Skip to main content
Nature Communications logoLink to Nature Communications
. 2014 Sep 26;5:4997. doi: 10.1038/ncomms5997

Is wave–particle objectivity compatible with determinism and locality?

Radu Ionicioiu 1,2, Thomas Jennewein 3,4, Robert B Mann 3,4,5, Daniel R Terno 6,a
PMCID: PMC5877209  PMID: 25256419

Abstract

Wave–particle duality, superposition and entanglement are among the most counterintuitive features of quantum theory. Their clash with our classical expectations motivated hidden-variable (HV) theories. With the emergence of quantum technologies, we can test experimentally the predictions of quantum theory versus HV theories and put strong restrictions on their key assumptions. Here, we study an entanglement-assisted version of the quantum delayed-choice experiment and show that the extension of HV to the controlling devices only exacerbates the contradiction. We compare HV theories that satisfy the conditions of objectivity (a property of photons being either particles or waves, but not both), determinism and local independence of hidden variables with quantum mechanics. Any two of the above conditions are compatible with it. The conflict becomes manifest when all three conditions are imposed and persists for any non-zero value of entanglement. We propose an experiment to test our conclusions.


Inline graphicArguably, the most counterintuitive aspects of quantum mechanics are indeterminacy of physical quantities and ambiguity of wave/particle behaviour prior to measurement. Terno et al. propose an experiment to test hidden-variable models that aim to restore objectivity and determinism in quantum theory.


Quantum mechanics is proverbially counterintuitive1,2. For many years, thought experiments were used to dissect its puzzling properties, while hidden-variable (HV) models strived to explain or even to remove them1,2,3,4. The development of quantum technologies5,6 enabled us not only to perform several former gedanken experiments1,2, but also to devise new ones7,8,9,10,11. One can gain new insights into quantum foundations by introducing quantum controlling devices10,11,12 into well-known experiments. This has led, for example, to a reinterpretation11,12,13,14 of Bohr’s complementarity principle15.

Wave–particle duality is best illustrated by the classic Wheeler delayed-choice experiment (WDC)16,17,18, Fig. 1a,b. A photon enters a Mach–Zehnder interferometer (MZI) and its trajectory is coherently split by the beamsplitter BS1 into an upper and a lower path. The upper path contains a variable phase shift φ. A random number generator controls the insertion (b=1) or removal (b=0) of a second beamsplitter BS2. If BS2 is present, the interferometer is closed and we observe an interference pattern depending on the phase shift φ. If BS2 is absent, the MZI is open and the detectors measure a constant probability distribution independent of φ. Thus, depending on the experimental setup, the photon behaves in two completely different ways. In the case of the closed MZI, the interference pattern suggests that the photon travelled along both paths simultaneously and interfered with itself at the second beamsplitter BS2, hence showing a wave-like behaviour. However, if the interferometer is open, since always only one of the two detectors fires, one is led to the conclusion that the photon travelled only one path, hence displaying a particle-like behaviour.

Figure 1. The evolution of the delayed-choice experiment.

Figure 1

(a) In Wheeler’s classic experiment, the second beamsplitter is inserted or removed after the photon is inside the interferometer; this prevents the photon from changing its mind16 about being a particle or a wave. The detectors observe either an interference pattern depending on the phase ϕ (wave behaviour), or an equal distribution of hits (particle behaviour). A quantum random number generator (QRNG) determines whether BS2 is inserted or not. Quantum networks: (b) in the classic delayed-choice experiment the QRNG is an auxiliary quantum system initially prepared in the equal superposition state Inline graphic and then measured. The Hadamard gate H is the quantum network equivalent of the beamsplitter; (c) delayed choice with a quantum control11; (d) entanglement-assisted quantum delayed-choice experiment19. The ancilla C is measured along the direction −α, equivalent to the application of a rotation Inline graphic before a measurement in the computational basis.

The complementarity of the interferometer setups required to observe particle or wave behaviour obscures the simultaneous presence of both properties, allowing the (objective) view that, at any moment of time, a photon can be either a particle or a wave. The WDC experiment uncovers the difficulty inherent in this view by randomly choosing whether or not to insert the second beamsplitter (BS2) after the photon enters the interferometer (Fig. 1a). This delayed choice prevents a possible causal link between the experimental setup and the photon’s behaviour: the photon should not know beforehand if it has to behave like a particle or like a wave.

