 2 we compare individuals’ first and second responses to the income gamble questions. Almost 90% of the individuals in our samples provided responses in both 1993 and 2002, but for this cross-tabulation, we include a small number of 1993–2004 and 2002–2004 comparisons as well. Table 2 reveals that roughly one-half of the women in our sample fall into risk Category 1 (least tolerant) based on the first response, and that 68% of these women remain in Category 1 when they answer the income gamble questions a second time. Among the women whose first response places them in Category 4 (most tolerant), only 25% remain in the same category—that is, 75% of these women appear to become less risk tolerant over time, while only 32% of the women who are initially in Category 1 appear to become more risk tolerant over time. Among women who are initially in Category 2, 53% reported a lower risk tolerance the second time, while only 28% reported a higher level; for those initially in Category 3, 61% reported a lower level and 17% reported a higher level the second time. These patterns reveal why we model log ρit as a function of age: although much of the within-person variation in risk category can be attributed to reporting error, women also become less risk tolerant as they age.

Table 2 reveals two salient differences between men and women: men are more risk tolerant than women and are somewhat less likely to decrease their risk tolerance with age. On the basis of their first responses, men are 5 percentage points less likely than women to fall into Category 1 (44.7% versus 49.8%) and 6 percentage points more likely to fall into Category 4 (26.1% versus 19.5%). Among men whose first response places them in Category 1 or 2, 36% report a higher level of risk tolerance with their second response (versus only 28%–32% of women). Among men whose first response places them in Category 4, 72% move to a lower level of risk tolerance on the basis of their second response (versus 75% of women).

Table 3 summarizes the distribution of the variable RT among women and men in each self-reported risk category; for this table, we use the value of RT for the year corresponding to the individual’s first response to the income gamble questions. Although both the mean and median of RT increase monotonically with the risk category, as expected, considerable variation exists in RT within each category. For example, it ranges from 0.21 to 1.43 among women and from 0.23 to 1.80 among men whose income gamble responses place them in Category 2 even though the upper and lower bounds for that category are 0.27 and 0.50 (see footnote 8). This imperfect correspondence between individuals’ categorical responses and our variable reflects the fact that we “smooth” over a considerable amount of reporting error in constructing RT. As shown in Table 1, the two estimated error variances in our log ρit model are roughly equal in magnitude for men and women, which suggests that one-half of the total variation is attributable to error.

Table 3.

Summary Statistics for Risk Tolerance Variable by Risk Category Based on First Response

Risk Category, First Responsea Risk Tolerance (RT)b
Mean SD Minimum Median Maximum Number
Women
  1 0.25 0.18 0.11 0.20 1.06 1,601
  2 0.46 0.25 0.21 0.42 1.43 430
  3 0.60 0.30 0.26 0.55 1.76 556
  4 1.15 0.85 0.38 0.99 3.67 628
  All 0.51 0.56 0.11 0.38 3.67 3,214
Men
  1 0.32 0.26 0.11 0.26 1.31 1,480
  2 0.59 0.37 0.23 0.49 1.80 366
  3 0.74 0.44 0.29 0.60 2.25 582
  4 1.65 1.30 0.43 1.28 5.42 870
  All 0.77 0.90 0.11 0.47 5.42 3,298
a

See note to Table 2 for variable definition.

b

Computed relative risk tolerance for the same year as the first response to the income gamble questions.

Other Covariates

We use many variables to control for the expected gains to marriage and divorce. These variables are intended to capture heterogeneity in match quality, marriage-specific capital, intrahousehold specialization, intrahousehold consumption smoothing, bargaining power, divorce costs, remarriage opportunities, and attitudes toward marriage and divorce. To organize our discussion, we group the variables into economic measures, demographic and family background characteristics, and environmental factors. Summary statistics are in Table 4.

Table 4.

Definitions and Summary Statistics for Variables Used in Divorce Model

Variable Definition Women
Men
Mean SD Mean SD
Divorce 1 if divorces during interval 0.04 0.04
Risk Tolerance Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk tolerance 0.51 0.56 0.75 0.95
Economic Variables
  Assets Total net family assetsa 102.37 256.73 107.97 263.13
  Total income Sum of spouses’ labor incomesa 56.03 41.53 54.95 40.46
  Income share Own share of total incomea 33.95 22.24 65.76 22.65
  Income correlation Correlation between spouses’ incomesa,b 0.08 0.54 0.06 0.58
  No correlation 1 if income correlation is missingb 0.01 0.01
  Predicted total income Predicted total incomea 53.19 24.94 49.25 24.32
  Predicted income share Predicted own share of total incomea 34.98 17.17 71.30 17.99
  Predicted income correlation Predicted income correlationa,b 0.09 0.17 0.06 0.18
Demographic Variables
  Number of children Number of children in household 1.42 1.19 1.35 1.20
  Children aged 0–6 1 if any children age 6 or younger 0.50 0.48
  Male children 1 if any male children 0.53 0.49
  Premarriage children 1 if any children born before marriageb 0.16 0.06
  Age at marriage Age at marriageb 23.77 4.35 25.02 4.21
  Age gap Difference in spouses’ agesb 3.43 3.61 2.78 2.77
  Schooling gap Difference in spouses’ years of schoolb 1.42 1.62 1.31 1.52
  Cohabited with spouse 1 if cohabited with spouseb 0.31 0.35
  Cohabited with other 1 if cohabited with other partnerb 0.02 0.02
  Black 1 if blackb 0.24 0.23
  Hispanic 1 if Hispanicb 0.19 0.20
  Baptist 1 if religion is Baptistb 0.26 0.25
  Catholic 1 if religion is Catholicb 0.39 0.38
  Other religion 1 if no or other religionb 0.10 0.11
  Lived with mother 1 if lived with mother only, age 14b 0.14 0.14
  Lived with mother/stepfather Lived with mother/stepfather, age 14b 0.06 0.06
  Lived without mother No mother, age 14b 0.07 0.07
  Traditional views 1 if agrees women are happier at homeb 0.27 0.37
Environmental Variables
  No-fault 1 if no-fault law for divorcec 0.35 0.35
  Property no-fault 1 if no-fault law for property settlementc 0.42 0.42
  Separation duration Minimum required separation (months)c 10.59 11.53 10.54 11.50
  County unemployment rate County unemployment rate 6.90 3.16 6.77 3.04
  County divorce rate County divorce rate 4.91 1.96 4.93 1.89
  County race Percentage of county population same race 59.63 31.19 59.21 32.46
  County male Percentage of county population male 48.82 1.32 48.86 1.22
Number of Person-Year Observations 38,733 37,662
Number of Individuals 3,214 3,298

Note: The model also includes dummy variables identifying current marriage duration.

a

Income levels are deflated by the CPI-U and expressed in thousands of 2000 dollars.

b

Variable does not change value over the duration of the marriage.

c

Based on state-specific divorce laws for the given calendar year.

Our economic variables include a measure of each individual’s net family assets. We construct this variable by summing the values of homes, automobiles, cash holdings, stocks, bonds, trusts, retirement accounts, and various other assets that are reported in each interview from 1985 onward, and subtracting the reported values of mortgages, business debts, and other debts.10 We include net assets in our model to capture the value of marriage-specific capital and public goods that increase the gains to marriage and lower the probability of divorce.

