Abstract
This paper considers psychotic symptoms in terms of false inferences or beliefs. It is based on the notion that the brain is an inference machine that actively constructs hypotheses to explain or predict its sensations. This perspective provides a normative (Bayes-optimal) account of action and perception that emphasizes probabilistic representations; in particular, the confidence or precision of beliefs about the world. We will consider hallucinosis, abnormal eye movements, sensory attenuation deficits, catatonia, and delusions as various expressions of the same core pathology: namely, an aberrant encoding of precision. From a cognitive perspective, this represents a pernicious failure of metacognition (beliefs about beliefs) that can confound perceptual inference. In the embodied setting of active (Bayesian) inference, it can lead to behaviors that are paradoxically more accurate than Bayes-optimal behavior. Crucially, this normative account is accompanied by a neuronally plausible process theory based upon hierarchical predictive coding. In predictive coding, precision is thought to be encoded by the post-synaptic gain of neurons reporting prediction error. This suggests that both pervasive trait abnormalities and florid failures of inference in the psychotic state can be linked to factors controlling post-synaptic gain – such as NMDA receptor function and (dopaminergic) neuromodulation. We illustrate these points using biologically plausible simulations of perceptual synthesis, smooth pursuit eye movements and attribution of agency – that all use the same predictive coding scheme and pathology: namely, a reduction in the precision of prior beliefs, relative to sensory evidence.
Keywords: free energy, active inference, precision, sensory attenuation, illusions, psychosis, schizophrenia
Introduction
This paper attempts to explain the positive and negative symptoms of schizophrenia in terms of false inference about states of the world producing sensations – and to link this explanation to neuromodulatory dysconnections at the synaptic level. In brief, we take a normative approach to action and perception – namely, active inference and the Bayesian brain hypothesis. We then consider neuronally plausible implementations of active inference to see how particular failures of neuromodulation would be expressed in terms of perceptual inference and behavior. The main conclusion is that a wide range of psychotic symptoms can be explained by a failure to represent the precision of beliefs about the world – and that this failure corresponds to abnormal neuromodulation of the post-synaptic gain of superficial pyramidal cells in cortical hierarchies. This may sound like a very specific assertion; however, there are many converging lines of evidence that point to this conclusion – lines that we try to draw together in this paper.
The basic idea is that faulty inference leads to false concepts (delusions) or percepts (hallucinations) and that this failure is due to a misallocation of precision to hierarchical representations in the brain. In what follows, we will refer to beliefs, inference, priors, and precision in a Bayesian sense. In this setting, a belief is a probability distribution over some unknown state or attribute. Beliefs, in this sense, may or may not be consciously accessible. A belief can be held with great precision, such that the probability distribution is concentrated over the most likely value – the mean or expectation. This means the precision (inverse variance) corresponds to the confidence or certainty associated with a belief. In Bayesian inference, beliefs prior to observing data are called prior beliefs, which are updated to posterior beliefs after seeing the data. This updating rests upon combining a prior belief with sensory evidence or the likelihood of the data. In hierarchical Bayesian inference, the sufficient statistics of a belief (like the expectation and precision) are themselves treated as unknown quantities. This means that one can have beliefs about beliefs; for example, one can have an expectation about a precision (c.f., expected uncertainty). Heuristically, this leads to the distinction between fixed and random effects in classical statistics; or between risk (known uncertainty) and ambiguity (unknown uncertainty) in economics. Beliefs about beliefs are inevitable in hierarchical inference and are sometimes referred to as empirical priors, because they provide constraints on beliefs at lower levels of the hierarchy. Behaviorally, precision and beliefs about precision (including subjective confidence in beliefs) are to some extent dissociable (Fleming et al., 2012). Beliefs about precision are particularly important in hierarchical Bayesian inference, because they can have a profound effect on posterior expectations – and inappropriate beliefs about precision can easily lead to false inference.
The nature of this failure can be understood intuitively by considering classical statistical inference: imagine that we are using a t-test to compare the mean of some data, against the null hypothesis that the mean is zero. The sample mean provides evidence against the null hypothesis in the form of a prediction error: namely, the sample mean minus the expectation under the null hypothesis. The sample mean provides evidence against the null but how much evidence? This can only be quantified in relation to the precision of the prediction error. The t-statistic is simply the prediction error weighted by its precision (i.e., divided by its standard error). If this precision-weighted prediction error is sufficiently large, one rejects the null hypothesis. Clearly, if we overestimate the precision of the data, the t-statistic will be too large and we expose ourselves to false positives. Analogous rules apply to Bayesian inference, in that the optimal combination of a prior belief with some evidence is a posterior belief whose mean is a mixture of the prior and data means, weighted according to their precision. If the precision of the data is overestimated, or if the precision of the prior is underestimated, the posterior expectation will shift from the prior mean to the data mean (Figure 1).
So how could this lead to false beliefs and delusions? The following scenario (Frith and Friston, 2012) illustrates this: imagine the temperature warning light in your car is too sensitive (precise), reporting the slightest fluctuations (prediction errors) above some temperature. You naturally infer that there is something wrong with your car and take it to the garage. However, they find no fault – and yet the warning light continues to flash. Your first instinct may be to suspect the garage has failed to identify the fault – and even to start to question the Good Garage Guide that recommended it. From your point of view, these are all plausible hypotheses that accommodate the evidence available to you. However, from the perspective of somebody who has never seen your warning light, your suspicions would have an irrational and slightly paranoid flavor. This anecdote illustrates how delusional systems may be elaborated as a consequence of imbuing sensory evidence with too much precision. Note that the primary pathology here is quintessentially metacognitive in nature: in the sense that it rests on a belief (the warning light reports precise information) about a belief (the engine is overheating). Crucially, there is no necessary impairment in forming predictions or prediction errors – the problem lies in the way they are used to inform inference or hypotheses.
In what follows, we will consider the brain as performing inference using predictive coding, in which the evidence for hypotheses is reported by precision-weighted prediction errors. In these schemes, certain neurons compare bottom-up inputs with top-down predictions to form a prediction error that is weighted in proportion to its expected precision. Crucially, this weighting corresponds to the gain or sensitivity of prediction error units. This means that abnormalities in the modulation of post-synaptic gain could, in principle, lead to false inferences of the sort described above. We will illustrate this in a concrete fashion using biologically plausible simulations of false inference, all of which use exactly the same predictive coding scheme and intervention; namely, a decrease in the precision (post-synaptic gain of prediction error units) at higher levels of cortical hierarchies, relative to the precision at sensory levels. Some of these simulations have been reported previously in different contexts (Friston and Kiebel, 2009a; Adams et al., 2012; Brown et al., in press). Here, we frame these simulations in terms of false inference and emphasize their common mechanisms. There are several other examples that we could have used; for example, the relationship between state-dependent precision and attention or the role of dopamine in encoding the precision of affordance and its effects on action selection. However, the examples chosen are sufficient to illustrate the diverse phenomenology that can be explained by one simple abnormality – a reduction in the precision of empirical prior beliefs, relative to sensory precision.
This paper focuses on false inference. However, the normative principles we appeal to cover both inference and learning. Neurobiologically, this corresponds to the distinction between updating neuronal representations in terms of synaptic activity and learning causal structure through updating synaptic efficacy (i.e., synaptic plasticity). The important thing here is that abnormal beliefs about precision also lead to false learning, which produces – and is produced by – false inference. This circular causality follows inevitably from the nature of inference, which induces posterior dependencies among estimates of hidden quantities in the world (encoded by synaptic activity and efficacy respectively). The point here is that a simple failure of neuromodulation (and implicit encoding of precision) can have far-reaching and knock-on effects that can be manifest at many different levels of perceptual inference, learning, and consequent behavior.
This paper comprises six sections. We start with a brief review of the symptoms and signs of schizophrenia, with a special focus on how trait and state abnormalities can be cast in terms of false inference. The second section reviews the psychopharmacology of psychosis with an emphasis on the synaptic (neuromodulatory) mechanisms that we suppose underlie false inference. The third establishes the normative theory (active inference) and its biological instantiation in the brain (generalized Bayesian filtering or predictive coding). The resulting scheme is used in the final three sections to illustrate failures of perceptual inference in the context of omission paradigms, abnormalities of active inference in the context of smooth pursuit eye movements and misattribution of agency in the context of deficits in sensory attenuation.
Psychosis and False Inference
In this section, we briefly review the state and trait abnormalities of schizophrenia to emphasize a common theme; namely, a failure of inference about the world that arises from an imbalance in the precision or confidence attributed to beliefs. We distinguish between state and trait abnormalities because the evidence suggests that trait abnormalities may be associated with a relative decrease in prior precision, while some state abnormalities can be explained by a (possibly compensatory) increase in prior precision (or reduction in sensory precision). In this setting, state abnormalities include the florid (Schneiderian or first rank) symptoms of acute psychosis, while trait abnormalities are more pervasive and subtle. The diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia are based largely on state abnormalities, because they are easily and reliably detected. These include:
Delusions and hallucinations: c.f., positive symptoms (Crow, 1980) and the reality distortion of chronic schizophrenia (Liddle, 1987).
Thought disorder and catatonia (World Health Organization, 1992; American Psychiatric Association, 2000), where formal thought disorder is also characteristic of the disorganization syndrome of chronic schizophrenia (Liddle, 1987). Other (as yet non-diagnostic) state abnormalities include:
Abnormalities of perceptual organization: in particular a decreased influence of context, leading to a loss of global (Gestalt) organization (Phillips and Silverstein, 2003). These abnormalities have not been found in first-degree relatives or before the first psychotic episode, and tend to covary with disorganization symptoms (reviewed in Silverstein and Keane, 2011). A decreased influence of context can sometimes lead to perceptions that are more veridical than those of normal subjects. Important examples here include a resistance to the hollow mask illusion – which is also state-dependent (Keane et al., in press) – and size-weight illusion (Williams et al., 2010).
These symptoms can occur episodically and – with the possible exception of catatonia-respond well to anti-dopaminergic drugs in the majority of patients. We use the term “trait” abnormalities to refer to more constant features of the disorder, which are less responsive to dopamine blockade (although these responses have not been explored as thoroughly as those of state symptoms). Some are found in first-degree relatives and high-risk groups, and may qualify as endophenotypes of schizophrenia. Despite their prevalence, they are less diagnostic because they are found in other diagnostic categories (and to some extent in the normal population). They include (among others):
Soft neurological signs: probably best exemplified by abnormalities of smooth pursuit eye movements (SPEM) as reviewed by O’Driscoll and Callahan (2008). These abnormalities are present in first-degree relatives (Calkins et al., 2008) and in drug naive first episode schizophrenics (Campion et al., 1992; Sweeney et al., 1994; Hutton et al., 1998), and may even be exacerbated by dopamine blockade (Hutton et al., 2001).
Abnormal event-related potentials: such as a larger P50 response to a repeated stimulus, and reduced P300 and mismatch negativity (MMN) responses to violations or oddball stimuli. Abnormal P50, P300, and MMN responses have also been demonstrated in first-degree relatives, and do not normalize with treatment (reviewed in Winterer and McCarley, 2011).
Anhedonia, cognitive impairments, and negative symptoms: such as loss of normal affect, experience of pleasure, motivation, and sociability are all found (subclinically) in first-degree relatives (Fanous et al., 2001; Jabben et al., 2010) to a greater or lesser degree (Johnstone et al., 1987; Mockler et al., 1997) and are notoriously resistant to anti-dopaminergic treatment.
Many trait abnormalities have been considered as the result of a failure to adequately predict sensory input, rendering all percepts surprising (e.g., the P50) and reducing differential responses to oddball stimuli (e.g., the MMN and P300). Predictive coding in particular has been used in recent formulations of these deficits in schizophrenia (Fletcher and Frith, 2009). Specifically, it is suggested that the main problem in schizophrenia lies not with the prediction of sensory input per se, but in the delicate balance of precision ascribed to prior beliefs and sensory evidence (Friston, 2005; Corlett et al., 2011). Later, we will use simulations to demonstrate how a relative increase in – or failure to attenuate – sensory precision can explain abnormal responses to surprising events.