The delayed-choice experiment with a quantum control (Fig. 1c) highlights the complexity of space–time ordering of events, once parts of the experimental setup become quantum systems11. The quantum-controlled delayed-choice experiment has been recently implemented in several different systems19,20,21,22,23. To ensure the quantum behaviour of the controlling device, one can either test the Bell inequality23 or use an entangled ancilla19.

The theoretical analysis of the quantum WDC involved so far a single binary HV λ describing the classical concepts of wave/particle. Here, we introduce a full HV description for both the photon A and the ancilla. We analyse the relationships between the concepts of determinism, wave–particle objectivity and local independence of HV in the entanglement-controlled delayed-choice experiment. We show that, when combined, these assumptions lead to predictions that are different from those of quantum mechanics, even if any two of them are compatible with it. We propose and discuss an experiment to test our conclusions.

Results

Notation

We use the conventions as in refs 3, 12; q(a, b,…) are the quantum-mechanical probability distributions and p(a, b, . . . , Λ) the predictions of HV theories with a HV Λ. We consider either a single HV Λ, which fully determines behaviour of the system, or refine it as Λ1, Λ2 pertaining to different parts of the system. For simplicity, we assume Λ is discrete; the analysis can be easily generalized to the continuous case.

Quantum system

The system we analyse consists of three qubits: a photon A and an entangled pair BC (Fig. 1d). We denote the measurement outcomes for the photon A as a=0, 1 and for the two ancilla qubits as b and c; the corresponding detectors are DA, DB and DC. The system is prepared in the initial state Inline graphic; for Inline graphic, BC is a maximally entangled EPR pair.

Photon A enters a MZI in which the second beamsplitter is quantum-controlled by qubit B. The third qubit C undergoes a σy rotation Inline graphic followed by a measurement in the computational basis. The state before the measurements is

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m4.jpg

The counting statistics that result from the particle-like state Inline graphic and the wave-like state Inline graphic are discussed below (equations (3 and 4) and Methods).

Constraints on HV theories

Our strategy is to show that q(a, b, c) cannot result from a probability distribution p(a, b, c, Λ) of a HV theory satisfying the requirements of wave–particle objectivity, local independence and determinism. Any viable HV theory should satisfy the adequacy condition: namely, it should reproduce the quantum statistics by summing over all HVs Λ:

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m7.jpg

We encapsulate the additional classical expectations into three assumptions (see Box 1 for the formal definitions of the concepts we consider in this section).

Wave–particle objectivity. We define particles and waves according to the experimental behaviour in an open, respectively closed, MZI11. A particle in an open interferometer (b=0) is insensitive to the phase shift in one of the arms and therefore has the statistics

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m84.jpg

In contrast, a wave in a closed MZI (b=1) shows interference

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m85.jpg

The sets Inline graphicp and Inline graphicw must be disjoint; otherwise, there are values of Λ that introduce wave–particle duality. Writing Inline graphicpInline graphicw=Inline graphic, the wave/particle property is expressed by a mapping λ:Inline graphic↦{p, w} and the sets Inline graphicp=λ−1(p), Inline graphicw=λ−1(w) are the pre-images of p, w under the function λ.

Determinism. The HV Λ determines the individual outcomes of the detection3. Specifically, for the setup of (Fig. 1d)

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m86.jpg

where the indicator function χ=1, if Λ belongs to some predetermined set, and χ=0 otherwise.

Local independence. The HV Λ are split into Λ1 and Λ2, and the prior probability distribution has a product structure

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m87.jpg

for some probability distributions f and F, where the subscripts 1 and 2, respectively, refer to the photon A and the pair BC. Such bilocal variables have been previously considered in ref. 29.

For a given photon, we require the property of being a particle or a wave to be objective (intrinsic), that is, to be unchanged during its lifetime. This condition selects from the set of adequate HV theories those models that have meaningful notions of particle and wave11. For each photon, the HV Λ should determine unambiguously if the photon is a particle or a wave, thus allowing the partition of the set of HVs Inline graphic into two disjoint subsets, Inline graphic=Inline graphicpInline graphicw, where the subscript indicates the property, particle or wave.