Our covariates include four income measures. First, we control for the couple’s total labor income, which is the sum of the partners’ wage and salary income in the last year. This variable is intended to capture such gains to marriage as the joint consumption associated with income (Moffitt 2000). Second, we control for the share of total family income contributed by the individual. This variable reflects the degree to which a husband and wife exploit their comparative advantages in market and home production, thereby increasing the gains to marriage (Becker 1974; Becker et al. 1977). In addition, the share of total income contributed by the woman represents her economic independence, which is a key component of her expected gains to divorce (Oppenheimer 1997). For both reasons, an increase in the woman’s share of income is predicted to increase the probability of divorce, holding total income constant. Following Hess (2004), we also control for the correlation coefficient between spouses’ labor income to measure the extent of intrahousehold income risk sharing. A couple with negatively correlated incomes are best able to exploit the risk sharing advantages of marriage and, as a result, are less likely to divorce. Because income correlation cannot be computed for marriages that contribute only one observation, we also include a dummy variable indicating that the variable is missing; we set the income correlation to zero in such cases.11

Because an individual’s labor income can be endogenously determined by her beliefs about a future divorce (Greene and Quester 1982; Johnson and Skinner 1986; Stevenson 2007), we also use a specification that replaces the income variables with predicted versions. Replacing actual labor income with its predicted value is also in the spirit of Pollak’s (2005) argument that wage rates are preferred to actual earnings as measures of bargaining power. We predict respondents’ income with a cubic in age, three dummy variables for schooling attainment, age-adjusted Armed Forces Qualifications Test (AFQT) scores, number of children, occupation dummy variables, state dummy variables, and the median income in the county of residence in the given calendar year. To predict spousal income, we omit AFQT scores and assume that husbands and wives share race/ethnicity and state and county of residence to skirt the fact that this information is known only for respondents. We estimate separate, gender-specific predicting equations for blacks, Hispanics, and whites using observations for first marriages for all NLSY79 respondents, regardless of whether they appear in our sample. Following Hess (2004), we predict the couple’s income correlation directly from a race/ethnicity–specific regression of observed correlation on the same variables used to predict annual income.

The demographic controls used in our divorce model include the number of children in the household, dummy variables indicating whether any children are age 6 or younger or male, and a dummy variable indicating whether any children were born before the marriage began. These child-related variables are intended to capture a key component of marriage-specific capital (Becker 1974; Becker et al. 1977). We control for whether a male child resides in the household in light of empirical evidence that divorce is less likely and remarriage is more likely for women with sons (Lundberg and Rose 2003). The “premarriage children” variable indicates a lack of marital capital insofar as these children may have biological parents outside the marriage, and it also measures match quality, given that marriages that are instigated by a pregnancy may be less strong than other marriages (Becker et al. 1977).

Other measures of match quality include the individual’s age at marriage and 10 dummy variables that identify current marriage duration. These variables control for variation in current age as well; the addition of direct controls for age proved to have insignificant effects on the estimates. We also control for the absolute value of the difference in the husband’s and wife’s age, the absolute value of the difference in their highest education grade completed, and dummy variables identifying premarital cohabitation. Individuals who marry at relatively later ages may have decreased search costs (and, therefore, may have higher-quality marriages) as a result of prior matching experience (Becker et al. 1977), and positive assortative mating on age and schooling attainment are also expected to increase the gains to marriage (Becker 1974). Although numerous empirical studies have shown that premarital cohabitation is associated with increased divorce (Axinn and Thornton 1992; Brien, Lillard, and Stern 2006; Lillard, Brien, and Waite 1995), the effect of cohabiting with one’s current spouse is theoretically ambiguous. If cohabitation is used as a “testing ground,” then couples who eventually choose to marry should be relatively well matched; however, divorce-prone couples may be more likely than others to self-select into premarital cohabitation.

Our demographic controls also include dummy variables indicating whether the individual is black or Hispanic, the religion in which the individual was raised (Baptist, Catholic, or other/none, with Protestant as the omitted group), and family composition at age 14. These controls are intended to capture widely documented effects of religion, race/ethnicity, and family background on attitudes toward marriage, the characteristics of marriage markets, and other factors that influence entry into and exit from marriage (Bumpass, Martin, and Sweet 1991; Lehrer and Chiswick 1993). As an additional measure of marriage-related attitudes, we use responses to a question that asked NLSY79 respondents whether they agree with the following statement: “Women are much happier if they stay at home and take care of their children.” We construct a dummy variable that equals 1 if the respondent agreed or strongly agreed with the statement and 0 if she disagreed or strongly disagreed.

Our environmental variables include three measures of the legal climate governing divorce and the division of property in the individual’s state of residence in the given calendar year. We use a dummy variable to indicate whether state law requires that only “no-fault” divorces be granted in the given year; the omitted category identifies states that either allow or require that “fault” be established as grounds for divorce. We also include a dummy variable indicating whether the state uses no-fault for property division and alimony decisions, and a variable that identifies the mandatory separation period required before a no-fault or unilateral divorce is granted; the separation duration variable equals 0 if the state imposes no separation requirement.12 Both the theoretical and empirical effects of no-fault or unilateral divorce laws on divorce decisions have been debated in the literature for many years (Becker et al. 1977; Friedberg 1998; Mechoulan 2006; Peters 1986; Stevenson 2007), with recent findings (Wolfers 2006) suggesting that the liberalization of divorce law leads to increased divorce rates in the short run.

We include four additional environmental variables that measure the characteristics of the individual’s county of residence for the given year. These variables—from various issues of the City and County Data Book—include the county- and year-specific unemployment rate and divorce rate, the percentage of the county population with the same race/ethnicity (black, white, or Hispanic) as the individual, and the percentage of the county population that is male. Similar variables have been used by Lichter, McLaughlin, and Ribar (2002) as controls for economic opportunities and marriage market characteristics.

FINDINGS

Estimated Effects of Risk Tolerance

In Tables 5 and 6, we present estimates for women and men, respectively, for three specifications of our divorce model. Specification 1 includes all controls described earlier (with the income variables based on actual values rather than predictions), along with RT. Specification 2 uses predicted values for the four income variables but is identical to Specification 1 in all other respects. Specification 3 reverts to actual values of the income variables but omits RT.

Table 5.