In terms of cognitive paradigms, the “beads task” has been used to characterize formal beliefs and probabilistic reasoning in schizophrenic subjects. In this paradigm, subjects are told that red and green beads are drawn at random from an urn that contains (for example) 85% of one color and 15% of the other. The subject must decide which color predominates. In reality, all subjects are shown the same sequence of beads. In the draws to decision version of the task, the subject has to answer as soon as they are certain. In the probability estimates version, the subject can continue to draw and change their answer. Interestingly, delusional patients “jump to conclusions” in the first version, while they are more willing to revise their decision in light of contradictory evidence in the second (Garety and Freeman, 1999). Bayesian modeling suggests that jumping to conclusions may reflect greater “cognitive noise” in delusional patients (Moutoussis et al., 2011), which may speak to reduced precision of higher level (cognitive) representations and consequently a greater influence of new sensory evidence (Speechley et al., 2010).
Can state abnormalities also be explained by imbalances in the precisions of prior beliefs and sensations? The short answer is yes. For example, delusional mood describes a state in which patients feel the world is strange and has changed in some way – where their attention is drawn to apparently irrelevant stimuli and odd coincidences. A loss of precise prior beliefs is consistent with a sense of unpredictability and greater attention to sensory events. Indeed, this line of thinking has been used to explain the loss of Gestalt or central coherence in autism (Pellicano and Burr, 2012). In terms of formal models, the top-down control of sensory precision has been shown to explain several psychophysical and physiological aspects of attention (Feldman and Friston, 2010); thereby providing a formal link between precision and attention. The key insight from these models is that posterior beliefs about states of the world can direct attention to sensory features by top-down modulation of sensory precision. A failure of top-down attenuation of sensory precision (sensory attenuation) therefore fits comfortably with abnormalities of sensory attention in this context.
State abnormalities include the cardinal psychotic symptoms, such as hallucinations and delusions. Hallucinations could be understood as the result of an increase in the relative precision of prior beliefs, such that the posterior beliefs are impervious to contradictory – but imprecise – sensory evidence. This has been discussed as an explanation for visual hallucinosis in organic psychosyndromes (Friston, 2005). However, the hallucinations associated with psychosis may be better understood as a failure to attenuate the sensory consequences (corollary discharge) of self-made acts; for example, a failure to attenuate the auditory consequences of sub-vocal or inner speech (Frith et al., 1998; Allen et al., 2007). Delusions are probably more complex and their emergence may be better understood as secondary phenomena: several authors have proposed that they could arise as rational (Bayes-optimal) posterior beliefs that explain away precise sensory prediction errors: e.g., Fletcher and Frith (2009). These explanations relate to earlier “empiricist” accounts such as Maher (1974), Gray et al. (1991), and Kapur (2003), who emphasizes aberrant salience (c.f., sensory precision). Implicit in these secondary accounts is a compensatory increase in the precision of explanations for sensory cues that are imbued with too much precision or salience. This is consistent with their peculiar resistance to rational argument. In the final section, we will consider an example of a compensatory increase in the precision of high-level beliefs that is necessary to compensate for a failure of sensory attenuation.
Summary
In summary, the symptoms and signs of schizophrenia are not inconsistent with a reduction of high-level precision or a failure of sensory attenuation (the top-down attenuation of sensory precision), with compensatory (secondary) changes in the precision of (empirical) prior beliefs. In particular, some psychotic states may reflect a compensatory response to trait abnormalities that bias inference toward sensory evidence that is imbued with too much precision or salience. A further mechanistic dissociation between state and trait abnormalities is suggested by the fact that the former generally respond to antipsychotic (anti-dopaminergic) treatment, while trait abnormalities do not. Before considering the computational anatomy of hierarchical inference in the brain, we will briefly review the psychopharmacology and neuropathology of schizophrenia.
The Psychopharmacology of Precision
This section considers the neuromodulatory processes implicated in schizophrenia, with a special focus on the laminar specificity of cortical neuromodulation. Our premise here is that psychotic abnormalities are manifestations of false inference, caused by the aberrant encoding of precision. This precision is thought to be encoded by post-synaptic gain of neuronal populations reporting prediction errors – the principal or pyramidal cells of superficial cortical layers (Mumford, 1992; Feldman and Friston, 2010). Synaptic gain modulation is a change in the response amplitude of a neuron that is independent of its selectivity or receptive field characteristics (Salinas and Thier, 2000). In other words, post-synaptic gain is a factor that quantifies the effect of a presynaptic input on post-synaptic output (e.g., depolarization at the soma). Changes in synaptic gain are generally thought to be mediated by non-linear (e.g., multiplicative) synaptic mechanisms; for example, NMDA receptor activation.
Of all the receptors that determine synaptic gain, the most ubiquitous is the glutamatergic NMDA receptor (NMDA-R). NMDA-Rs have several important functions that are expressed over different timescales. First, they can drive (i.e., induce an excitatory post-synaptic potential) post-synaptic cells like other ionotropic glutamatergic (AMPA and Kainate) receptors. However, the driving effect of NMDA-Rs is only possible if the cell is already depolarized; otherwise, the NMDA-R is blocked by a magnesium ion. This non-linear property makes them synaptic coincidence detectors or “AND gates.” Second, NMDA-Rs have time constants that are much longer than that of AMPA-Rs and Kainate-Rs. This enables integration of synaptic inputs over tens to hundreds of milliseconds – increasing the gain of synaptic inputs to distal dendrites. Finally, NMDA-Rs are famous for their role in plasticity: at longer timescales, the influx of calcium ions through NMDA-R channels causes a cascade of intracellular events that result in long-term synaptic depression or potentiation (LTD or LTP). However, NMDA-Rs also have a major impact on the short-term plasticity of glutamatergic synapses. This is because they regulate the functional state and number of AMPA-Rs – by phosphorylation or by changing the trafficking of AMPA-R subunits to and from the cell membrane (Passafaro et al., 2001; Montgomery and Madison, 2004; Bagal et al., 2005). Together, these properties make a significant contribution to the dynamics of neural networks, especially to oscillatory behavior and sustained firing patterns (Durstewitz, 2009).
Other key determinants of synaptic gain are the classical neuromodulator receptors; e.g., dopamine (DA-Rs), acetylcholine (in particular muscarinic AChRs), and serotonin (5-HTRs). With the exception of nicotinic AChRs (which are ionotropic) these are all metabotropic receptors – they do not activate ion channels but are coupled to signal transduction mechanisms (via G proteins) that affect intracellular second messengers, such as cyclic adenosine monophosphate (cAMP) or cyclic guanosine monophosphate (cGMP). Fluctuations in cAMP/cGMP concentration affect the activity of protein kinases, which – through phosphorylation – alters neuronal excitability via changes in the production, surface expression or activity of voltage or ligand-gated ion channels, including the NMDA-R itself. This mechanism is also used by another glutamatergic receptor – with pronounced modulatory effects on synaptic gain – the metabotropic glutamate receptor (mGluR; De Pasquale and Sherman, 2012). It is important to note that DA-R subtypes have opposite effects on synaptic gain: D1R activation stimulates cAMP production and increases the excitability of depolarized neurons, whereas D2R activation inhibits cAMP production and reduces gain (reviewed in Frank, 2005).
Synaptic gain is not just determined by receptor activity but also by network dynamics, like the synchronization of fast oscillations, especially in the 40–100 Hz or gamma frequencies (c.f., synchronous gain: Chawla et al., 1999). The fast acting inhibitory γ-amino butyric acid receptor (GABAA-R) is instrumental in this synchronization process. In the cortex, a GABAergic (parvalbumin-positive basket cell or PVBC) interneuron contacts many pyramidal cells, which it transiently hyperpolarizes. When this hyperpolarization wears off, all the cortical pyramidal cells can then fire together, leading to synchronous firing across the network and oscillations as the cycle recurs (Gonzalez-Burgos and Lewis, 2012).
Abnormalities in at least three of these synaptic gain mechanisms have been proposed to be a primary pathology in schizophrenia – those of NMDA, GABA, and dopamine receptors. NMDA-Rs play a central role in theories of schizophrenia (Olney and Farber, 1995; Abi-Saab et al., 1998; Goff and Coyle, 2001; Stephan et al., 2006; Corlett et al., 2011). Studies of genetic risk in schizophrenia have highlighted the role of genes related to glutamatergic transmission, with GABA and dopamine related genes implicated to a lesser extent (Harrison and Weinberger, 2005; Stephan et al., 2006; Hall et al., 2009; Greenwood et al., 2012). Neuropathological evidence indicates abnormalities of the glutamate and GABA systems: both pre- and post-synaptic markers, morphometric, and biochemical measures of glutamatergic transmission are reduced, as is the expression of the GABA synthesizing enzyme glutamic acid decarboxylase (GAD), parvalbumin-immunoreactive GABAergic interneurons and their synaptic markers (reviewed in Harrison et al., 2011). These neuropathological changes are particularly apparent in hippocampus and frontal cortex, both at high levels in the cortical hierarchy (Felleman and Van Essen, 1991).
Conversely, the evidence for dopaminergic abnormalities in schizophrenia is neither neuropathological nor structural, but functional. The most widely replicated abnormality is that of elevated striatal dopamine availability – in acute psychoses of both schizophrenia (Laruelle et al., 1996; Breier et al., 1997) and epilepsy (Reith et al., 1994). A recent review concluded that dopamine dysregulation is more closely linked to the state of psychosis than the trait of schizophrenia (Howes and Kapur, 2009), although there are some important caveats: presynaptic dopamine is also raised to a lesser degree in those who are prone to psychosis but not floridly psychotic, and patients with symptoms resistant to dopamine blockade do not have elevated striatal dopamine synthesis (Demjaha et al., 2012).
Is aberrant glutamatergic and GABAergic transmission linked to the trait abnormalities of the previous section? The psychotomimetic effects of ketamine suggest a strong association. Ketamine blocks NMDA-Rs and also potentiates AMPA-R signaling, leading to decreased burst firing of pyramidal neurons, with subsequent impairment of activation of GABAergic interneurons (Shi and Zhang, 2003). Ketamine administration can reproduce a whole spectrum of trait phenomena: such as SPEM abnormalities (Radant et al., 1998; Weiler et al., 2000); impaired P50 suppression (Oranje et al., 2002); diminished P300 (Gunduz-Bruce et al., 2012); reduced MMN (Umbricht et al., 2000; Schmidt et al., 2012); cognitive impairments (Kantrowitz and Javitt, 2010); and negative symptoms (Krystal et al., 1994). In fact, the only trait phenomenon that ketamine does not reproduce is a reduced susceptibility to the hollow mask illusion (Passie et al., 2003). This is in contrast to dopaminergic agonists, which do not reproduce perceptual, SPEM (Reilly et al., 2008), P50 (Oranje et al., 2004) or MMN (Leung et al., 2007) abnormalities – and have only small effects on the P300 (Luthringer et al., 1999). Indeed, prefrontal D1R hypoactivity has been associated with cognitive deficits and negative symptoms in animal models (Goldman-Rakic et al., 2004).
Ketamine’s reproduction of state symptoms is less consistent: its effects include loss of perceptual organization (Uhlhaas et al., 2007) and induction of a delusional mood (Corlett et al., 2011), but it does not cause a loss of attenuation of self-induced sensations (PC Fletcher, personal communication) or lead to auditory verbal hallucinations. It is interesting to note that while the negative symptoms induced by ketamine are correlated with its NMDA-R binding, the positive symptoms are not (Stone et al., 2008). Conversely, D2R levels in cortical and striatal areas correlate with positive but not negative symptom scores (Kessler et al., 2009). Nevertheless, some trait-like phenomena can be reproduced by both ketamine and dopaminergic agonists, such as reduced latent inhibition (Young et al., 2005; Razoux et al., 2007), blocking (O’Tuathaigh et al., 2003; Freeman et al., 2013), and the body ownership illusion (Albrecht et al., 2011; Morgan et al., 2011). This is not surprising, as there are complex interactions between glutamatergic, GABAergic, and dopaminergic neurotransmission, within and between the brain stem, striatum, and prefrontal cortex (see Figure 2). For example, hypofunction of NMDA-Rs in cortical projections to the ventral tegmental area (which are themselves regulated by D2 autoreceptors, nACh-Rs, and 5-HT-Rs) are in a position to reduce the activity of mesofrontal D1R-projecting dopaminergic neurons (that potentiate prefrontal NMDA-Rs) and increase activity (via decreased GABAergic inhibition) of mesostriatal D2R-projecting neurons (Stephan et al., 2009). NMDA-Rs and D1Rs within the same cell potentiate each other in numerous ways (Cepeda and Levine, 2006). In the prefrontal cortex, NMDA-R impairments may lead to hypofunction of GABAergic PVBC’s, disinhibition of pyramidal cells, and reduced prefrontal gamma activity (Gonzalez-Burgos and Lewis, 2012). Alternatively, NMDA-R hypofunction could impact directly on the excitability of prefrontal pyramidal cells.