The particle (wave) properties are abstractions of the particle (wave) counting statistics in open (closed) MZI, respectively. The behaviour of a particle (wave) in a closed (open) MZI is not constrained; this allows for significant freedom in constructing HV theories. Experimentally, the wave or particle behaviour depends only on the photon and the settings of the MZI:

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m8.jpg

for all values of a, b, c and Λ.

By replacing the single-qubit ancilla with an entangled pair, one can take advantage of both the quantum control and the space-like separation between events. The rationale behind the third qubit C is that it allows us to choose the rotation angle α after both qubits A (the photon) and B (the quantum control) are detected. This is not possible in the standard quantum WDC11, Fig. 1c, where the quantum control B has to be prepared (by setting the angle α) before it interacts with A. As discussed in Methods, there is a unique assignment of probabilities that satisfies all the requirements of adequacy, wave–particle objectivity and determinism. Adopting this assignment, we reach the same level of incongruity as in ref. 11, since the probability p(λ) of photon A being a particle or a wave is determined by the entanglement between B and C,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m9.jpg

This incongruity becomes an impossibility when the photon A and the entangled pair BC are prepared independently. In this case, their HVs are generated independently; that is, a single HV Λ not only has the structure Λ=(Λ12), where the subscripts 1 and 2 refer to the photon A and the pair BC, respectively, but the prior probability distribution of HV has a product form. To realize this condition experimentally, we rely on the absence of the superluminal communication and a space-like separation of the two events.

Unlike the typical Bell-inequality scenarios, we have a single measurement setup which involves two independent HV distributions. Moreover, by performing the rotation Ry(α) and the detection DC sufficiently fast, such that the information about A and Λ1 cannot reach the detector DC, the detection outcome is determined only by Λ2. Since being a wave (particle) is assumed to be an objective property of A, λ=λ1) is a binary function of the HV Λ1 only.

Contradiction

We show in Methods that for η≠0, 1 (these two cases correspond to an always closed or opened MZI), the requirements of adequacy, wave–particle objectivity, determinism and local independence are satisfied only if

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m10.jpg

This proves our main theoretical result: determinism, local independence and wave–particle objectivity are not compatible with quantum mechanics for any α≠±π/4, ±3π/4. We will later discuss how exactly a HV theory that satisfies the three classical assumptions is inadequate.

Proposed experiment

In Fig. 2, we show the proposed experimental setup for the entanglement-controlled delayed-choice experiment. Two pump pulses (blue) are incident on two nonlinear crystals and generate via spontaneous parametric down-conversion two pairs of entangled photons (red). One of the photons is the trigger and the other three are the photons A, B, C, with BC being the entangled pair.

Figure 2. Proposed experimental setup.

Figure 2

Two space-like separated pump pulses (blue) generate, via spontaneous parametric down-conversion, two pairs of entangled photons (red). The first photon is the trigger and the other three the photons A, B, C. Inset: the quantum-controlled MZI. The optical delays in the three photon arms, τA, τB, τC can be adjusted to ensure the desired time ordering of the detection events.

Photons A and B are held in the lab (with appropriate delay lines) and together they implement the controlled MZI. The central element is the quantum switch, which is the controlled-Hadamard gate C(H)=(WI)C(Z)(WI), where Inline graphic. The photonic controlled-Z gate C(Z) is implemented with a partially polarizing beamsplitter and is done probabilistically via post-selection24,25. Optical wave plates perform single-qubit rotations (gates H, φ and W) on photon A. Photon C is sent through a channel at a distant location, then measured in a rotated basis. Two independent lasers generate the two photon pairs (Fig. 2 (refs 26, 27)); in this case, we can use equation (6) to describe independent probability distributions for Λ1 and Λ2.

Discussion

In this section, we consider how exactly a HV theory, which satisfies the three classical assumptions, fails the adequacy test. The interference pattern measured by the detector DA0 is IA(φ)=Tr(ρA|0〉〈0|), with ρA=TrBC|ψ〉〈ψ|, the reduced density matrix of photon A. The data can be postselected according to the outcome c resulting in IA|c. The visibility of the interference pattern (Methods) is V=(ImaxImin)/(Imax+Imin), where the min/max values are calculated with respect to φ. The postselected visibility for c=0 is (Fig. 3)

Figure 3. Visibility.