Probit Estimates of Effects of Variables on Probability of Divorce: Women

Variable Specification 1
Specification 2a
Specification 3
Coefficient Marginal Effects Coefficient Marginal Effects Coefficient Marginal Effects
Risk Tolerance 0.050 (0.023) 0.0037 0.052 (0.022) 0.0037 ––
Economic Variables
  Assets / 100 −0.042 (0.014) −0.0031 −0.030 (0.012) −0.0021 −0.042 (0.014) −0.0031
  Total income / 100 0.006 (0.050) 0.0005 −0.504 (0.091) −0.0354 −0.007 (0.050) −0.0005
  Income share 0.003 (0.001) 0.0002 0.009 (0.001) 0.0006 0.003 (0.001) 0.0002
  Income correlation −0.035 (0.027) −0.0026 0.189 (0.092) 0.0131 −0.033 (0.027) −0.0024
  No correlation 1.519 (0.174) 0.3362 1.486 (0.172) 0.3171 1.524 (0.174) 0.3383
Demographic Variables
  Number of children −0.077 (0.020) −0.0056 −0.031 (0.020) −0.0021 −0.076 (0.020) −0.0056
  Children aged 0–6 −0.073 (0.034) −0.0054 −0.046 (0.035) −0.0032 −0.074 (0.034) −0.0054
  Male children −0.087 (0.035) −0.0064 −0.081 (0.035) −0.0057 −0.089 (0.035) −0.0066
  Premarriage children 0.231 (0.046) 0.0195 0.199 (0.046) 0.0158 0.232 (0.046) 0.0196
  Age at marriage −0.033 (0.004) −0.0024 −0.023 (0.004) −0.0016 −0.033 (0.004) −0.0024
  Age gap 0.005 (0.005) 0.0004 0.017 (0.006) 0.0012 0.005 (0.005) 0.0004
  Schooling gap −0.014 (0.009) −0.0011 −0.011 (0.009) −0.0008 −0.014 (0.009) −0.0010
  Cohabited with spouse 0.033 (0.033) 0.0025 0.040 (0.033) 0.0029 0.033 (0.033) 0.0025
  Cohabited with other 0.229 (0.098) 0.0206 0.191 (0.102) 0.0159 0.234 (0.097) 0.0211
  Black −0.055 (0.065) −0.0039 −0.159 (0.068) −0.0103 −0.052 (0.065) −0.0037
  Hispanic 0.028 (0.063) 0.0021 −0.108 (0.064) −0.0072 0.031 (0.063) 0.0023
  Baptist 0.035 (0.043) 0.0026 −0.001 (0.042) −0.0001 0.034 (0.043) 0.0025
  Catholic −0.047 (0.039) −0.0034 −0.038 (0.039) −0.0026 −0.048 (0.039) −0.0035
  Other religion 0.058 (0.049) 0.0044 0.036 (0.051) 0.0026 0.058 (0.049) 0.0045
  Lived with mother 0.058 (0.044) 0.0044 0.060 (0.044) 0.0044 0.059 (0.044) 0.0045
  Lived with mother/stepfather 0.187 (0.051) 0.0159 0.192 (0.052) 0.0157 0.185 (0.051) 0.0158
  Lived without mother 0.117 (0.055) 0.0094 0.096 (0.054) 0.0072 0.119 (0.055) 0.0096
  Traditional views −0.091 (0.033) −0.0064 −0.089 (0.033) −0.0060 −0.090 (0.033) −0.0064
Environmental Variables
  No-fault 0.126 (0.047) 0.0096 0.106 (0.046) 0.0076 0.126 (0.047) 0.0096
  Property no-fault 0.026 (0.038) 0.0019 0.073 (0.039) 0.0052 0.026 (0.038) 0.0019
  Separation duration 0.005 (0.002) 0.0003 0.005 (0.002) 0.0004 0.005 (0.002) 0.0003
  County unemployment rate −0.004 (0.005) −0.0003 −0.011 (0.005) −0.0007 −0.005 (0.005) −0.0003
  County divorce rate 0.008 (0.008) 0.0006 0.009 (0.008) 0.0006 0.009 (0.008) 0.0007
  County race −0.000 (0.001) −0.0000 −0.001 (0.001) −0.0001 −0.000 (0.001) −0.0000
  County male −0.019 (0.012) −0.0014 −0.020 (0.012) −0.0014 −0.018 (0.012) −0.0013
Log-Likelihood −6,065.282 −5,944.188 −6,068.289

Notes: The sample consists of 38,733 observations for 3,214 women. Standard errors, shown in parentheses, account for nonindependence across observations for a given woman. Marginal effects are computed at the gender-specific sample means. Each specification also includes controls for current marital duration.

a

Total income, income share, and income correlation are based on predicted income rather than actual income.

Table 6.

Probit Estimates of Effects of Variables on Probability of Divorce: Men

Variable Specification 1
Specification 2a
Specification 3
Coefficient Marginal Effects Coefficient Marginal Effects Coefficient Marginal Effects
Risk Tolerance 0.019 (0.015) 0.0013 0.023 (0.015) 0.0015
Economic Variables
  Assets / 100 −0.022 (0.008) −0.0014 −0.008 (0.008) −0.0005 −0.022 (0.008) −0.0014
  Total income / 100 −0.028 (0.052) −0.0018 −0.785 (0.102) −0.0501 −0.028 (0.052) −0.0018
  Income share −0.002 (0.001) −0.0001 0.004 (0.001) 0.0002 −0.002 (0.001) −0.0001
  Income correlation −0.022 (0.027) −0.0015 0.098 (0.083) 0.0063 −0.022 (0.027) −0.0015
  No correlation 2.514 (0.367) 0.6989 2.487 (0.357) 0.6845 2.520 (0.367) 0.7010
Demographic Variables
  Number of children −0.140 (0.023) −0.0093 −0.147 (0.024) −0.0094 −0.141 (0.023) −0.0093
  Children aged 0–6 −0.270 (0.038) −0.0179 −0.305 (0.039) −0.0195 −0.269 (0.038) −0.0178
  Male children −0.067 (0.043) −0.0044 −0.062 (0.043) −0.0039 −0.067 (0.043) −0.0045
  Premarriage children 0.133 (0.071) 0.0099 0.089 (0.071) 0.0061 0.132 (0.071) 0.0098
  Age at marriage −0.031 (0.005) −0.0021 −0.013 (0.005) −0.0008 −0.032 (0.005) −0.0021
  Age gap 0.015 (0.005) 0.0010 0.006 (0.005) 0.0004 0.015 (0.005) 0.0010
  Schooling gap −0.021 (0.010) −0.0014 −0.017 (0.010) −0.0011 −0.021 (0.010) −0.0014
  Cohabited with spouse 0.011 (0.033) 0.0008 0.021 (0.034) 0.0014 0.012 (0.033) 0.0008
  Cohabited with other 0.163 (0.096) 0.0125 0.113 (0.097) 0.0080 0.164 (0.096) 0.0126
  Black 0.108 (0.068) 0.0076 −0.014 (0.072) −0.0009 0.107 (0.068) 0.0075
  Hispanic −0.049 (0.067) −0.0032 −0.173 (0.070) −0.0100 −0.051 (0.067) −0.0033
  Baptist 0.093 (0.046) 0.0064 0.056 (0.046) 0.0037 0.094 (0.046) 0.0065
  Catholic 0.084 (0.043) 0.0057 0.092 (0.044) 0.0060 0.087 (0.043) 0.0059
  Other religion 0.083 (0.055) 0.0059 0.067 (0.056) 0.0045 0.085 (0.055) 0.0060
  Lived with mother 0.057 (0.042) 0.0039 0.045 (0.042) 0.0030 0.055 (0.042) 0.0038
  Lived with mother/stepfather 0.134 (0.056) 0.0100 0.118 (0.056) 0.0083 0.135 (0.056) 0.0101
  Lived without mother 0.075 (0.058) 0.0053 0.056 (0.059) 0.0037 0.073 (0.058) 0.0052
  Traditional views 0.001 (0.033) 0.0001 −0.041 (0.033) −0.0026 0.003 (0.032) 0.0002
Environmental Variables
  No-fault 0.071 (0.046) 0.0048 0.072 (0.046) 0.0047 0.073 (0.046) 0.0049
  Property no-fault 0.038 (0.039) 0.0025 0.053 (0.040) 0.0034 0.039 (0.039) 0.0026
  Separation duration 0.000 (0.002) 0.0000 0.001 (0.002) 0.0001 0.000 (0.002) 0.0000
  County unemployment rate −0.000 (0.005) −0.0000 −0.009 (0.005) −0.0006 −0.000 (0.005) −0.0000
  County divorce rate 0.033 (0.008) 0.0022 0.035 (0.009) 0.0022 0.033 (0.009) 0.0022
  County race 0.000 (0.001) 0.0000 −0.001 (0.001) −0.0001 0.000 (0.001) 0.0000
  County male −0.035 (0.017) −0.0023 −0.041 (0.017) −0.0026 −0.035 (0.017) −0.0023
  Log-Likelihood −5,613.018 −5,543.940 −5,614.212