The neuropathology of schizophrenia is usually associated with higher cortical systems; e.g., prefrontal cortex and the medial temporal lobe. For example, perceptual deficits in schizophrenics (and normal subjects) have been shown to correlate with frontal and temporal volume loss (Dazzan et al., 2006). The hierarchical level of a cortical area is defined in terms of extrinsic (ascending and descending) connections that have a laminar specificity: ascending (extrinsic) projections target the granular layer 4, which sends forward (intrinsic) connections to (supragranular) layers 2 and 3. These then either send further forward (extrinsic) projections up to the next hierarchical level, or pass signals down via (infragranular) layers 5 and 6 to the level below. See Bastos et al. (2012) for a review of this canonical circuitry from the point of view of predictive coding. In prefrontal cortex – as in the rest of the cerebrum – NMDA-Rs are distributed throughout the cortical layers but are most concentrated in superficial layers 2 and 3 (Jansen et al., 1989), as are D1Rs (Lidow et al., 1991). By contrast, D2Rs are much less prevalent than D1Rs in the cortex (by an order of magnitude) and their peak concentration is in layer 5 (Lidow et al., 1991). Nevertheless, Opris et al. (2012) have recently shown in primates that cocaine (which increases dopaminergic transmission) reduces the activity of superficial pyramidal cells (perhaps via D2Rs) and thereby their synchronization with layer 5 pyramidal cells in the same minicolumn – impairing performance in a working memory task.
Many of the neuropathological changes in schizophrenia are found in supragranular layers 2 and 3, with additional abnormalities in layer 5: see Harrison et al. (2011) for a fuller treatment of this complex and sometimes inconsistent literature. In brief, the somal volume of layer 3 DLPFC pyramidal cells has been found to be reduced (Rajkowska et al., 1998; Pierri et al., 2001), and these neurons have smaller basal dendrites (Glantz and Lewis, 2000; Kalus et al., 2000) and lower dendritic spine density (Kolluri et al., 2005). These changes may be caused by the neurotrophic effects of reduced NMDA-R inputs (Rajan and Cline, 1998; Monfils and Teskey, 2004) and a loss of synaptic connectivity (Perrone-Bizzozero et al., 1996; Glantz and Lewis, 1997) – perhaps with the thalamus (Lewis et al., 2001) or association cortex (Sweet et al., 2007). Others have found losses of interneurons in layer 2 in both prefrontal and cingulate cortex (Benes et al., 1991) and smaller dendritic fields of prefrontal layer 5 pyramidal cells (Black et al., 2004). In the medial temporal lobe, most abnormalities are again found in the superficial layers; such as atypical clustering of neurons in layer 2 of entorhinal cortex (Jakob and Beckmann, 1986; Arnold et al., 1991; Falkai et al., 2000).
Summary
In summary, the main neuropathological abnormalities appear to be expressed in high hierarchical levels (prefrontal cortex and the medial temporal lobe), particularly in supragranular layers that contain superficial pyramidal cells. The main neuromodulatory (trait) abnormalities include the hypofunction of cortical NMDA-Rs and GABAergic neurons (and possibly D1Rs) – in contrast to the elevation of striatal D2R activity in (the state of) psychosis. In short, the neuropharmacological and neuropathological evidence points to abnormal neuromodulation of superficial pyramidal cells. This is important because – in predictive coding schemes – the post-synaptic gain of these cells encodes the precision of prediction error. The next section explains why this is the case, starting from basic principles.
Neurobiological Implementation of Active Inference
This section introduces the theory behind inference in the brain. This normative account provides key constraints on the functional (computational) anatomy of action and perception. This allows one to understand (and simulate) inference in a principled way – that is also grounded in neuroanatomy and neurophysiology. We will use the formalism below to simulate some of the schizophrenic abnormalities reviewed above. These simulations rest on descriptions of the neuronal processes (differential equations) that underwrite inference in the brain. These equations are based on three assumptions:
The brain minimizes the free energy of sensory inputs defined by a generative model.
The generative model used by the brain is hierarchical, non-linear, and dynamic.
Neuronal firing rates encode the expected state of the world, under this model.
The first assumption is the free energy principle, which leads to active inference in the embodied setting of action (Friston et al., 2010a). This provides a normative (Bayes-optimal) account of action and perception, in which both minimize a free energy bound on the (negative log) evidence for the brain’s model of the world. Free energy is a quantity from statistics that measures the quality of a model in terms of the probability that it could have generated observed outcomes. This means that minimizing free energy maximizes the Bayesian evidence for the generative model (Ballard et al., 1983; Hinton and van Camp, 1993; Dayan et al., 1995). The second assumption is motivated by noting that the world is both dynamic and non-linear and that hierarchical causal structure emerges inevitably from a separation of temporal scales (Ginzburg, 1955; Haken, 1983). The final assumption is the Laplace assumption that, in terms of neural codes, leads to the Laplace code that is arguably the simplest and most flexible of all neural codes (Friston, 2009).
Given these assumptions, one can simulate a whole variety of neuronal processes by specifying the particular equations that constitute the brain’s generative model. Action and perception are then specified completely by the above assumptions and can be implemented in a biologically plausible fashion. In brief, these simulations use differential equations that minimize the free energy of sensory input using a generalized gradient descent (Friston et al., 2010b).
(1) |
These coupled differential equations describe perception and action respectively. They say that neuronal activity encoding posterior expectations about (generalized) hidden states of the world and action a reduce free energy – where free energy is a function of (generalized) sensory inputs and neuronal activity. The first differential equation is known as generalized predictive coding or Bayesian filtering: see also Rao and Ballard (1999). The first term is a prediction based upon a differential matrix operator 𝒟 that returns the generalized motion of expected hidden states. The second (correction) term is usually expressed as a mixture of prediction errors that ensures the changes in posterior expectations are Bayes-optimal predictions about hidden states of the world. The second differential equation says that action also minimizes free energy. The differential equations above are coupled because sensory input depends upon action, which depends upon perception through the posterior expectations. This circular dependency leads to a sampling of sensory input that is both predicted and predictable, thereby minimizing free energy and, implicitly, prediction errors.
To perform neuronal simulations under this scheme, it is only necessary to integrate or solve Eq. 1 to simulate the neuronal dynamics that encode posterior expectations and associated action. Posterior expectations depend upon the brain’s generative model of the world, which we assume has the following hierarchical form:
(2) |
This equation describes a probability density over the sensory and hidden states that generate sensory input. Here, the hidden states have been divided into hidden states and causes (x(i), v(i)), with (i) denoting their level within the hierarchical model. Hidden states and causes are abstract variables that the brain uses to explain or predict sensations – like the motion of an object in the field of view. In these models, hidden causes link hierarchical levels, whereas hidden states link dynamics over time. Here (g(i), f (i)) are non-linear functions of hidden states and causes that generate hidden causes for the level below and – at the lowest level – sensory inputs. Random fluctuations in the motion of hidden states and causes enter each level of the hierarchy. Gaussian assumptions about these random fluctuations make the model probabilistic. They play the role of sensory noise at the first level and induce uncertainty at higher levels. The amplitudes of these random fluctuations are quantified by their precisions that may depend upon the hidden states or causes through their log precisions
Perception and predictive coding
Given the form of the generative model Eq. 2 we can now write down the differential Eq. 1 describing neuronal dynamics in terms of (precision weighted) prediction errors on the hidden causes and states. These errors represent the difference between posterior expectations and predicted values, under the generative model (using A × B: = ATB and omitting higher-order terms):
(3) |
Equation 3 can be derived by computing the free energy for the hierarchical model in Eq. 2 and inserting its gradients into Eq. 1. This produces a relatively simple update scheme, in which posterior expectations are driven by a mixture of prediction errors, where prediction errors are defined by the equations of the generative model.
It is difficult to overstate the generality of Eq. 3: its solutions grandfather nearly every known statistical estimation scheme, under parametric assumptions about additive or multiplicative noise (Friston, 2008). These range from ordinary least squares to advanced variational deconvolution schemes. The scheme is called generalized Bayesian filtering or predictive coding (Friston et al., 2010b). In neural network terms, Eq. 3 says that error units compute the difference between expectations at one level and predictions from the level above . Conversely, posterior expectations (encoded by the activity of state units) are driven by prediction errors from the same level and the level below. These constitute bottom-up and lateral messages that drive posterior expectations toward a better prediction to reduce the prediction error in the level below. This is the essence of recurrent message passing between hierarchical levels to optimize free energy or suppress prediction error: see Friston and Kiebel (2009b) and Feldman and Friston (2010) for a more detailed discussion. Crucially, in neurobiological implementations of this scheme, the sources of bottom-up prediction errors have to be superficial pyramidal cells, because it is these – and only these – cells that send forward (ascending) connections to higher cortical areas. Conversely, predictions are conveyed from deep pyramidal cells, by backward (descending) connections, to target the superficial pyramidal cells encoding prediction error (Mumford, 1992; Bastos et al., 2012): see Figure 3.
Note that the precisions depend on the expected hidden causes and states. We have proposed that this dependency mediates attention and action selection in hierarchical processing (Feldman and Friston, 2010; Friston et al., 2012). Equation 3 tells us that the (state-dependent) precisions modulate the responses of prediction error units to their presynaptic inputs. This modulation depends on the posterior expectations about the states and suggests something intuitive – attention is mediated by activity-dependent modulation of the synaptic gain of principal cells that convey sensory information (prediction error) from one cortical level to the next. This translates into a top-down control of synaptic gain in principal (superficial pyramidal) cells elaborating prediction errors and fits comfortably with the modulatory effects of top-down connections in cortical hierarchies that have been associated with attention and action selection.
Action
In active inference, posterior expectations elicit behavior by sending top-down predictions down the hierarchy that are unpacked into proprioceptive predictions at the level of the cranial nerve nuclei and spinal cord. These engage classical reflex arcs to suppress proprioceptive prediction errors and produce the predicted motor trajectory
(4) |
The reduction of action to classical reflexes follows because the only way that action can minimize free energy is to change sensory (proprioceptive) prediction errors by changing sensory signals; cf., the equilibrium point formulation of motor control (Feldman and Levin, 1995). In short, active inference can be regarded as equipping a generalized predictive coding scheme with classical reflex arcs: see Friston et al. (2009) and Adams et al. (2013) for details. The actual movements produced clearly depend upon top-down predictions that can have a deep and complex structure, as we will see later.
Summary
In summary, starting with the assumption that the brain is trying to maximize the evidence for its model of the world, one can derive plausible equations describing neuronal dynamics in terms of message passing among different levels of a (cortical) hierarchical model. These messages comprise precision-weighted prediction errors that are passed forward from one level to the next and top-down predictions that are reciprocated to minimize prediction error. In this scheme, precision is encoded by the gain of superficial pyramidal cells reporting prediction error, which is implicated in the synaptic pathology of schizophrenia. This is a straightforward consequence of the mathematical form of predictive coding and the fact that superficial pyramidal cells are the source of ascending connections in the brain. At the proprioceptive level, prediction errors can be reduced either by changing predictions (perception) or by changing sensations (action). In the last three sections, we use Eqs 3 and 4 to simulate active inference under a number of generative models, while manipulating the precision at different hierarchical levels. These models are described completely by the Eq. 2, which are provided in figures that summarize the generative model used in each example.
Perceptual Inference and Hallucinations
This section focuses on perceptual inference to show how reducing the precision at high levels of a generative model can confound perception and distort perceptual synthesis. We will examine a non-trivial problem; namely, recognizing structure and syntax in communication, using a well studied model – birdsong. This is an interesting problem because it calls upon both the dynamics modeled by hidden states and a hierarchical structure that entails a separation of temporal scales (Kiebel et al., 2009). We first describe our generative model of birdsong and then examine the sorts of inference that arise when prior precision is reduced. We then model a compensatory reduction in sensory precision. In brief, we will see a loss of responses to violations – of the sort that characterize psychotic traits (e.g., reduced MMN) – and the emergence of hallucinosis with compensatory changes in sensory precision.
Attractors in the brain
The basic idea behind the generative model in this section is that the environment unfolds as an ordered sequence of dynamics, whose equations of motion have an attractor manifold that contains sensory trajectories. Crucially, the shape of this manifold is itself changed by other dynamical systems that have their own attracting sets. If the brain has a generative model of these hierarchically coupled dynamics, then we would expect to see cascades of neuronal attractors (c.f., central pattern generators) that are trying to predict sensory input. In this hierarchical setting, one would expect higher attractors to predict the changing shape of lower attractors, thereby modeling a separation of temporal scales of the sort seen in language (e.g., from formants to phonemes, from phonemes to words, from words to phrases, from phrases to sentences, and so on).