Figure 3

The visibilities VA|c=0 (yellow) and VA|c=1 (blue), are calculated in Methods. In HV theories, the visibility does not distinguish between the c=0, 1 cases. The inset illustrates this for Inline graphic, with the straight line representing the HV visibility prediction.

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m12.jpg

The full (non-postselected) visibility is VA=1−η and gives information about the initial entanglement of the BC pair. On the other hand, if one assumes that the HV are distributed according to equation (6) and satisfy the wave–particle objectivity and determinism, the visibility is independent of c,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m13.jpg

in contrast with the quantum-mechanical prediction (Fig. 3). Details of this calculation are in Methods.

This incompatibility between the basic tenets of HV theories and quantum mechanics has two remarkable features. First, the contradiction is revealed for any, arbitrarily small, amount of entanglement. This test is in sharp distinction with Bell-type experiments insofar as our result is free from inequalities. Wave–particle objectivity, revealed only statistically, is more intuitive and technically milder than the assumption of sharp values of quantum incompatible observables. Second, in our setup, any two of the classical ideas together are compatible with the quantum-mechanical predictions. This fact, and the way we arrived at the contradiction, invite questions concerning the internal consistency of classical concepts28.

Methods

Quantum-mechanical analysis

The initial state of photons A, B and C is

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m14.jpg

The ancilla qubits B and C are maximally entangled for Inline graphic. The final state before measurement is given by equation (1). From it, we calculate the quantum statistics q(a, b, c), where each of a, b, and c take the values {0, 1}. The probability distribution for c=0 is

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m16.jpg

where the four entries correspond to the values (a, b)=(00, 01, 10, 11). For c=1, we obtain

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m17.jpg

This in turn yields

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m18.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m19.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m20.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m21.jpg

For Inline graphic the probability distributions for b and c are equal. If Inline graphic, B and C are no longer maximally entangled and the symmetry between them is broken: a rotation α on C no longer corresponds to a rotation α on B. The conditional probabilities are

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m24.jpg

and from Bayes’ rule q(b|c)=q(c|b)q(b)/q(c).

Solution to the three constraints

We now show that it is possible to construct a HV model that is adequate, objective and deterministic. The unknown parameters at our disposal are 16 probabilities p(a, b, c, λ). These probabilities are derived from the underlying distribution p(Λ) summed over appropriate domains. At this stage, we do not enquire about the connection with the HV Λ. The probabilities p(a, b, c, λ) satisfy seven adequacy constraints, equations (13) and (14), plus the normalization constraint. The adequacy conditions can be written as

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m25.jpg

In addition, equation (7) and the standard rules for the conditional probabilities, such as

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m26.jpg

imply the existence of four additional constrains,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m27.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m28.jpg

The resulting linear system has a four-parameter family of solutions. However, a straightforward calculation shows that for all these solutions p4(a, b, c, λ), the resulting statistics in an open/closed MZI is independent of λ,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m29.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m30.jpg

that is, the statistics of DA is determined solely by the state of the interferometer.

We can avoid the reintroduction of wave–particle duality using a special solution

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m31.jpg

which imposes the bλ correlation (compare ref. 11). As a result,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m32.jpg

and since the probabilities are positive,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m33.jpg

the eight above probabilities are zero individually. The system appears overconstrained, but it still has a unique solution

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m34.jpg

In particular,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m35.jpg

Deriving the contradiction

In addition to the partition Inline graphic of according to the values of λ=p, w, we will use the decomposition of the set of HV according to the outcomes of DC. The two branches c=0, 1 correspond to the partition

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m36.jpg

where for Λ∈Inline graphicc, the outcome of DC is c. The assumption of local independence implies a Cartesian product structure

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m37.jpg

of the set of HV, where the subsets depend on the experimental setup. When the superscripts 1 and 2 on Inline graphic are redundant, we may omit them.