Notes: The sample consists of 37,662 observations for 3,298 men. Standard errors, shown in parentheses, account for nonindependence across observations for a given man. Marginal effects are computed at the gender-specific sample means. Each specification also includes controls for current marital duration.

a

Total income, income share, and income correlation are based on predicted income rather than actual income.

Table 5 reveals that the estimated coefficient for RT in Specification 1 is large, positive, and precisely estimated for women; its estimated marginal effect is 0.0037 at the sample means. Table 6 reveals a much smaller and less precisely estimated effect for men, with an estimated marginal effect of 0.0013. Given the unconditional, 12-month divorce rate of 0.04, this means a 1-point increase in relative risk tolerance—which corresponds to 1.8 and 1.0 standard deviations for women and men, respectively—is predicted to increase the probability of divorce by 9.25% for women and 3.25% for men. The model includes a broad array of variables representing the gains associated with both marriage and divorce, including controls for risk sharing and match quality that may themselves be affected by an individual’s level of risk tolerance. Thus, we believe a plausible interpretation of the estimated effect of RT is that it represents the risk premium associated with divorce. The predicted probability of divorce increases in RT because the more risk tolerant a person is, the smaller is her risk premium—that is, smaller is the amount by which the expected gains to divorce must exceed the expected gains to marriage to compensate her for the additional risk inherent in divorce. The fact that the estimated effect is considerably larger for women than for men is consistent with the view that women tend to face greater income risk than men upon divorcing because of women’s reliance on income sources (husband’s earnings, alimony, child support) that are highly unpredictable.

In Specification 2 in Tables 5 and 6, we replace total income, the individual’s share of total income, and the within-couple income correlation with predicted values, given that these variables are likely to be endogenous to the expected probability of divorce. The use of predicted income significantly alters our inferences about the effects of income-related factors on divorce but has only a minor effect on the estimated coefficients for RT: for women, the Specification 2 estimate (0.052) is 4% larger than the estimate in Specification 1, while for men, the Specification 2 estimate (0.023) is 21% larger than the corresponding Specification 1 estimate. In neither case is the cross-model difference in estimates statistically different from zero at conventional significance levels.

Specification 3 in Tables 5 and 6 is identical to Specification 1 except that RT is excluded. We find that the estimated coefficients for all variables—including assets, income correlation, the individual’s income share, age at marriage, and other factors that we expect to be correlated with risk preference—are virtually invariant to the inclusion or exclusion of RT. Risk preference has a nontrivial effect on the probability of divorce, yet omitting RT from the model does not cause other observed factors to “absorb” its effect.13

To compare the estimated effect of risk preference to the effects of other key determinants of divorce, we focus on the Specification 1 estimates in Tables 5 and 6. For women, a 1-point (1.8 SD) increase in RT is associated with a 9.25% increase in the predicted probability of divorce. An identical 9.25% marginal effect is generated by a $119,000 (0.5 SD) loss of assets, an 18–percentage-point (0.5 SD) increase in the woman’s income share, a 1.5-year (0.4 SD) reduction in her age at marriage, or a 12-month (1.0 SD) increase in the state’s mandatory separation requirement. For men, a 1-point (1.0 SD) increase in RT generates a 3.25% increase in the predicted probability of divorce, as does a $93,000 (0.4 SD) decrease in assets, a 13–percentage-point (0.6 SD) decrease in the man’s income share, or a 0.6-year (0.2 SD) decrease in the age at marriage. For both women and men, the estimated effect of a 1-point increase in RT is comparable in magnitude to the estimated effects of modest changes in assets, income, and age at marriage.

In contrast, the estimated effects of risk tolerance are dominated in magnitude by the impact of several background factors. Women without male children are predicted to be 16% (0.0064 / 0.04) more likely to divorce than are women with boys; the presence of children born prior to marriage is predicted to raise women’s divorce probabilities by 49%; women who lived apart from their mothers at age 14 are predicted to be 24% more likely to divorce than are women who lived with both biological parents; and women without “traditional views” (i.e., who disagree that “women are much happier if they stay at home and take care of their children”) are predicted to be 16% more likely to divorce than are their “traditional” counterparts. Although “traditional views” proves to have an unimportant effect on divorce probabilities for men, the absence of preschool children (ages 0–6) is predicted to raise a man’s divorce probability by 45%, and the presence of “premarriage” children is predicted to raise the same probability by 25%; men who lived apart from their mothers at age 14 are predicted to be 13% more likely to divorce than are men who lived with both biological parents.

To judge these magnitudes further, we compare predicted divorce probabilities for representative women and men at various marriage durations and with various levels of risk tolerance. In the top rows of Table 7, we consider representative women for whom all variables other than RT and duration equal the mean (if continuous) or mode (if discrete) based on subsamples of women with the same marriage duration. Table 7 reveals that in the fourth year of marriage, a representative woman with risk tolerance at the 10th percentile (based on the RT distribution for all women) has a .034 probability of divorcing in the next year, and an otherwise identical woman with risk tolerance at the 90th percentile has a predicted probability (.038) that is 11.8% higher. At all marriage durations shown in Table 7, an increase in risk tolerance from the 10th percentile to the 90th percentile is associated with a 10%–12% increase in the woman’s predicted probability of divorce. When we move from the median level of risk tolerance to the 90th percentile, the predicted probability of divorce increases by 8%–9%. At any marriage duration beyond 12 months, the most risk tolerant woman in our sample is roughly 80% more likely to divorce than her counterpart with the minimum level of risk tolerance. The middle rows of Table 7 reveal that the corresponding estimates are considerably smaller for men. Focusing on current durations of 37–48 months, the predicted probability of divorce increases by 9.1% (.022 to .024) when we move from the 10th percentile to the 90th percentile, by 4.3% when we move from the median to the 90th percentile, and by 54.5% when we move from the minimum to the maximum level of risk tolerance. These are smaller than the corresponding numbers for women despite the fact that each movement within the gender-specific risk distribution represents a larger absolute change in risk tolerance for men than for women.