The example used here deals with the generation and recognition of birdsongs (Laje and Mindlin, 2002). We imagine that birdsongs are produced by two time-varying control parameters that control the frequency and amplitude of vibrations of a songbird’s syrinx (see Figure 4). There has been an extensive effort using attractor models at the biomechanical level to understand the generation of birdsong; e.g., Laje et al. (2002). Here, we use attractors at higher levels to provide time-varying control over the resulting sonograms. To produce synthetic stimuli, we drove the syrinx with two states of a Lorenz attractor, one controlling the frequency (between 2 and 5 kHz) and the other controlling the amplitude or volume. The parameters of the Lorenz attractor were chosen to generate a short sequence of chirps every second or so. To endow the generative model with a hierarchical structure, we placed a second Lorenz attractor – whose dynamics were an order of magnitude slower – over the first. The states of the slower attractor entered as control parameters (the Rayleigh and Prandtl number) to control the shape of the lower attractor.
We generated a single song, corresponding roughly to a cycle of the higher attractor and then filtered the ensuing sonogram (summarized as peak amplitude and volume) using the message-passing scheme described in the previous section Eq. 3. The results are shown in Figure 4 (lower panels), in terms of the predicted sonogram and prediction error at the sensory level. These results show that – after several hundred milliseconds – the veridical hidden states and causes can be recovered and provide accurate predictions of auditory sensations. Note that the percept or predictions are not an exact copy of the stimulus – the mismatch is reflected in the prediction errors on the lower right. These prediction errors provide contextual guidance for posterior expectations about hidden causes and states. Note that prediction errors coincide with the onset of each chirp, where the prediction errors for the third chirp are more protracted – suggesting that this chirp was less easy to predict than the others.
Omission-related responses
To examine responses to surprising stimuli or violations – and how they depend upon precision – we repeated the simulation but omitted the last three chirps. The corresponding percepts are shown with their prediction errors in Figure 5 (top row). These results illustrate two important phenomena. First, there is a vigorous expression of prediction error with the first missing chirp. This reflects the dynamical nature of perception: at this point, there is no sensory input to predict and the prediction error is generated entirely by top-down predictions. Second, it can be seen that there is a transient (illusory) percept, when the missing chirp should have occurred. Its frequency is too low, but its timing is preserved in relation to the expected chirp. This is an interesting stimulation from the point of view of ERP studies of omission-related responses that provide clear evidence for the predictive capacity of the brain (e.g., Nordby et al., 1994; Yabe et al., 1997).
This simulation models neuronal responses to unpredicted or surprising stimuli of the sort used in oddball paradigms to elicit the MMN or P300. These electrophysiological markers are particularly pertinent here, because the same cells reporting prediction error (superficial pyramidal cells) are thought to be the primary source of electrophysiological measurements. In these simulations, the sensory log precision was two, the log precision of (first level) hidden states was eight and the log precision of second level prediction errors was high (16). These precisions correspond to the true uncertainty or amplitude of random fluctuations used to generate the song. So what would happen if we reduced the precision of prediction errors at the second level that provides top-down predictions about the syntax and timing of the chirps?
Precision and oddball responses
The middle row of Figure 5 shows the results of repeating the simulation when the log precision at the second level was reduced to two. This has two remarkable effects: first, there is a failure to detect the third chirp (that previously elicited the greatest prediction error – white arrow) and, second, there is a marked attenuation of the omission–related response. The explanation for these phenomena is straightforward: because we have reduced the precision at higher levels, there is less confidence in top-down predictions and therefore every stimulus is relatively surprising. In fact, the third stimulus is so unpredictable it is not perceived, eliciting a large prediction error (black arrow in the middle right panel). Similarly, a high amplitude prediction error is seen shortly afterward in response to the surprising omission. However, it is attenuated in comparison to responses under precise top-down predictions. This allows sensory evidence to resolve prediction errors more quickly, thereby reducing their amplitude. This may speak to the attenuation of oddball responses as a psychotic trait. In particular, the attenuation of the MMN can be seen in terms of the difference between the prediction errors to the omitted chirp, relative to the third (standard) chirp (red arrows). These simulations highlight an important but intuitive point: attenuated mismatch or violation responses in chronic schizophrenia may not reflect a failure to detect surprising events but reflect a failure to detect unsurprising (predictable) events. In other words, they may reflect the fact that every event is surprising. In summary, a reduced precision of (confidence in) top-down predictions means that everything is mildly surprising and may provide an explanation for the failure to confidently infer regularities in the sensorium (and for larger P50 responses to repeated stimuli). As noted above, abnormal P50, P300, and MMN responses have also been demonstrated in first-degree relatives, and do not normalize with anti-dopaminergic treatment (Winterer and McCarley, 2011) – consistent with their status as trait phenomena. So what would happen if we tried to compensate for reduced prior precision by reducing sensory precision?
Precision and hallucinations
The lower row of Figure 5 shows the results of the simulation with a compensatory reduction in sensory log precision from two to minus two. Here, the omission–related response is abolished; however there is a complete failure of perceptual inference, during the song and after its termination. Although the tempo of the percept is roughly the same as the stimulus, there is loss of frequency tracking and syntax. This false percept emerges because sensory information is not afforded the precision needed to constrain or entrain top-down predictions. The structured and autonomous nature of these predictions is an inevitable consequence of a generative model with deep structure – that is required to explain the dynamic and non-linear way in which our sensations are caused. The ensuing false inference can be associated with hallucinosis in the sense that there is a perceptual inference in the absence of sensory evidence. Clearly, the computational anatomy of hallucinations in the psychotic state is probably much more complicated – and specific to the domain of self-made acts (such as speech and movement). We will turn to the misattribution of agency in the final section. Here, it is sufficient to note that a compensatory reduction of sensory precision could produce hallucinosis of the sort seen in organic psychosyndromes. Note that the prediction error persists throughout the stimulus train and has, paradoxically, lower amplitude than in the previous simulations. This is because the prediction error is precision weighted – and we have reduced its precision.
Summary
In summary, we have used a fairly sophisticated generative model with dynamical and hierarchical structure to recognize sequences of simulated chirps in birdsong. This is a difficult Bayesian filtering problem that the brain seems to solve with ease. The key thing to take from these simulations is that some of the trait abnormalities associated with psychosis (schizophrenia) can be explained by a loss of precise top-down predictions – rendering everything relatively surprising (c.f., delusional mood), and reducing the difference between responses to standard and oddball stimuli. The loss of precise top-down (empirical) priors can also be invoked to explain a resistance to illusions (Silverstein and Keane, 2011) that depend upon prior beliefs. We will revisit this in the context of the force-matching illusion in the last section. One can compensate for relatively precise sensory prediction errors by reducing sensory precision – but at the expense of dissociating from the sensorium and false (hallucinatory) inference. This compensated state could be a metaphor for some psychotic states. Having said this, the fact that the hallucinations of schizophrenia respond to antipsychotics suggests that they are associated with a hyper-dopaminergic state and may involve a failure of sensory attenuation of corollary discharge (see last section). In the next section, we ask what would happen if perceptual deficits of this sort occurred during active inference and affected motor behavior.
Abnormalities of Smooth Pursuit Under Visual Occlusion
This section uses a generative model for smooth oculomotor pursuit to illustrate the soft neurological signs that result from changing the precision of prediction errors in active inference. This example is particularly pertinent to schizophrenia where, arguably, some of the most reproducible signs are found in terms of eye movements. To simulate anticipatory smooth pursuit eye movements, we require a hierarchical model that generates hidden motion. One such model is summarized in Figure 6 (see figure legend for details). In brief, this model produces smooth pursuit eye movements because it embodies prior beliefs that gaze and the target are attracted by the same invisible point v(1) in the visual field. Target motion then provides evidence that the attracting (invisible) point is moving, which induces posterior beliefs that the eye will be attracted to that moving point. These posterior beliefs create proprioceptive predictions that descend to the oculomotor system, where they are fulfilled by oculomotor reflexes (see Figure 6). Crucially, we also equipped the subject with (veridical) prior beliefs that the invisible point moves with sinusoidal motion (equations at the second level in Figure 6) – so that, during periods of visual occlusion, the subject can anticipate where the target will reappear. This part of the model constitutes the highest hierarchical level and allowed us to simulate smooth pursuit of a target with sinusoidal motion that passes temporarily behind a visual occluder.
Simulating psychopathology
We modeled a putative deficit in schizophrenia by reducing the precision on the prediction errors of hidden states at the second level. Lowering this precision (the precision of in Figure 6) reduces the contribution of prediction errors to the posterior expectations modeling (hidden) periodic motion of the target. This results in a slowing of the (prior beliefs about the) target trajectory, as confidence in the prediction errors about its motion falls. This would normally place more emphasis on bottom-up prediction errors to guide inference; however, during occlusion these prediction errors are not available and we should see a behavioral effect of reducing precision.
To test for these behavioral effects, we reduced the log precision on the second level from −1 to −1.25. Neurobiologically, this corresponds to a reduction in the post-synaptic gain of superficial pyramidal cells encoding prediction error in cortical areas responsible for representing regularities in target motion. Figure 7 shows the resulting active inference (upper panels) and trajectories of the target (solid black line) and eye (broken red lines) in the middle and bottom panels respectively. Comparison with the equivalent results under normal precision (broken black lines) reveals some characteristic properties of schizophrenic pursuit. First, with reduced precision, pursuit is disproportionately affected by target occlusion: at the end of occlusion, the lag behind the target is increases. This is despite the fact that when the target is visible and pursuit is stabilized, the tracking is normal (1200–1400 and 2000–2200 ms). This reproduces empirical findings in schizophrenia at modest speeds (see Thaker et al., 1999). Second, pursuit under reduced precision is less accurate on the third cycle than the first, consistent with a deficit in inferring the target trajectory. Indeed, it lags so much just prior to 2700 ms that it has to make a catch-up saccade when the target re-emerges (saccades exceed 30 °/s). Overall, these results are consistent with findings in schizophrenia that suggest an impaired ability to maintain veridical pursuit eye movements in the absence of visual information. Furthermore, they suggest that the computational mechanism that underlies this failure rests on a failure to assign precision or certainty to (empirical) prior beliefs about hidden trajectories.
The relative loss of certainty about top-down predictions may also explain the ability of schizophrenics to respond to unpredicted changes in direction of the target. To demonstrate this, we removed the occluder, decreased the target period to around 500 ms, and introduced an unexpected reversal in the motion of the target – at the beginning of the second cycle of motion (at around 780 ms). The results of these simulations are shown in Figure 8. The traces in black correspond to normal pursuit and the traces in red show the performance under reduced precision. Although the effect is small (as it is in real subjects – Hong et al., 2005), the schizophrenic simulation (red lines) shows more accurate pursuit performance, both in terms of the displacement between the target and center of gaze, and in terms of a slight reduction in the peak velocity during the compensatory eye movement – a movement that is nearly fast enough to be a saccade. These differences are highlighted by red circles.
Summary
In summary, a reduction in the precision of high-level prediction errors can account for both impaired smooth pursuit eye movements during occlusion and the paradoxical improvement of responses to unpredictable changes in target direction. This dissociation makes perfect sense from the point of view of the computational anatomy we have modeled here – reducing synaptic gain (precision) at high levels of a hierarchical predictive coding scheme reduces confidence in predictions that impairs performance when these predictions are needed (during occlusion) and that improves performance when they are not (during unpredicted motion). In the final simulations, we retain a focus on active inference but instead of attenuating high-level precision we examine the effects of failing to attenuate low-level sensory precision.
Sensory Attenuation, Attribution of Agency, and Delusions
This section uses a generative model of (somatosensory) sensations that could be generated internally or externally. This model is used to illustrate the perceptual consequences of sensory attenuation, in terms of estimating the magnitude of externally and internally generated events. In brief, we reproduce the force-matching illusion (Shergill et al., 2003, 2005) by yoking externally applied forces to the perceived level of self-generated forces. Finally, we demonstrate the disappearance of the illusion and the emergence of false inferences about (antagonistic) external forces, when there is a failure to attenuate sensory precision and a compensatory increase in the precision of empirical prior beliefs.