Now, we show that under the assumptions of adequacy and the three classical assumptions of the wave–particle objectivity, determinism and local independence, it is impossible to derive the solution p(a, b, c, λ) with any arrangement of the probabilities p(Λ). The probability of the outcome c satisfies

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m38.jpg

To simplify the calculations, we enumerate the variables Λ1,2 by the indices i, j, respectively. The domain Inline graphic corresponds, according to the hypothesis, to the index set Jc of Λ2, and the domains Inline graphic and Inline graphic to the index sets Ip and Iw of Λ1, respectively. In particular,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m42.jpg

for some Inline graphic. The prior distribution of HV and the domains of summation can depend on the parameters η, φ and α.

The putative behaviour of a wave (λ=w) in an open (b=0) interferometer and of a particle (λ=p) in a closed (b=1) one is characterized by two unknown distributions xij, iIw and yij, iIp, respectively

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m44.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m45.jpg

allowing for a possible dependence on a value of Λ2. The remaining two sets of variables are the probability distributions for b conditioned on the values of HVs Λ:

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m46.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m47.jpg

The requirement of adequacy means that the proposed HV theory reproduces the quantum statistics given above. For compactness, we refer to the probability of having the HV values Inline graphic, Inline graphic, as pij, using the same convention as for xij, yij, zij and υij. For c=0, we have

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m50.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m51.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m52.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m53.jpg

with analogous expressions for c=1. Adding and subtracting equations (39) and (41) we obtain, respectively

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m54.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m55.jpg

Adding equations (40) and (42) yields

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m56.jpg

which on substitution back into equation (40) results in

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m57.jpg

Four additional equations (giving a total of seven independent equations) are obtained for jJ1 with cos2 α↔sin2 α.

From equation (26), it follows that υij=0, iIw and zij=1, iIp. Hence, for c=0, only two equations are not automatically satisfied,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m58.jpg

The corresponding equations for c=1 are

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m59.jpg

which are in agreement with q(c), equation (18).

Now we use the product structure of the probability distribution, equation (6),

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m60.jpg

Using equations (28) and (30), we find that

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m61.jpg

Adding the pairs of equations in (47) and (48) and summing over the index i, we express the adequacy condition Inline graphic,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m63.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m64.jpg

but on the other hand, for η≠0, 1 summing over i in each of these four equations separately and using equation (50) we get

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m65.jpg

These equations can be satisfied for any η only if

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m66.jpg

resulting in the contradiction (for arbitrary α) cos 2α=0.

Experimental signature

The interference pattern measured by the detector DA is IA(φ)=Tr(ρA|0〉〈0|), with ρA=TrBC|ψ〉〈ψ| the reduced density matrix of photon A. The data can be postselected according to the outcome c resulting in IA|c. The intensity (signal) measured by detector DA for c=0 (and no post-selection on b) is:

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m67.jpg

giving the visibility

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m68.jpg

A similar calculation gives the visibility for c=1

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m69.jpg

The full intensity measured by detector DA (without postselecting on c) is Inline graphic and the corresponding visibility

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m71.jpg

Thus the visibility of detector DA gives information about the entanglement of the BC pair.

We now calculate the visibilities predicted by a non-trivial HV theory that is assumed to satisfy the three classical assumptions. Using equation (26), we rewrite the counting statistics as

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m72.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m73.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m74.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m75.jpg

For the product probability distribution above, we get

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m76.jpg
graphic file with name ncomms5997-m77.jpg

for j=0, 1 separately, where Inline graphic. As a result,

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m79.jpg

giving

graphic file with name ncomms5997-m80.jpg

for the visibilities in HV theories.

Additional information

How to cite this article: Ionicioiu, R. et al. Is wave–particle objectivity compatible with determinism and locality? Nat. Commun. 5:4997 doi: 10.1038/ncomms5997 (2014).

Acknowledgments

D.R.T. thanks Perimeter Institute for support and hospitality. We thank Lucas Céleri, Jim Cresser, Berge Englert, Peter Knight, Stojan Rebić, Valerio Scarani, Vlatko Vedral and Man-Hong Yung for discussions and critical comments and Alla Terno for help with visualization. This work was supported in part by the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada. R.I. acknowledges support from the Institute for Quantum Computing, University of Waterloo, Canada, where this work started.