Table 7.

Predicted Divorce Probabilities for Representative Women and Men

Sample Useda Marriage Duration (months) Level of Risk Tolerance (RT)b
Min. = .08 p10 = .11 Med. = .34 p90 = 1.03 Max. = 5.50
Women 13–24 .033 (.004) .033 (.005) .034 (.005) .037 (.005) .059 (.015)
Women 37–48 .034 (.005) .034 (.005) .035 (.005) .038 (.005) .060 (.016)
Women 61–72 .025 (.004) .025 (.004) .026 (.004) .028 (.004) .046 (.013)
Min. = .07 p10 = .13 Med. = .44 p90 = 1.64 Max. = 9.23

Men 13–24 .036 (.005) .036 (.005) .037 (.005) .039 (.006) .053 (.016)
Men 37–48 .022 (.004) .022 (.004) .023 (.004) .024 (.004) .034 (.011)
Men 61–72 .022 (.004) .022 (.004) .023 (.004) .024 (.004) .034 (.011)
Min. = .07 p10 = .12 Med. = .39 p90 = 1.32 Max. = 9.23

Women 37–48 .034 (.005) .034 (.005) .035 (.005) .039 (.005) .086 (.033)
Women + Men 37–48 .036 (.005) .036 (.005) .038 (.005) .042 (.006) .084 (.033)
Men 37–48 .022 (.004) .022 (.004) .023 (.004) .024 (.004) .034 (.011)
Women + Men 37–48 .025 (.004) .025 (.004) .025 (.004) .026 (.005) .037 (.013)

Note: Standard errors are in parentheses.

a

The representative woman or man under consideration is assigned mean values for all continuous variables (except RT) and modal values for all discrete variables (except duration), where means and modes are based on a sample of women, men, or women plus men in the given duration category.

b

The representative woman or man under consideration is assigned a level of RT equal to the minimum, 10th percentile, median, 90th percentile, and maximum values for the total sample of women (top rows), men (middle rows), or women plus men (bottom rows).

We have thus far assigned our representative individuals gender-specific values of each covariate, including RT. In the bottom rows of Table 7, we consider identical levels of risk preference for both men and women. We compute one set of predicted probabilities for a representative woman and a representative man who continue to possess gender-specific mean/modal characteristics, and another set for an identical woman and man, both of whom are assigned mean/modal characteristics based on a pooled sample of men and women. Focusing on the (roughly) 1-point increase in RT that corresponds to a movement from the median to the 90th percentile within the pooled distribution, we find that a representative woman with the higher level of risk tolerance has a 3.9% predicted probability of divorce in the next year, which is 11.4% higher than the predicted probability for her counterpart with a median level of risk tolerance. Among men, the corresponding change in predicted divorce probabilities is 4.3%. When we instead consider identical changes in risk tolerance for identical men and women, we find that a 1-point increase in RT (from the median to the 90th percentile) is associated with a 16.7% increase in the predicted probability of divorce for women and a 4.0% increase for men. In short, women are more responsive than observationally equivalent men to a given change in risk preference. This finding is consistent with the notion that divorce is riskier for women than for men.

Robustness Checks

Although our risk premium interpretation of the role of RT appears plausible, the estimated effect can also reflect correlation between RT and unobserved components of the expected gains to marriage and divorce. Despite our inclusion of a rich set of proxies for the expected gains to marriage and divorce, components of these gains invariably go unmeasured. We cannot separate the “risk premium” effect of RT from the “errors in variables” effect, but in this subsection, we experiment with measureable factors to demonstrate that our findings are not influenced by correctable forms of model misspecification.

The invariance of each covariate’s estimated coefficient to the exclusion of RT (seen by comparing Specifications 1 and 3 in Tables 5 and 6) suggests that the estimated effects of risk preference in Specifications 1 and 2 are unlikely to reflect simple forms of misspecification, such as the omission of higher-order terms in income or assets. To substantiate this, in Table 8 we show the estimated coefficients for RT for a range of alternative specifications; the first row of Table 8 provides the Specification 1 estimates from Tables 5 and 6 to facilitate comparison.

Table 8.

Probit Estimates of Effects of Risk Tolerance on Probability of Divorce, Based on Alternative Specifications

Specification Women
Men
Coefficient SE Marginal Effect Coefficient SE Marginal Effect
1. From Tables 5 and 6 0.050 0.023 0.0037 0.019 0.015 0.0013
4. Add Quartic in Assetsa 0.049 0.023 0.0036 0.019 0.015 0.0013
5. Add Quartic in Total Incomea 0.049 0.023 0.0036 0.019 0.015 0.0013
6. Add Dummy Variables for Schooling Gapb 0.049 0.023 0.0036 0.020 0.015 0.0013
7. Add Own Schooling Dummy Variablesc 0.048 0.023 0.0036 0.023 0.015 0.0015
8. Childless Individuals Onlyd 0.050 0.043 0.0042 0.004 0.020 0.0005
9. Categorical Risk Variablese
  Risk Category 2 0.027 0.032 0.0024 0.028 0.036 0.0019
  Risk Category 3 0.064 0.038 0.0048 −0.013 0.042 −0.0009
  Risk Category 4 0.139 0.068 0.0114 0.124 0.052 0.0091

Note: The table shows estimated coefficients for RT in Specifications 1 and 4–8, and estimated coefficients for categorical risk variables in Specification 9.

a

Specifications 4 and 5 add three higher-order terms in Assets and Total income, respectively.

b

Replaces Schooling gap with three dummy variables indicating whether the individual’s highest grade completed is less than, equal to, or greater than the spouse’s.

c

Adds four dummy variables indicating whether the individual’s highest grade completed is 0–11, 12, 13–15, or 16 or more.

d

Reduces samples to childless individuals; samples sizes are 10,813 for women and 11,971 for men.

e

Replaces RT with dummy variables indicating whether average response to income gamble questions is Category 2, 3, or 4 (most risk tolerant); Category 1 (least risk tolerant) is the omitted group.

Specification 4 in Table 8 is identical to Specification 1 except for the addition of Assets2, Assets3, and Assets4. Any suspicion that the estimated effect of RT reflects misspecification of the asset effect is dispelled by the finding that Specifications 1 and 4 yield virtually identical estimated coefficients for RT. The same is true when we instead introduce a quartic function of total income in Specification 5. When we introduce more flexibility in the effect of schooling attainment—either by distinguishing whether the individual’s highest grade completed is greater than, equal to, or less than the spouse’s (Specification 6) or by adding four dummy variables to identify the individual’s highest grade completed (Specification 7)—the estimated coefficient for RT increases slightly for men. However, as with Specifications 4 and 5, we fail to reject the null hypothesis that the difference in parameter estimates is zero. These findings confirm that the estimated effect of RT does not reflect an overrestrictive parameterization of our divorce model.