Active inference and sensory attenuation
Sensory attenuation refers to a decrease in the intensity of a perceived stimulus when it is self generated (Blakemore et al., 1998). We have suggested that sensory attenuation is necessary to allow reflex arcs to operate (Brown et al., in press). The argument is simple: proprioceptive prediction errors can only be resolved by moving – via motor reflexes – or by changing predictions. This means the effects of ascending prediction errors on posterior expectations must be attenuated to allow movement: if proprioceptive sensations are conveyed by ascending primary (Ia and Ib) sensory afferents with too much precision, then they would subvert descending predictions that create prediction errors and therefore prevent movement. It is therefore necessary to temporarily suspend the precision of sensory reafference to permit movement. If we associate the perceived intensity or detectability of the sensory consequences of action with a lower bound on their posterior confidence interval, attenuation of sensory precision provides a simple explanation for the attenuation of the perceived intensity of self-generated sensations. In what follows, we present simulations of sensory attenuation by simulating the force-match illusion and then demonstrate how overly precise prior beliefs can compensate for a failure of sensory attenuation but expose the actor to somatic delusions.
The generative process and model
Figure 9 summarizes the generative process and model (using the form of Eq. 2). This model is as simple as we could make it, while retaining the key ingredients that are required to demonstrate inference about or attribution of agency. The equations on the left describe the real world, while the equations on the right constitute the subject’s generative model. In the real world, there is one hidden state xi modeling self-generated force that is registered by both proprioceptive sp and somatosensory ss inputs. Externally generated forces ve are added to internally generated forces to provide somatosensory input. The key thing about this model is that somatosensory sensations are caused ambiguously, by either internally or externally generated forces: ss = xi + ve. The only way that the underlying cause of the sensations can be inferred is by reference to proprioceptive input – that is only generated internally. This is a very simple model, where the somatosensory input is used metaphorically to represent the sensory consequences of events that could be caused by self or others, while proprioceptive input represents signals that can only be caused by self-made acts. Active inference now compels the subject to infer the causes of its sensations.
The generative model used for this inference is shown on the right. In this model, internally and externally generated forces (xi, xe) are modeled symmetrically, where changes in both are attributed to internal and external hidden causes (vi, ve). The hidden causes trigger the dynamics associated with the hidden states, much like the push that sets a swing in motion. This means that proprioceptive and somatosensory inputs are explained in terms of hidden causes, where proprioceptive sensations are caused by internally generated forces and somatosensory consequences report a mixture of internal and external forces. Crucially, the precision afforded sensory prediction errors depends upon the internally generated force (and its hidden cause). This dependency is controlled by a parameter γ that mediates the attenuation of sensory precision: as internally generated forces rise, sensory precision falls, thereby attenuating the amplitude of (precision weighted) sensory prediction errors. These context or state-dependent changes in precision enable the agent to attend to sensory input, or not – depending upon the relative precision of prediction errors at the sensory and higher levels. This context sensitive sensory precision is shown in Figure 10 as π (cyan circles).
Functional anatomy
Figure 10 illustrates how this generative model could be transcribed into a plausible neuronal architecture. In this example, we have assigned sensory expectations and prediction errors to the thalamus, while corresponding expectations and prediction errors about hidden states (forces) are associated with the sensorimotor cortex. The expectations and prediction errors about the hidden causes of forces have been placed – somewhat agnostically – in the prefrontal cortex. Notice how proprioceptive predictions descend to the spinal cord to elicit output from alpha motor neurons (playing the role of proprioceptive prediction error units) that cause movements through a classical reflex arc. Red connections denote ascending prediction errors, black connections descending predictions (posterior expectations), and the cyan connection denotes descending neuromodulatory effects that mediate sensory attenuation. The ensuing hierarchy conforms to the functional form of the predictive coding scheme in Eq. 3. In this architecture, predictions based on expected states of the world can either be fulfilled by reflex arcs or they can be corrected by ascending sensory prediction errors. Which of these alternatives occurs depends on the relative precisions along each pathway – that are set by the descending modulatory connection to sensory prediction errors. We now use this model to demonstrate some key points.
Sensory attenuation and the force-matching illusion
To produce internally generated movements, we simply supplied the subject with prior beliefs that the internal hidden cause increased transiently to a value of one, with high sensory attenuation γ = 6. We then followed this self-generated movement with an exogenously generated force that matched the self-generated force. The left-hand panels in Figure 11 show the results of this simulation. The lower left panel shows the internal hidden cause (blue line) with relatively tight 90% confidence intervals (gray areas). Prior beliefs about this hidden cause excite posterior beliefs about internally generated forces, while at the same time attenuating the precision of sensory prediction errors. This is reflected by the rise in the posterior expectation of the internal force (blue line in the upper right panel) and the transient increase in the confidence interval about this expectation. The resulting proprioceptive predictions are fulfilled by action (bottom right panel) to produce the predicted sensations (upper left panel). Note that proprioceptive prediction (blue line) corresponds to somatosensory prediction (green line) and that both are close to the real values (broken black line). This simulation shows normal self-generated movement under permissive sensory attenuation.
The right-hand panels of Figure 11 show exactly the same results as in the left-hand panels; however here, we have yoked the exogenous force xe to the self-generated force xi perceived at 90% confidence (dotted line in the top right graph) – as opposed to the true force exerted by the subject. In other words, the external force corresponds to the force that would be reported by the subject to match the perceived force at 90% confidence. The 90% confidence interval was chosen as a proxy for the percept to reconcile the perceived intensity literature with results from signal detection paradigms (Cardoso-Leite et al., 2010). Experimental work in the auditory domain has demonstrated that perceived intensity can be attenuated by increasing sensory noise (decreasing precision) (Lochner and Burger, 1961; Richards, 1968). When coupled to the 90% confidence interval, the internally generated force is now much greater than the matched external force (shown on the upper left graph). This is the key finding in the force-matching illusion and is entirely consistent with sensory attenuation. In this setting, the loss of confidence in posterior estimates of hidden states that are self-generated translates into an illusory increase in the force applied, relative to the equivalent force in the absence of sensory attenuation.
We repeated these simulations under different levels of self-generated forces by modulating the prior beliefs about the internal hidden cause (from a half to twice the normal amplitude). The results are shown as the blue circles in the left panel of Figure 12, which plots the self-generated force against the yoked or matched external force with a corresponding 90% confidence interval. These results are remarkably similar to those obtained empirically (right panel – reproduced from Shergill et al., 2005) and reveal sensory attenuation through an illusory increase in the self-generated force, relative to matched forces over a wide range of forces. The red line in the left panel comes from the final simulations, in which we asked what would happen if subjects compensated for a failure in sensory attenuation by increasing the precision of their prior beliefs?
False inference and failures of sensory attenuation
We now demonstrate two pathologies of sensory attenuation: first, a loss of sensory attenuation resulting in a catatonic state and second, how compensation for such a loss could allow movement but result in a somatic delusion. The consequences of reducing sensory attenuation (from six to two) are illustrated in the left panels of Figure 13. Here, the loss of sensory attenuation maintains the precision of the hidden states above the precision of prior beliefs about hidden causes (lower left panel). This means that bottom-up sensory prediction errors predominate over top-down predictions and expectations about internally generated forces are profoundly suppressed. Because there are no predictions about proprioceptive changes, there is a consequent akinesia. This state is reminiscent of the catatonic symptoms of schizophrenia such as immobility, mutism, catalepsy and waxy flexibility, in which the patient may maintain a fixed posture for a long time, even though (in the case of waxy flexibility) their limbs can be moved easily by someone else.
We shall now examine how a loss of sensory attenuation might be compensated for by increasing the precision of prediction errors at higher levels in the hierarchy (by increasing the log precision of prediction errors on hidden states and causes by four log units). This compensatory increase is necessary for movement and ensures the precision of top-down predictions is greater than bottom-up sensory prediction errors. These manipulations permit movement but abolish the force-matching illusion, as indicated by the line of red circles in the left panel of Figure 12. One might ask – why don’t subjects adopt this strategy and use precise prior beliefs about hidden causes all the time?
The answer is evident in the right panels of Figure 13, which show the results of a simulation with low sensory attenuation and compensatory increases in precision at higher levels. Here, there is an almost perfect and precise inference about internally and externally generated sensations. However, there is a failure of inference about their hidden causes. This can be seen on the lower left, where the subject has falsely inferred an antagonistic external hidden cause that mirrors the internal hidden causes. Note that this false inference does not occur during normal sensory attenuation (see Figure 11), where the true external hidden cause always lies within the 90% confidence intervals. The reason for this false inference or delusion is simple: action is driven by proprioceptive prediction errors that always report less force than that predicted. However, when these prediction errors are very precise they need to be explained – and can only be explained by falsely inferring an opposing exogenous force. This only occurs when both the predictions and their consequences are deemed to be very precise. This false inference could be interpreted as a delusion in the same sense that the sensory attenuation is an illusion. Having said this, it should be noted that – from the point of view of the subject – its inferences are Bayes-optimal. It is only our attribution of the inference as false that gives it an illusory or delusionary aspect.
This simulation has some face validity in relation to empirical studies of the force-matching illusion. The illusion is attenuated in normal subjects that score highly on ratings of delusional beliefs (Teufel et al., 2010). Furthermore, subjects with schizophrenia – who are prone to positive symptoms like delusions – do not show the force-matching illusion (Shergill et al., 2005). In other words, there may be a trade-off between illusions at a perceptual level and delusions at a conceptual level that is mediated by a (failure of) sensory attenuation.
Summary
The ideas reviewed in this section suggest that attribution of agency – in an ambiguous situation – can be resolved by attenuating the precision of sensory evidence during movement: in other words, attending away from the consequences of self-made acts. When implemented in the context of active inference, this provides a Bayes-optimal explanation for sensory attenuation and attending illusions. The simulations show how exacerbations of a trait loss of sensory attenuation could subvert movement and even cause catatonia. This can be ameliorated by compensatory increases in high-level precision, which in turn necessarily induce false (delusional) inferences about agency. This is important, given the negative correlation between sensory attenuation and predisposition to delusional beliefs in normal subjects and the reduced force-matching illusion in schizophrenia. On a physiological level, increased dopaminergic transmission in the striatum could reflect a putative increase in high-level precision, compensating for hypofunction of cortical NMDA-Rs. In summary, we have shown how active inference can explain the fundamental role of sensory attenuation, and how its failure could lead to not only catatonic states but also compensatory changes that induce delusions. This is one illustration of how psychotic state abnormalities might be secondary compensations for trait abnormalities.
Conclusion
Bayesian computations enable inference and learning under uncertainty. Furthermore, they prescribe the optimal integration of prior expectations (amassed over a lifetime or indeed evolution) with the sensory evidence of a moment; this integration is optimal because it embodies the relative uncertainty (precision) of each source of information. For this reason, the accurate representation of precision in a hierarchical Bayesian scheme is crucial for inference. The aberrant encoding of precision can therefore lead to false inference by overweighting prior expectations or sensory evidence. This paper has described how various trait abnormalities in schizophrenia could result from a decrease in prior precision (or a failure to attenuate sensory precision); and how some psychotic states could result from compensatory increases in prior precision (or decreases in sensory precision). We have outlined several physiological mechanisms for encoding precision (such as neuromodulation and neuronal oscillations) that are abnormal in schizophrenia. Genetic and neuropathological evidence suggest that NMDA-R (and GABA to some extent) may play a role in trait abnormalities, whereas the physiological evidence points toward dopaminergic pathology in the psychotic state. Clearly, a strict dichotomy is unlikely, since these neurotransmitter systems have complex interactions.
Using a biologically plausible predictive coding scheme, we have shown how a reduction of high-level (prior) precision can account for two trait phenomena: abnormal ERP responses to predictable and unpredictable stimuli and SPEM abnormalities. We have also shown how a failure to attenuate sensory precision might explain a resistance to (force-matching) illusions and (in severe cases) catatonia. Using these model systems, we were able to explain the delusional and hallucinatory inference characteristic of the psychotic state by compensatory increases (resp. decreases) in prior (resp. sensory) precision.
One might ask how specific these “trait” and “state” simulations are to schizophrenia, as opposed to psychotic symptoms per se. An important point to take from the formal arguments in this paper is that the common factor underlying psychotic phenomena is computational, not physiological: i.e., the key to understanding these symptoms is as disorders of precision encoding, and not – for example – necessarily of a particular neuromodulator. Another important message is that these simulations undermine a clear division between “normal” and “psychotic” brains, as even bizarre phenomena such as somatic delusions can occur in a normal inferential architecture in which precision encoding is awry. To what extent the physiological (or pharmacological) causes of transient psychotic symptoms in healthy people overlap with similar symptoms in schizophrenia is an interesting question, which physiologically informed models may help us to address (Moran et al., 2011).