We also ask whether the estimated effect of RT is sensitive to the presence of children in the household, given that levels of risk tolerance and the riskiness of divorce might be closely tied to child-rearing. To explore this issue, in Specification 8, we restrict the samples to childless individuals. For women, the estimated coefficient for RT in specification 8 is 0.050, which is identical to the Specification 1 estimate. For men, the estimated coefficient decreases from 0.019 to 0.004 (although the difference in point estimates is statistically insignificant), which is consistent with the notion that divorce is relatively low-risk for childless men.

In the final alternative specification presented in Table 8, we replace RT with the direct, categorical responses to the income gamble questions described earlier in the Data section. Although we prefer the computed variable RT to the raw responses for the reasons discussed in that section, it is important to establish that the positive relationship between RT and divorce probabilities does not arise solely from the procedure used to compute the variable.14

Table 8 reveals that for women, the estimated effects of risk tolerance are 0.027, 0.064, and 0.139 for Categories 2, 3, and 4, respectively. Although the estimated coefficient for Category 4 (which represents the highest level of risk tolerance) is the only one that is statistically different than zero at conventional significance levels, this specification reveals a positive relationship between categorical levels of risk tolerance and divorce probabilities that is qualitatively similar to what is found for specifications that include the computed variable RT. For men, we obtain small and imprecisely estimated coefficients for Categories 2 and 3, but a precisely estimated coefficient of 0.124 for Category 4. The estimates for Specification 9 support our conclusion that the relationship between risk tolerance and divorce probabilities is positive for everyone, but more pronounced and more precisely estimated for women than for men.

CONCLUSION

Beginning with Becker et al. (1977), researchers analyzing the decision to divorce have used a decision-making framework in which risk neutral agents choose the state (marriage or divorce) that maximizes expected utility. Most researchers have estimated a discrete choice model for the probability of divorce in which the covariates are proxies for the expected gains to marriage and divorce. In this study, we extend the orthodox divorce model by assuming that (1) agents are risk averse, (2) remaining married is a risky option, and (3) divorce is an even riskier option. We demonstrate that the familiar risk premium argument can be applied to this scenario: conditional on the expected gains to marriage and divorce, the probability of divorce increases in risk tolerance because highly risk averse individuals require a relatively large premium in order to accept the greater risk associated with divorce.

We assess the empirical relationship between risk tolerance and divorce decisions by using NLSY79 data to estimate gender-specific probit models of divorce. We control for a rich array of proxies for the gains to marriage and divorce, as well as a measure of the Arrow-Pratt coefficient of relative risk tolerance derived from responses to questions on the willingness to make hypothetical, large-stakes income gambles. We find that risk tolerance is an important determinant of divorce. With current marriage duration equal to 37–48 months and all other characteristics equal to gender-specific sample means and modes, the most risk tolerant woman in the sample is 76% more likely to divorce than is the least risk tolerant woman. A woman with risk tolerance equal to the 90th percentile is 11.8% more likely to divorce than is a woman whose risk tolerance equals the 10th percentile, and 8.6% more likely than a woman with the median level of risk tolerance. Among men, for whom divorce entails much less of an income gamble, a corresponding move from the median to the 90th percentile is associated with a 4.3% decrease in the predicted probability of divorce.

Our findings could reflect effects of unobserved components of the gains to marriage and divorce that are correlated with individual levels of risk tolerance. However, they are consistent with the risk premium interpretation and with the notion that divorce entails a greater income gamble for women than for men. If this risk premium interpretation is correct, then existing policies designed to raise the welfare of divorced women by improving the enforcement of child support agreements and providing income assistance to low-income, unmarried mothers may serve the additional purpose (by reducing the riskiness of the gamble) of enticing relatively risk averse women to end their marriages.

Acknowledgments

We gratefully acknowledge financial support from the Initiative in Population Research at Ohio State University and core support from a population research center grant (1 R21 HD047943-01) awarded by the National Institute of Child Health and Human Development. We thank Susan Brown, Isaac Meilijson, David Schmeidler, and Lucie Schmidt for helpful comments.

APPENDIX: COMPUTING RELATIVE RISK TOLERANCE

We use the model given by Eq. (5) in the Data section, along with data on age and categorical responses to the income gamble questions, to compute gender-specific maximum likelihood estimates for the parameters β, ᾱ, σα, and σu, which we then use to calculate each individual’s expected ρit at every age. In this appendix, we describe the sample log-likelihood function, provide the maximum likelihood estimates, and give expressions for the conditional expectation of ρit.

We form the sample log-likelihood functions for men and women by summing each individual’s log-likelihood function. Each individual’s contribution takes a different form depending on whether she provides responses to the income gamble question in one, two, or all three survey years (1993, 2002, and 2004). All NLSY79 respondents who answer the questions contribute to the likelihood function regardless of whether they appear in our “first marriage” samples. If individual i answers the income gamble questions in a single year t, the probability that her risk category (cit) is j (j = 1,2,3,4) is

P(cit=j|Ageit)=P(logρ_j<logρit<logρ¯j)=Φ(logρ¯jα¯βAGEitσα2+σu2)Φ(logρ_jα¯βAGEitσα2+σu2),

where ρ̲j and ρ̄j are the lower and upper bounds associated with risk category j(see foot note 8) and Φ is the univariate normal cumulative distribution function. If individual i answers the income gamble questions in years t and s, the probability that her risk category is j in year t and k in year s is

P(cit=j,cis=k|Ageit,Ageis)=P(logρ_j<logρit<logρ¯j,logρ_k<logρis<logρ¯k)=[{Φ(logρ¯jαiβAGEitσu)Φ(logρ_jαiβAGEitσu)×{Φ(logρ¯kαiβAGEisσu)Φ(logρ_kαiβAGEisσu)}]dF(αi).

If an individual answers the income gamble questions in all three years, we extend the preceding expression to define the probability that her risk category is j in year t, k in year s, and l in year r:

P(cit=j,cis=k,cir=l|AGEit,AGEis,AGEir)                =P(logρ_j<logρit<logρ¯j,logρ_k<logρis<logρ¯k,logρ_l<logρ_ir<logρ¯l)                =[{Φ(logρ¯jαiβAGEitσu)Φ(logρ_jαiβAGEitσu)}                    ×{Φ(logρ¯kαiβAGEisσu)Φ(logρ_kαiβAGEisσu)}                     ×{Φ(logρ¯lαiβAGEirσu)Φ(logρ_lαiβAGEirσu)}]dF(αi).

The maximum likelihood estimates that we compute are given in Table 1. We use these estimates to compute the expected relative risk tolerance for every individual i at any time τ, conditional on her categorical response to the income gamble questions, her age at the time(s) those questions were answered, and her age at τ. The computation of these conditional expectations depends on whether the individual responds to the income gamble questions once, twice, or all three times.

For an individual i whose response to the income gamble questions in year t (and no other year) places her in risk category j, her expected relative risk tolerance at time τ is

E(ρit|cit=j,AGEit,AGEiτ)=exp(α¯^+β^AGEiτ+12σ^α2)P(logρ_j<logρit+σ^α2<logρ¯j)P(logρ_j<logρit<logρ¯j).

If an individual answers the income gamble questions in years t and s, the expectation is

E(ρit|cit=j,cis=k,AGEit,AGEis,AGEiτ)    =exp(α¯^+β^AGEiτ+12σ^α2)P(logρ_j<logρit+σ^α2<logρ¯j,logρ_k<logρis+σ^α2<logρ¯k)P(logρ_j<logρit<logρ¯j,logρ_k<logρis<logρ¯k).

The preceding expression is extended accordingly for an individual who responds in all three years.

Footnotes

1.

Details on the income gamble questions are provided in the data section. The design and validity of these questions—which originated in the Health and Retirement Study—are discussed in Barsky et al. (1997) and Kimball, Sahm, and Shapiro (2008).

2.

Other sources of data on individual risk preferences include the Surveys of Consumers, Italy’s Survey of Household Income and Wealth, the Dutch Brabant Survey, and the Dutch DNB Household Survey.

3.

Becker et al. (1977:1143) implicitly acknowledged that marriage is risky when they claimed that “(t)he probability of divorce is smaller the greater the expected gain from marriage, and the smaller the variance of the distribution of unanticipated gains from marriage.” However, they did not explicitly consider the risky nature of divorce and, in fact, appeared to assume that agents are risk neutral.

4.

We do not attempt to measure the riskiness of divorce by comparing actual pre- and post-divorce income because risk is based on ex ante assessments and not ex post realizations. Stated differently, whether a woman ultimately “wins” or “loses” the income gamble inherent in divorce is not an indication of the risk she faced.

5.

Ross (1981) demonstrated that a mean-preserving spread does not guarantee that the risk premium is monotonic in the Arrow-Pratt index unless additional distributional assumptions are made. The distributional assumption of location-independent risk guarantees the monotonicity of the risk premium for every nondecreasing and concave utility function. In order to include risk lovers (for whom utility functions are nonconcave), we would have to assume the definition of riskiness proposed by Bickel and Lehmann (1979).

6.

If women self-insure against a potential divorce by increasing their labor supply (Greene and Quester 1982; Johnson and Skinner 1986; Stevenson 2007), relatively risk averse women may contribute a relatively high share of total household income—but this factor is readily measured.

7.

We focus on first marriages to simplify the analysis. Individuals in later marriages differ systematically from the “first married” in terms of age, the presence of children, asset levels, and levels of relative risk tolerance. It is likely that they also differ in important unobserved dimensions, such as match quality. We would not want to ignore these differences by combining all marriages into a single sample, yet exploring the differences goes beyond the scope of the current study.

8.

This particular example refers to an individual in risk Category 3. The lower and upper bounds for individuals in risk Categories 1, 2, and 4 are (0,0.27), (0.27,0.5), and (1.0,∞), respectively.

9.

We do not correct the standard errors in our probit model for sampling variation in RT because to our knowledge, analytic methods for computing standard errors for two-step models (e.g., Murphy and Topel 1985) cannot be extended to our model. Using bootstrap methods for a similar model, Kimball et al. (2008) demonstrated that sampling variance in the computed regressor has little effect on estimated standard errors and does not alter their inferences regarding statistical significance.

10.

We impute values when a respondent says that she has a particular asset or debt but does not report its value. If the item’s value is reported in an earlier and later interview, we use the closest-reported values to linearly interpolate the missing value. If multiple values are reported either before or after the missing year, we use estimated coefficients from a within-person regression of asset values on year to linearly extrapolate the missing value. This procedure is identical to the method used to create the total net worth variable in the NLSY79, although we take the additional step of imputing values for 1979–1984.

11.

We experimented with additional income variables used by Hess (2004) and others, including the mean income gap between the husband and wife, the ratio of their within-marriage income variances, and the level of each partner’s income variance. None had a statistically significant coefficient or a discernible effect on the estimated coefficient for RT.

13.

Moreover, a likelihood ratio test reveals that the exclusion of RT does not cause a substantial decrease in explanatory power. The same is true when we exclude other covariates (e.g., assets and premarital cohabitation) with statistically significant coefficients.

14.

The level of each individual’s computed RT depends on her responses to the income gamble questions in all three years (assuming the individual answered the questions in 1993, 2002, and 2004). For comparability, the categorical variables used in Specification 9 represent the individual’s (rounded) average response over all three years. For example, a woman whose responses place her in Categories 4, 3, and 3 is assigned Category 3.