Simulations of the sort used above clearly require empirical validation: this should be possible as the models make quantitative predictions about the dynamics of cortical populations that can be tested with dynamic causal modeling (Friston et al., 2003). Indeed, dynamic causal modeling studies of schizophrenic subjects have already demonstrated changes in effective connectivity consistent with decreased high level – and increased low-level – precision in the hollow mask paradigm (Dima et al., 2009, 2010). We conclude with some of the many interesting and outstanding questions in the computational modeling of schizophrenia:
If NMDA-R and GABA transmitter systems are distributed evenly throughout the cortex, why does their pathology in schizophrenia seem to be restricted to high-level cortical areas such as the prefrontal cortex and temporal lobe? Pathology could be localized in high-level areas for genetic or developmental reasons. Alternatively, regional specificity could reflect interactions with ascending neuromodulatory projections – for example the mesocortical dopaminergic projections from the ventral tegmental area.
Second, could the elevated presynaptic striatal dopamine in the psychotic state (Howes and Kapur, 2009) reflect (or compensate for) a primary decrease in prefrontal precision due to NMDA-R hypofunction? Or could there be another factor that reflects the contribution of developmental and environmental stressors (Giovanoli et al., 2013) or a combination of the above.
Third, given that post-synaptic D2Rs reduce neuronal excitability, one might suppose that they decrease the precision of striatal prediction errors. The opposite may be true, however, as D2Rs are preferentially expressed in the indirect pathway (Figure 2), where their activation may increase cortical excitation by reducing activity in this inhibitory circuit (Fusar-Poli et al., 2011).
Fourth, as reductionist efforts to find the best explanatory level for schizophrenia have shifted from gene-based theories to brain circuit-based accounts, a better computational understanding of trait abnormalities might enable the rational design and testing of neuromodulatory therapies; particularly those which can alleviate the debilitating antipsychotic-resistant cognitive and negative symptoms. Likewise, model-based techniques might finesse diagnostic and treatment decisions for individual patients (as has been demonstrated in aphasic patients by Brodersen et al., 2011), if the actions of different neuromodulators (for example) are formalized with appropriate models (as in Moran et al., 2011).
Finally, schizophrenia is unlikely to be the only pathology of precision – it is notable that most current treatments for psychiatric disorders target neuromodulatory systems. Aberrant precision estimation may also prove to be a simple but powerful explanation for other psychiatric disorders; e.g., the loss of central coherence in autism (Pellicano and Burr, 2012). In future, many psychiatric disorders may be distinguished by their sites of – and causes of – variation in their encoding of precision; e.g., the precision of distributions over future action outcomes modeling helplessness in depression (Huys and Dayan, 2009).
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Acknowledgments
This work was funded by the Wellcome Trust. Klaas Enno Stephan would like to acknowledge support by the René and Susanne Braginsky Foundation. The authors would also like to thank Steve Silverstein for his very useful comments on the manuscript, and also our reviewers whose suggestions have improved the paper.
References
- Abi-Saab W. M., D’Souza D. C., Moghaddam B., Krystal J. H. (1998). The NMDA antagonist model for schizophrenia: promise and pitfalls. Pharmacopsychiatry 31 (Suppl. 2), 104–109 10.1055/s-2007-979354 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Adams R. A., Perrinet L. U., Friston K. (2012). Smooth pursuit and visual occlusion: active inference and oculomotor control in schizophrenia. PLoS ONE 7:e47502. 10.1371/journal.pone.0047502 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Adams R. A., Shipp S., Friston K. J. (2013). Predictions not commands: active inference in the motor system. Brain Struct. Funct. 218, 611–643 10.1007/s00429-012-0475-5 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Albrecht M. A., Martin-Iverson M. T., Price G., Lee J., Iyyalol R., Waters F. (2011). Dexamphetamine effects on separate constructs in the rubber hand illusion test. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 217, 39–50 10.1007/s00213-011-2255-y [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Allen P., Aleman A., McGuire P. K. (2007). Inner speech models of auditory verbal hallucinations: evidence from behavioural and neuroimaging studies. Int. Rev. Psychiatry 19, 407–415 10.1080/09540260701486498 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- American Psychiatric Association (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders: DSM-IV-TR, 4th Edn Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association [Google Scholar]
- Arnold S. E., Hyman B. T., Van Hoesen G. W., Damasio A. R. (1991). Some cytoarchitectural abnormalities of the entorhinal cortex in schizophrenia. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 48, 625–632 10.1001/archpsyc.1991.01810310043008 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bagal A. A., Kao J. P. Y., Tang C.-M., Thompson S. M. (2005). Long-term potentiation of exogenous glutamate responses at single dendritic spines. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102, 14434–14439 10.1073/pnas.0501956102 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Ballard D. H., Hinton G. E., Sejnowski T. J. (1983). Parallel visual computation. Nature 306, 21–26 10.1038/306021a0 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bastos A. M., Usrey W. M., Adams R. A., Mangun G. R., Fries P., Friston K. J. (2012). Canonical microcircuits for predictive coding. Neuron 76, 695–711 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.10.038 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Benes F. M., McSparren J., Bird E. D., SanGiovanni J. P., Vincent S. L. (1991). Deficits in small interneurons in prefrontal and cingulate cortices of schizophrenic and schizoaffective patients. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 48, 996–1001 10.1001/archpsyc.1991.01810350036005 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Black J. E., Kodish I. M., Grossman A. W., Klintsova A. Y., Orlovskaya D., Vostrikov V., et al. (2004). Pathology of layer V pyramidal neurons in the prefrontal cortex of patients with schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 161, 742–744 10.1176/appi.ajp.161.4.742 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Blakemore S. J., Wolpert D. M., Frith C. D. (1998). Central cancellation of self-produced tickle sensation. Nat. Neurosci. 1, 635–640 10.1038/2870 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Breier A., Su T. P., Saunders R., Carson R. E., Kolachana B. S., de Bartolomeis A., et al. (1997). Schizophrenia is associated with elevated amphetamine-induced synaptic dopamine concentrations: evidence from a novel positron emission tomography method. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 94, 2569–2574 10.1073/pnas.94.6.2569 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Brodersen K. H., Schofield T. M., Leff A. P., Ong C. S., Lomakina E. I., Buhmann J. M., et al. (2011). Generative embedding for model-based classification of fMRI data. PLoS Comput. Biol. 7:e1002079. 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002079 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Brown H., Adams R. A., Parees I., Edwards M., Friston K. (in press). Active inference, sensory attenuation and illusions. Cogn. Process. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Calkins M. E., Iacono W. G., Ones D. S. (2008). Eye movement dysfunction in first-degree relatives of patients with schizophrenia: a meta-analytic evaluation of candidate endophenotypes. Brain Cogn. 68, 436–461 10.1016/j.bandc.2008.09.001 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Campion D., Thibaut F., Denise P., Courtin P., Pottier M., Levillain D. (1992). SPEM impairment in drug-naive schizophrenic patients: evidence for a trait marker. Biol. Psychiatry 32, 891–902 10.1016/0006-3223(92)90178-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cardoso-Leite P., Mamassian P., Schütz-Bosbach S., Waszak F. (2010). A new look at sensory attenuation. Action-effect anticipation affects sensitivity, not response bias. Psychol. Sci. 21, 1740–1745 10.1177/0956797610389187 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Carlsson A., Waters N., Carlsson M. L. (1999). Neurotransmitter interactions in schizophrenia-therapeutic implications. Eur. Arch. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 249 (Suppl. 4), 37–43 10.1007/PL00014183 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cepeda C., Levine M. S. (2006). Where do you think you are going? The NMDA-D1 receptor trap. Sci. STKE 2006, e20 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Chawla D., Lumer E. D., Friston K. J. (1999). The relationship between synchronization among neuronal populations and their mean activity levels. Neural Comput. 11, 1389–1411 10.1162/089976699300016287 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Corlett P. R., Honey G. D., Krystal J. H., Fletcher P. C. (2011). Glutamatergic model psychoses: prediction error, learning, and inference. Neuropsychopharmacology 36, 294–315 10.1038/npp.2010.163 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Crow T. J. (1980). Molecular pathology of schizophrenia: more than one disease process? Br. Med. J. 280, 66–68 10.1136/bmj.280.6207.66 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dayan P., Hinton G. E., Neal R. M., Zemel R. S. (1995). The Helmholtz machine. Neural Comput. 7, 889–904 10.1162/neco.1995.7.5.889 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dazzan P., Morgan K. D., Chitnis X., Suckling J., Morgan C., Fearon P., et al. (2006). The structural brain correlates of neurological soft signs in healthy individuals. Cereb. Cortex 16, 1225–1231 10.1093/cercor/bhj063 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- De Pasquale R., Sherman S. M. (2012). Modulatory effects of metabotropic glutamate receptors on local cortical circuits. J. Neurosci. 32, 7364–7372 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0090-12.2012 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Demjaha A., Murray R. M., McGuire P. K., Kapur S., Howes O. D. (2012). Dopamine synthesis capacity in patients with treatment-resistant schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 169, 1203–1210 10.1176/appi.ajp.2012.12010144 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dima D., Dietrich D. E., Dillo W., Emrich H. M. (2010). Impaired top-down processes in schizophrenia: a DCM study of ERPs. Neuroimage 52, 824–832 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.12.086 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dima D., Roiser J. P., Dietrich D. E., Bonnemann C., Lanfermann H., Emrich H. M., et al. (2009). Understanding why patients with schizophrenia do not perceive the hollow-mask illusion using dynamic causal modelling. Neuroimage 46, 1180–1186 10.1016/j [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Durstewitz D. (2009). Implications of synaptic biophysics for recurrent network dynamics and active memory. Neural Netw. 22, 1189–1200 10.1016/j.neunet.2009.07.016 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Falkai P., Schneider-Axmann T., Honer W. G. (2000). Entorhinal cortex pre-alpha cell clusters in schizophrenia: quantitative evidence of a developmental abnormality. Biol. Psychiatry 47, 937–943 10.1016/S0006-3223(99)00250-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Fanous A., Gardner C., Walsh D., Kendler K. S. (2001). Relationship between positive and negative symptoms of schizophrenia and schizotypal symptoms in non-psychotic relatives. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 58, 669–673 10.1001/archpsyc.58.7.669 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Feldman A. G., Levin M. F. (1995). The origin and use of positional frames of reference in motor control. Behav. Brain Sci. 18, 723–744 10.1017/S0140525X0004070X [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Feldman H., Friston K. J. (2010). Attention, uncertainty, and free-energy. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 4:215 10.3389/fnhum.2010.00215 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Felleman D. J., Van Essen D. C. (1991). Distributed hierarchical processing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cereb. Cortex 1, 1–47 10.1093/cercor/1.1.1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Fleming S. M., Dolan R. J., Frith C. D. (2012). Metacognition: computation, biology and function. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 367, 1280–1286 10.1098/rstb.2012.0021 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Fletcher P. C., Frith C. D. (2009). Perceiving is believing: a Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 10, 48–58 10.1038/nrn2536 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Frank M. J. (2005). Dynamic dopamine modulation in the basal ganglia: a neurocomputational account of cognitive deficits in medicated and non-medicated Parkinsonism. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 17, 51–72 10.1162/0898929052880093 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Freeman T. P., Morgan C. J. A., Pepper F., Howes O. D., Stone J. M., Curran H. V. (2013). Associative blocking to reward-predicting cues is attenuated in ketamine users but can be modulated by images associated with drug use. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 225, 41–50 10.1007/s00213-012-2791-0 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. (2008). Hierarchical models in the brain. PLoS Comput. Biol. 4:e1000211. 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000211 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. (2009). The free-energy principle: a rough guide to the brain? Trends Cogn. Sci. (Regul. Ed.) 13, 293–301 10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K., Kiebel S. (2009a). Cortical circuits for perceptual inference. Neural Netw. 22, 1093–1104 10.1016/j.neunet.2009.07.023 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K., Kiebel S. (2009b). Predictive coding under the free-energy principle. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 364, 1211–1221 10.1098/rstb.2008.0300 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. J. (2005). Hallucinations and perceptual inference. Behav. Brain Sci. 28, 764–766 10.1017/S0140525X05290131 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. J., Daunizeau J., Kiebel S. J. (2009). Reinforcement learning or active inference? PLoS ONE 4:e6421. 10.1371/journal.pone.0006421 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. J., Daunizeau J., Kilner J., Kiebel S. J. (2010a). Action and behavior: a free-energy formulation. Biol. Cybern. 102, 227–260 10.1007/s00422-010-0364-z [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K., Stephan K., Li B., Daunizeau J. (2010b). Generalised filtering. Math. Probl. Eng. 2010, 1–35 10.1155/2010/621670 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. J., Harrison L., Penny W. (2003). Dynamic causal modelling. Neuroimage 19, 1273–1302 10.1016/S1053-8119(03)00202-7 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Friston K. J., Shiner T., Fitzgerald T., Galea J. M., Adams R., Brown H., et al. (2012). Dopamine, affordance and active inference. PLoS Comput. Biol. 8:e1002327. 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002327 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Frith C., Rees G., Friston K. (1998). Psychosis and the experience of self. Brain systems underlying self-monitoring. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 843, 170–178 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1998.tb08213.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Frith C. D., Friston K. J. (2012). “False perceptions and false beliefs: understanding schizophrenia,” in Working Group on Neurosciences and the Human Person: New Perspectives on Human Activities, The Pontifical academy of Sciences, 8–10 November 2012, Casina Pio IV [Google Scholar]
- Fusar-Poli P., Howes O. D., Allen P., Broome M., Valli I., Asselin M.-C., et al. (2011). Abnormal prefrontal activation directly related to pre-synaptic striatal dopamine dysfunction in people at clinical high risk for psychosis. Mol. Psychiatry 16, 67–75 10.1038/mp.2009.108 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Garety P. A., Freeman D. (1999). Cognitive approaches to delusions: a critical review of theories and evidence. Br. J. Clin. Psychol. 38 (pt. 2), 113–154 10.1348/014466599162700 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Ginzburg V. L. (1955). On the theory of superconductivity. Nuovo Cimento C 2, 1234–1250 10.1007/BF02731579 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Giovanoli S., Engler H., Engler A., Richetto J., Voget M., Willi R., et al. (2013). Stress in puberty unmasks latent neuropathological consequences of prenatal immune activation in mice. Science 339, 1095–1099 10.1126/science.1228261 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Glantz L. A., Lewis D. A. (1997). Reduction of synaptophysin immunoreactivity in the prefrontal cortex of subjects with schizophrenia. Regional and diagnostic specificity. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 54, 660–669 10.1001/archpsyc.1997.01830190088009 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Glantz L. A., Lewis D. A. (2000). Decreased dendritic spine density on prefrontal cortical pyramidal neurons in schizophrenia. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 57, 65–73 10.1001/archpsyc.57.1.65 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Goff D. C., Coyle J. T. (2001). The emerging role of glutamate in the pathophysiology and treatment of schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 158, 1367–1377 10.1176/appi.ajp.158.9.1367 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Goldman-Rakic P. S., Castner S. A., Svensson T. H., Siever L. J., Williams G. V. (2004). Targeting the dopamine D1 receptor in schizophrenia: insights for cognitive dysfunction. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 174, 3–16 10.1007/s00213-004-1793-y [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gonzalez-Burgos G., Lewis D. A. (2012). NMDA receptor hypofunction, parvalbumin-positive neurons, and cortical gamma oscillations in schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 38, 950–957 10.1093/schbul/sbs010 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gray J. A., Feldon J., Rawlins J. N. P., Hemsley D. R., Smith A. D. (1991). The neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Behav. Brain Sci. 14, 1–20 10.1017/S0140525X00065055 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Greenwood T. A., Light G. A., Swerdlow N. R., Radant A. D., Braff D. L. (2012). Association analysis of 94 candidate genes and schizophrenia-related endophenotypes. PLoS ONE 7:e29630. 10.1371/journal.pone.0029630 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gunduz-Bruce H., Reinhart R. M. G., Roach B. J., Gueorguieva R., Oliver S., D’Souza D. C., et al. (2012). Glutamatergic modulation of auditory information processing in the human brain. Biol. Psychiatry 71, 969–977 10.1016/j.biopsych.2011.09.031 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haken H. (1983). Synergetics: Introduction and Advanced Topics, 3rd Edn. Berlin: Springer [Google Scholar]
- Hall J., Romaniuk L., McIntosh A. M., Steele J. D., Johnstone E. C., Lawrie S. M. (2009). Associative learning and the genetics of schizophrenia. Trends Neurosci. 32, 359–365 10.1016/j.tins.2009.01.011 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Harrison P. J., Lewis D. A., Kleinman J. E. (2011). “Neuropathology of schizophrenia,” in Schizophrenia, eds Weinberger D. R., Harrison P. J. (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell; ), 372–392 [Google Scholar]
- Harrison P. J., Weinberger D. R. (2005). Schizophrenia genes, gene expression, and neuropathology: on the matter of their convergence. Mol. Psychiatry 10, 40–68; image 5. 10.1038/sj.mp.4001630 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hinton G. E., van Camp D. (1993). “Keeping the neural networks simple by minimizing the description length of the weights,” in Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Conference on Computational Learning Theory COLT ’93 (New York, NY: ACM; ), 5–13 Available at: http://doi.acm.org/10.1145/168304.168306 [accessed November 22, 2012] [Google Scholar]
- Hong L. E., Avila M. T., Thaker G. K. (2005). Response to unexpected target changes during sustained visual tracking in schizophrenic patients. Exp. Brain Res. 165, 125–131 10.1007/s00221-005-2276-z [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Howes O. D., Kapur S. (2009). The dopamine hypothesis of schizophrenia: version III – the final common pathway. Schizophr. Bull. 35, 549–562 10.1093/schbul/sbp006 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hutton S. B., Crawford T. J., Gibbins H., Cuthbert I., Barnes T. R., Kennard C., et al. (2001). Short and long term effects of antipsychotic medication on smooth pursuit eye tracking in schizophrenia. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 157, 284–291 10.1007/s002130100803 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hutton S. B., Crawford T. J., Puri B. K., Duncan L. J., Chapman M., Kennard C., et al. (1998). Smooth pursuit and saccadic abnormalities in first-episode schizophrenia. Psychol. Med. 28, 685–692 10.1017/S0033291798006722 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Huys Q. J. M., Dayan P. (2009). A Bayesian formulation of behavioral control. Cognition 113, 314–328 10.1016/j.cognition.2009.01.008 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jabben N., Arts B., van Os J., Krabbendam L. (2010). Neurocognitive functioning as intermediary phenotype and predictor of psychosocial functioning across the psychosis continuum: studies in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. J. Clin. Psychiatry 71, 764–774 10.4088/JCP.08m04837yel [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jakob H., Beckmann H. (1986). Prenatal developmental disturbances in the limbic allocortex in schizophrenics. J. Neural Transm. 65, 303–326 10.1007/BF01249090 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jansen K. L., Faull R. L., Dragunow M. (1989). Excitatory amino acid receptors in the human cerebral cortex: a quantitative autoradiographic study comparing the distributions of [3H]TCP, [3H]glycine, L-[3H]glutamate, [3H]AMPA and [3H]kainic acid binding sites. Neuroscience 32, 587–607 10.1016/0306-4522(89)90282-0 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Johnstone E. C., Owens D. G., Frith C. D., Crow T. J. (1987). The relative stability of positive and negative features in chronic schizophrenia. Br. J. Psychiatry 150, 60–64 10.1192/bjp.150.1.60 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kalus P., Müller T. J., Zuschratter W., Senitz D. (2000). The dendritic architecture of prefrontal pyramidal neurons in schizophrenic patients. Neuroreport 11, 3621–3625 10.1097/00001756-200011090-00044 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kantrowitz J. T., Javitt D. C. (2010). N-methyl-d-aspartate (NMDA) receptor dysfunction or dysregulation: the final common pathway on the road to schizophrenia? Brain Res. Bull. 83, 108–121 10.1016/j.brainresbull [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kapur S. (2003). Psychosis as a state of aberrant salience: a framework linking biology, phenomenology, and pharmacology in schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 160, 13–23 10.1176/appi.ajp.160.1.13 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Keane B. P., Silverstein S. M., Wang Y., Papathomas T. V. (in press). Reduced depth inversion illusions in schizophrenia are state specific and occur for multiple object types and viewing conditions. J. Abnorm. Psychol. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kessler R. M., Woodward N. D., Riccardi P., Li R., Ansari M. S., Anderson S., et al. (2009). Dopamine D2 receptor levels in striatum, thalamus, substantia nigra, limbic regions, and cortex in schizophrenic subjects. Biol. Psychiatry 65, 1024–1031 10.1016/j.biopsych.2008.12.029 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kiebel S. J., Daunizeau J., Friston K. J. (2009). Perception and hierarchical dynamics. Front. Neuroinform. 3:20 10.3389/neuro.11.020.2009 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kolluri N., Sun Z., Sampson A. R., Lewis D. A. (2005). Lamina-specific reductions in dendritic spine density in the prefrontal cortex of subjects with schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 162, 1200–1202 10.1176/appi.ajp.162.6.1200 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Krystal J. H., Karper L. P., Seibyl J. P., Freeman G. K., Delaney R., Bremner J. D., et al. (1994). Subanesthetic effects of the non-competitive NMDA antagonist, ketamine, in humans. Psychotomimetic, perceptual, cognitive, and neuroendocrine responses. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 51, 199–214 10.1001/archpsyc.1994.03950030035004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Laje R., Gardner T. J., Mindlin G. B. (2002). Neuromuscular control of vocalizations in birdsong: a model. Phys. Rev. E Stat. Nonlin. Soft Matter Phys. 65, 051921. 10.1103/PhysRevE.65.051921 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Laje R., Mindlin G. B. (2002). Diversity within a birdsong. Phys. Rev. Lett. 89, 288102. 10.1103/PhysRevLett.89.288102 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Laruelle M., Abi-Dargham A., van Dyck C. H., Gil R., D’Souza C. D., Erdos J., et al. (1996). Single photon emission computerized tomography imaging of amphetamine-induced dopamine release in drug-free schizophrenic subjects. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 93, 9235–9240 10.1073/pnas.93.17.9235 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Leung S., Croft R. J., Baldeweg T., Nathan P. J. (2007). Acute dopamine D(1) and D(2) receptor stimulation does not modulate mismatch negativity (MMN) in healthy human subjects. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 194, 443–451 10.1007/s00213-007-0865-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lewis D. A., Cruz D. A., Melchitzky D. S., Pierri J. N. (2001). Lamina-specific deficits in parvalbumin-immunoreactive varicosities in the prefrontal cortex of subjects with schizophrenia: evidence for fewer projections from the thalamus. Am. J. Psychiatry 158, 1411–1422 10.1176/appi.ajp.158.9.1411 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Liddle P. F. (1987). The symptoms of chronic schizophrenia. A re-examination of the positive-negative dichotomy. Br. J. Psychiatry 151, 145–151 10.1192/bjp.151.2.145 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lidow M. S., Goldman-Rakic P. S., Gallager D. W., Rakic P. (1991). Distribution of dopaminergic receptors in the primate cerebral cortex: quantitative autoradiographic analysis using [3H]raclopride, [3H]spiperone and [3H]SCH23390. Neuroscience 40, 657–671 10.1016/0306-4522(91)90003-7 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lisman J. E., Coyle J. T., Green R. W., Javitt D. C., Benes F. M., Heckers S., et al. (2008). Circuit-based framework for understanding neurotransmitter and risk gene interactions in schizophrenia. Trends Neurosci. 31, 234–242 10.1016/j.tins.2008.02.005 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lochner J. P. A., Burger J. F. (1961). Form of the Loudness function in the presence of masking noise. J. Acoust. Soc. Am. 33, 1705–1707 10.1121/1.1908548 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Luthringer R., Rinaudo G., Toussaint M., Bailey P., Muller G., Muzet A., et al. (1999). Electroencephalographic characterization of brain dopaminergic stimulation by apomorphine in healthy volunteers. Neuropsychobiology 39, 49–56 10.1159/000026560 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Maher B. A. (1974). Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. J. Individ. Psychol. 30, 98–113 [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mockler D., Riordan J., Sharma T. (1997). Memory and intellectual deficits do not decline with age in schizophrenia. Schizophr. Res. 26, 1–7 10.1016/S0920-9964(97)00031-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Monfils M.-H., Teskey G. C. (2004). Induction of long-term depression is associated with decreased dendritic length and spine density in layers III and V of sensorimotor neocortex. Synapse 53, 114–121 10.1002/syn.20039 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Montgomery J. M., Madison D. V. (2004). Discrete synaptic states define a major mechanism of synapse plasticity. Trends Neurosci. 27, 744–750 10.1016/j.tins.2004.10.006 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Moran R. J., Symmonds M., Stephan K. E., Friston K. J., Dolan R. J. (2011). An in vivo assay of synaptic function mediating human cognition. Curr. Biol. 21, 1320–1325 10.1016/j.cub.2011.06.053 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Morgan H. L., Turner D. C., Corlett P. R., Absalom A. R., Adapa R., Arana F. S., et al. (2011). Exploring the impact of ketamine on the experience of illusory body ownership. Biol. Psychiatry 69, 35–41 10.1016/j.biopsych.2010.07.032 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Morrison P. D. (2012). “5: the search for madness,” in Schizophrenia: The Final Frontier– A Festschrift for Robin M. Murray (Hove: Psychology Press; ), 71–85 Available at: http://books.google.co.uk/books?hl=en&lr=&id=A49Fm_9zfBAC&oi=fnd&pg=PA71&ots=fb6brPVa5S&sig=1XnMwcDROLDSEtxuJnhJNBiqqrg [accessed January 10, 2013] [Google Scholar]