REFERENCES

  1. Ahn T. “Attitudes Toward Risk and Self-employment of Young Workers”. Labour Economics. 2010;17:434–42. [Google Scholar]
  2. Axinn WG, Thornton A. “The Relationship Between Cohabitation and Divorce: Selectivity or Causal Inference?”. Demography. 1992;29:357–74. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Barsky RB, Kimball MS, Juster FT, Shapiro MD. “Preference Parameters and Behavioral Heterogeneity: An Experimental Approach in the Health and Retirement Study”. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1997;112:537–79. [Google Scholar]
  4. Becker GS. “A Theory of Marriage.”. In: Schultz TW, editor. The Economics of the Family: Marriage, Children, and Human Capital. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1974. pp. 299–344. [Google Scholar]
  5. Becker GS, Landes EM, Michael RT. “An Economic Analysis of Marital Instability”. Journal of Political Economy. 1977;85:1141–88. [Google Scholar]
  6. Bianchi SM, Subaiya L, Kahn JR. “The Gender Gap in the Economic Well-being of Nonresident Fathers and Custodial Mothers”. Demography. 1999;36:195–203. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Bickel PJ, Lehmann EL. “Descriptive Statistics for Nonparametric Models IV. Spread.”. In: Jurečková J, editor. Contributions to Statistics. Dordrecht: Reidel; Publishing: 1979. pp. 33–40. [Google Scholar]
  8. Brien MJ, Lillard LA, Stern S. “Cohabitation, Marriage, and Divorce in a Model of Match Quality”. International Economic Review. 2006;47:451–94. [Google Scholar]
  9. Bumpass LL, Martin TC, Sweet JA. “The Impact of Family Background and Early Marital Factors on Marital Disruption”. Journal of Family Issues. 1991;12:22–42. doi: 10.1177/019251391012001003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Burdett K, Coles MG. “Long-Term Partnership Formation: Marriage and Employment”. The Economic Journal. 1999;109:307–34. [Google Scholar]
  11. Cancian M, Danziger S, Gottschalk P. “Working Wives and Family Income Inequality Among Married Couples.”. In: Danziger S, Gottschalk P, editors. Uneven Tides: Rising Inequality in America. New York: Russell Sage Foundation; 1993. pp. 195–223. [Google Scholar]
  12. Charles KK, Stephens M., Jr “Job Displacement, Disability, and Divorce”. Journal of Labor Economics. 2004;22:489–522. [Google Scholar]
  13. Chateauneuf A, Cohen M, Meilijson I. “Four Notions of Mean-Preserving Increase in Risk, Risk Attitudes and Applications to the Rand-Dependent Expected Utility Model”. Journal of Mathematical Economics. 2004;40:547–71. [Google Scholar]
  14. Chiappori P-A, Reny PJ. “Matching to Share Risk”. 2006. Discussion paper Department of Economics, University of Chicago.
  15. Chiappori P-A, Weiss Y. “Divorce, Remarriage and Child Support”. Journal of Labor Economics. 2007;25:37–74. [Google Scholar]
  16. Ellman IM, Lohr SL. “Dissolving the Relationship Between Divorce Laws and Divorce Rates”. International Review of Law and Economics. 1998;18:341–59. [Google Scholar]
  17. Friedberg L. “Did Unilateral Divorce Raise Divorce Rates? Evidence From Panel Data”. American Economic Review. 1998;88:608–27. [Google Scholar]
  18. Greene WH, Quester AO. “Divorce Risk and Wives’ Labor Supply Behavior”. Social Science Quarterly. 1982;63:16–27. [Google Scholar]
  19. Hess GD. “Marriage and Consumption Insurance: What’s Love Got to Do With It?”. Journal of Political Economy. 2004;112:290–318. [Google Scholar]
  20. Hoffman SD, Duncan GJ. “The Effect of Incomes, Wages, and AFDC Benefits on Marital Disruption”. Journal of Human Resources. 1995;30:19–41. [Google Scholar]
  21. Jewitt I. “Choosing Between Risky Prospects: The Characterization of Comparative Statics Results, and Location Independent Risk”. Management Science. 1989;35:60–70. [Google Scholar]
  22. Johnson W, Skinner J. “Labor Supply and Marital Separation”. American Economic Review. 1986;76:455–69. [Google Scholar]
  23. Kimball MS, Sahm CR, Shapiro MD. “Imputing Risk Tolerance From Survey Responses”. Journal of the American Statistical Association. 2008;103:1028–38. doi: 10.1198/016214508000000139. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Kotlikoff LJ, Spivak A. “The Family as an Incomplete Annuities Market”. Journal of Political Economy. 1981;89:372–91. [Google Scholar]
  25. Landsberger M, Meilijson I. “The Generation Process and an Extension of Jewitt’s Location Independent Risk Concept”. Management Science. 1994;40:662–69. [Google Scholar]
  26. Lehrer EL, Chiswick C. “Religion as a Determinant of Marital Stability”. Demography. 1993;30:385–404. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Lichter DT, McLaughlin DK, Ribar DC. “Economic Restructuring and the Retreat From Marriage”. Social Science Research. 2002;31:230–56. [Google Scholar]
  28. Light A. “Gender Differences in the Marriage and Cohabitation Income Premium”. Demography. 2004;41:263–84. doi: 10.1353/dem.2004.0016. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  29. Lillard LA, Brien MJ, Waite LJ. “Premarital Cohabitation and Subsequent Marital Dissolution: A Matter of Self-selection?”. Demography. 1995;32:437–57. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Lundberg S, Rose E. “Child Gender and the Transition to Marriage”. Demography. 2003;40:333–50. doi: 10.1353/dem.2003.0015. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  31. Lundberg S, Pollak RA. “Separate Spheres Bargaining and the Marriage Market”. Journal of Political Economy. 1994;101:988–1010. [Google Scholar]
  32. Lundberg S, Pollak RA. “Bargaining and Distribution in Marriage”. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1996;10(4):139–58. [Google Scholar]
  33. Manser M, Brown M. “Marriage and Household Decision-Making: A Bargaining Analysis”. International Economic Review. 1980;21:31–44. [Google Scholar]
  34. McElroy MB, Horney MJ. “Nash-Bargained Household Decisions: Toward a Generalization of the Theory of Demand”. International Economic Review. 1981;22:333–49. [Google Scholar]
  35. Mechoulan S. “Divorce Laws and the Structure of the American Family”. Journal of Legal Studies. 2006;35:143–74. [Google Scholar]
  36. Moffitt RA. “Female Wages, Male Wages, and the Economic Gains to Marriage: The Basic Evidence.”. In: Waite LJ, editor. The Ties That Bind: Perspectives on Marriage and Cohabitation. New York: Aldine de Gruyter; 2000. pp. 302–19. [Google Scholar]
  37. Mortensen DT. “Matching: Finding a Partner for Life or Otherwise”. American Journal of Sociology. 1988;94:S215–S240. [Google Scholar]
  38. Murphy KM, Topel RH. “Estimation and Inference in Two-Step Econometric Models”. Journal of Business and Economic Statistics. 1985;3:88–97. [Google Scholar]
  39. Oppenheimer VK. “Women’s Employment and the Gain to Marriage: The Specialization and Trading Model”. Annual Review of Sociology. 1997;23:431–53. doi: 10.1146/annurev.soc.23.1.431. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. Peters HE. “Marriage and Divorce: Informational Constraints and Private Contracting”. American Economic Review. 1986;76:437–54. [Google Scholar]
  41. Pissarides CA. “Risk, Job Search, and Income Distribution”. Journal of Political Economy. 1974;82:1255–67. [Google Scholar]
  42. Pollak RA. National Bureau of Economic Research; Cambridge, MA: 2005. “Bargaining Power in Marriage: Earnings, Wage Rates and Household Production”. NBER Working Paper No 11239. [Google Scholar]
  43. Pratt JR. “Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large”. Econometrica. 1964;32:122–36. [Google Scholar]
  44. Rosenzweig MR, Stark O. “Consumption Smoothing, Migration, and Marriage: Evidence From Rural India”. Journal of Political Economy. 1989;97:905–26. [Google Scholar]
  45. Ross SA. “Some Stronger Measures of Risk Aversion in the Small and the Large With Applications”. Econometrica. 1981;49:621–38. [Google Scholar]
  46. Sahib PR, Gu X. “To Tie the Knot or Not: Cohabitation, Marriage and Individuals’ Attitudes to Risk”. Demographic Research. 2002;6:355–82. [Google Scholar]
  47. Sahm CR. “Stability of Risk Preference.”. 2007. Finance and Economics Discussion Series Paper 2007-66. Division of Research and Statistics and Monetary Affairs, Federal Reserve Board, Washington, DC.
  48. Schmidt LE. “Risk Preferences and the Timing of Marriage and Childbearing”. Demography. 2008;45:439–60. doi: 10.1353/dem.0.0005. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Spivey C. “Desperation or Desire? The Role of Risk Aversion in Marriage”. Economic Inquiry. 2010;48:499–516. [Google Scholar]
  50. Stevenson B. “The Impact of Divorce Laws on Marriage-Specific Capital”. Journal of Labor Economics. 2007;25:75–94. [Google Scholar]
  51. Weiss Y. “The Formation and Dissolution of Families: Why Marry? Who Marries Whom? And What Happens Upon Divorce?”. In: Rosenzweig MR, Stark O, editors. Handbook of Population and Family Economics. 1A. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science; 1997. pp. 81–123. [Google Scholar]
  52. Weiss Y, Willis RJ. “Match Quality, New Information, and Marital Dissolution”. Journal of Labor Economics. 1997;15:S293–S329. doi: 10.1086/209864. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  53. Wolfers J. “Did Unilateral Divorce Raise Divorce Rates? A Reconciliation and New Results”. American Economic Review. 2006;96:1805–20. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Demography are provided here courtesy of The Population Association of America

RESOURCES