- Moutoussis M., Bentall R. P., El-Deredy W., Dayan P. (2011). Bayesian modelling of jumping-to-conclusions bias in delusional patients. Cogn. Neuropsychiatry 16, 422–447 10.1080/13546805.2010.548678 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mumford D. (1992). On the computational architecture of the neocortex. II. The role of cortico-cortical loops. Biol. Cybern. 66, 241–251 10.1007/BF00198477 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nordby H., Hammerborg D., Roth W. T., Hugdahl K. (1994). ERPs for infrequent omissions and inclusions of stimulus elements. Psychophysiology 31, 544–552 10.1111/j.1469-8986.1994.tb02347.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- O’Driscoll G. A., Callahan B. L. (2008). Smooth pursuit in schizophrenia: a meta-analytic review of research since 1993. Brain Cogn. 68, 359–370 10.1016/j.bandc.2008.08.023 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Olney J. W., Farber N. B. (1995). Glutamate receptor dysfunction and schizophrenia. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 52, 998–1007 10.1001/archpsyc.1995.03950240016004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Opris I., Hampson R. E., Gerhardt G. A., Berger T. W., Deadwyler S. A. (2012). Columnar processing in primate pFC: evidence for executive control microcircuits. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 24, 2334–2347 10.1162/jocn_a_00307 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Oranje B., Gispen-de Wied C. C., Verbaten M. N., Kahn R. S. (2002). Modulating sensory gating in healthy volunteers: the effects of ketamine and haloperidol. Biol. Psychiatry 52, 887–895 10.1016/S0006-3223(02)01377-X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Oranje B., Gispen-de Wied C. C., Westenberg H. G. M., Kemner C., Verbaten M. N., Kahn R. S. (2004). Increasing dopaminergic activity: effects of L-dopa and bromocriptine on human sensory gating. J. Psychopharmacol. (Oxford) 18, 388–394 10.1177/026988110401800310 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- O’Tuathaigh C. M. P., Salum C., Young A. M. J., Pickering A. D., Joseph M. H., Moran P. M. (2003). The effect of amphetamine on Kamin blocking and overshadowing. Behav. Pharmacol. 14, 315–322 10.1097/01.fbp.0000080416.18561.3e [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Passafaro M., Piëch V., Sheng M. (2001). Subunit-specific temporal and spatial patterns of AMPA receptor exocytosis in hippocampal neurons. Nat. Neurosci. 4, 917–926 10.1038/nn0901-917 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Passie T., Karst M., Borsutzky M., Wiese B., Emrich H. M., Schneider U. (2003). Effects of different subanaesthetic doses of (S)-ketamine on psychopathology and binocular depth inversion in man. J. Psychopharmacol. (Oxford) 17, 51–56 10.1177/0269881103017001698 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Pellicano E., Burr D. (2012). When the world becomes “too real": a Bayesian explanation of autistic perception. Trends Cogn. Sci. (Regul. Ed.) 16, 504–510 10.1016/j.tics.2012.08.009 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Perrone-Bizzozero N. I., Sower A. C., Bird E. D., Benowitz L. I., Ivins K. J., Neve R. L. (1996). Levels of the growth-associated protein GAP-43 are selectively increased in association cortices in schizophrenia. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 93, 14182–14187 10.1073/pnas.93.24.14182 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Phillips W. A., Silverstein S. M. (2003). Convergence of biological and psychological perspectives on cognitive coordination in schizophrenia. Behav. Brain Sci. 26, 65–82 10.1017/S0140525X03000025 discussion 82–137. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Pierri J. N., Volk C. L., Auh S., Sampson A., Lewis D. A. (2001). Decreased somal size of deep layer 3 pyramidal neurons in the prefrontal cortex of subjects with schizophrenia. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 58, 466–473 10.1001/archpsyc.58.5.466 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Radant A. D., Bowdle T. A., Cowley D. S., Kharasch E. D., Roy-Byrne P. P. (1998). Does ketamine-mediated N-methyl-D-aspartate receptor antagonism cause schizophrenia-like oculomotor abnormalities? Neuropsychopharmacology 19, 434–444 10.1016/S0893-133X(98)00030-X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rajan I., Cline H. T. (1998). Glutamate receptor activity is required for normal development of tectal cell dendrites in vivo. J. Neurosci. 18, 7836–7846 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rajkowska G., Selemon L. D., Goldman-Rakic P. S. (1998). Neuronal and glial somal size in the prefrontal cortex: a postmortem morphometric study of schizophrenia and Huntington disease. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 55, 215–224 10.1001/archpsyc.55.3.215 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rao R. P., Ballard D. H. (1999). Predictive coding in the visual cortex: a functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nat. Neurosci. 2, 79–87 10.1038/4580 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Razoux F., Garcia R., Léna I. (2007). Ketamine, at a dose that disrupts motor behavior and latent inhibition, enhances prefrontal cortex synaptic efficacy and glutamate release in the nucleus accumbens. Neuropsychopharmacology 32, 719–727 10.1038/sj.npp.1301057 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Reilly J. L., Lencer R., Bishop J. R., Keedy S., Sweeney J. A. (2008). Pharmacological treatment effects on eye movement control. Brain Cogn. 68, 415–435 10.1016/j.bandc.2008.08.026 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Reith J., Benkelfat C., Sherwin A., Yasuhara Y., Kuwabara H., Andermann F., et al. (1994). Elevated dopa decarboxylase activity in living brain of patients with psychosis. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 91, 11651–11654 10.1073/pnas.91.24.11651 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Richards A. M. (1968). Monaural loudness functions under masking. J. Acoust. Soc. Am. 44, 599–605 10.1121/1.1911127 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Salinas E., Thier P. (2000). Gain modulation: a major computational principle of the central nervous system. Neuron 27, 15–21 10.1016/S0896-6273(00)00004-0 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt A., Bachmann R., Kometer M., Csomor P. A., Stephan K. E., Seifritz E., et al. (2012). Mismatch negativity encoding of prediction errors predicts s-ketamine-induced cognitive impairments. Neuropsychopharmacology 37, 865–875 10.1038/npp.2011.261 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Shergill S. S., Bays P. M., Frith C. D., Wolpert D. M. (2003). Two eyes for an eye: the neuroscience of force escalation. Science 301, 187. 10.1126/science.1085327 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Shergill S. S., Samson G., Bays P. M., Frith C. D., Wolpert D. M. (2005). Evidence for sensory prediction deficits in schizophrenia. Am. J. Psychiatry 162, 2384–2386 10.1176/appi.ajp.162.12.2384 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Shi W.-X., Zhang X.-X. (2003). Dendritic glutamate-induced bursting in the prefrontal cortex: further characterization and effects of phencyclidine. J. Pharmacol. Exp. Ther. 305, 680–687 10.1124/jpet.102.046359 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Silverstein S. M., Keane B. P. (2011). Perceptual organization impairment in schizophrenia and associated brain mechanisms: review of research from 2005 to 2010. Schizophr. Bull. 37, 690–699 10.1093/schbul/sbr052 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Simpson E. H., Kellendonk C., Kandel E. (2010). A possible role for the striatum in the pathogenesis of the cognitive symptoms of schizophrenia. Neuron 65, 585–596 10.1016/j.neuron.2010.02.014 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Speechley W. J., Whitman J. C., Woodward T. S. (2010). The contribution of hypersalience to the “jumping to conclusions” bias associated with delusions in schizophrenia. J. Psychiatry Neurosci. 35, 7–17 10.1503/jpn.090025 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stephan K. E., Baldeweg T., Friston K. J. (2006). Synaptic plasticity and dysconnection in schizophrenia. Biol. Psychiatry 59, 929–939 10.1016/j.biopsych.2005.10.005 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stephan K. E., Friston K. J., Frith C. D. (2009). Dysconnection in schizophrenia: from abnormal synaptic plasticity to failures of self-monitoring. Schizophr. Bull. 35, 509–527 10.1093/schbul/sbn176 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stone J. M., Erlandsson K., Arstad E., Squassante L., Teneggi V., Bressan R. A., et al. (2008). Relationship between ketamine-induced psychotic symptoms and NMDA receptor occupancy: a [(123)I]CNS-1261 SPET study. Psychopharmacology (Berl.) 197, 401–408 10.1007/s00213-007-1047-x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Sweeney J. A., Haas G. L., Li S., Weiden P. J. (1994). Selective effects of antipsychotic medications on eye-tracking performance in schizophrenia. Psychiatry Res. 54, 185–198 10.1016/0165-1781(94)90006-X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Sweet R. A., Bergen S. E., Sun Z., Marcsisin M. J., Sampson A. R., Lewis D. A. (2007). Anatomical evidence of impaired feedforward auditory processing in schizophrenia. Biol. Psychiatry 61, 854–864 10.1016/j.biopsych.2006.07.033 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Teufel C., Kingdon A., Ingram J. N., Wolpert D. M., Fletcher P. C. (2010). Deficits in sensory prediction are related to delusional ideation in healthy individuals. Neuropsychologia 48, 4169–4172 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.10.024 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Thaker G. K., Ross D. E., Buchanan R. W., Adami H. M., Medoff D. R. (1999). Smooth pursuit eye movements to extra-retinal motion signals: deficits in patients with schizophrenia. Psychiatry Res. 88, 209–219 10.1016/S0165-1781(99)00084-0 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Uhlhaas P. J., Millard I., Muetzelfeldt L., Curran H. V., Morgan C. J. A. (2007). Perceptual organization in ketamine users: preliminary evidence of deficits on night of drug use but not 3 days later. J. Psychopharmacol. (Oxford) 21, 347–352 10.1177/0269881107077739 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Umbricht D., Schmid L., Koller R., Vollenweider F. X., Hell D., Javitt D. C. (2000). Ketamine-induced deficits in auditory and visual context-dependent processing in healthy volunteers: implications for models of cognitive deficits in schizophrenia. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 57, 1139–1147 10.1001/archpsyc.57.12.1139 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Weiler M. A., Thaker G. K., Lahti A. C., Tamminga C. A. (2000). Ketamine effects on eye movements. Neuropsychopharmacology 23, 645–653 10.1016/S0893-133X(00)00156-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Williams L. E., Ramachandran V. S., Hubbard E. M., Braff D. L., Light G. A. (2010). Superior size-weight illusion performance in patients with schizophrenia: evidence for deficits in forward models. Schizophr. Res. 121, 101–106 10.1016/j.schres.2009.10.021 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Winterer G., McCarley R. W. (2011). “Electrophysiology of schizophrenia,” in Schizophrenia, eds Weinberger D. R., Harrison P. J. (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell; ), 311–333 [Google Scholar]
- World Health Organization (1992). ICD-10: International Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders: Clinical Descriptions and Diagnostic Guidelines. Geneva: World Health Organization [Google Scholar]
- Yabe H., Tervaniemi M., Reinikainen K., Näätänen R. (1997). Temporal window of integration revealed by MMN to sound omission. Neuroreport 8, 1971–1974 10.1097/00001756-199705260-00035 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Young A. M. J., Moran P. M., Joseph M. H. (2005). The role of dopamine in conditioning and latent inhibition: what, when, where and how? Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 29, 963–976 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2005.02.004 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]