The authors declare no competing financial interests.

Author contributions T.J. and R.I. conceived the entanglement-controlled protocol. D.R.T. performed the hidden-variable analysis. R.I. and T.J. produced the experimental design. R.B.M. and D.R.T. analysed the experimental signatures. All authors contributed to the writing of the manuscript. D.R.T. coordinated the project.

03/26/2018

The original HTML version of this Article had an incorrect article number of 3997; it should have been 4997. This has now been corrected in the HTML; the PDF version of the Article was correct from the time of publication.

References

  1. Wheeler J. A., Zurek W. H. (eds)Quantum Theory and Measurement Princeton Univ. Press (1984). [Google Scholar]
  2. Peres A. Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods Kluwer (1995). [Google Scholar]
  3. Brandenburger A. & Yanofsky N. A. Classification of hidden-variable properties. J. Phys. A 41, 425302 (2008). [Google Scholar]
  4. Englert B.-G. On quantum theory. Eur. J. Phys. D 67, 238 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  5. Nielsen M. A. & Chuang I. L. Quantum Computation and Quantum Information Cambridge Univ. Press (2000). [Google Scholar]
  6. Bruß D. & Leuchs G. Lectures on Quantum Information Wiley-VCH (2007). [Google Scholar]
  7. Scully O. M., Englert B.-G. & Walther H. Quantum optical tests of complementarity. Nature 351, 111–116 (1991). [Google Scholar]
  8. Schmidt L. Ph. H. et al. Momentum transfer to a free floating double slit: realization of a thought experiment from the Einstein-Bohr debates. Phys. Rev. Lett. 111, 103201 (2013). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Marshall W., Simon C., Penrose R. & Bouwmeester D. Towards quantum superpositions of a mirror. Phys. Rev. Lett. 91, 130401 (2003). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Arndt M. & Hornberger K. Testing the limits of quantum mechanical superpositions. Nat. Phys. 10, 271–275 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  11. Ionicioiu R. & Terno D. R. Proposal for a quantum delayed-choice experiment. Phys. Rev. Lett. 107, 230406 (2011). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  12. Céleri L. et al. Quantum control in foundational experiments. Found. Phys. 44, 576–587 (2014). [Google Scholar]
  13. Tang J.-S., Li Y.-L., Li C.-F. & Guo G.-C. Revisiting Bohr’s principle of complementarity using a quantum device. Phys. Rev. A 88, 014103 (2013). [Google Scholar]
  14. Qureshi T. Modified Two-Slit Experiments and Complementarity. Preprint at http://arxiv org/abs/1205.2207 (2012).
  15. Bohr N. inAlbert Einstein—Philosopher-Scientist (ed. Schlipp P. A. 200–241The Library of Living Philosophers (1949). [Google Scholar]
  16. Wheeler J. A. inQuantum Theory and Measurement (eds Wheeler J. A., Zurek W. H. 182–213Princeton Univ. Press (1984). [Google Scholar]
  17. Leggett A. J. inCompendium of Quantum Physics (eds Greenberger D., Hentschel K., Weinert F. 161–166Springer (2009). [Google Scholar]
  18. Jacques V. et al. Experimental realization of Wheeler’s delayed-choice Gedanken experiment. Science 315, 966–968 (2007). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Kaiser F. et al. Entanglement-enabled delayed choice experiment. Science 338, 637–640 (2012). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Roy S., Shukla A. & Mahesh T. S. NMR implementation of a quantum delayed-choice experiment. Phys. Rev. A 85, 022109 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  21. Auccaise R. et al. Experimental analysis of the quantum complementarity principle. Phys. Rev. A 85, 032121 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  22. Tang J.-S. et al. Realization of quantum Wheeler’s delayed-choice experiment. Nat. Photonics 6, 600–604 (2012). [Google Scholar]
  23. Peruzzo A. et al. A quantum delayed choice experiment. Science 338, 634–637 (2012). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Langford N. K. et al. Demonstration of a simple entangling optical gate and its use in Bell-state analysis. Phys. Rev. Lett. 95, 210504 (2005). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Kiesel N. et al. Linear optics controlled-phase gate made simple. Phys. Rev. Lett. 95, 210505 (2005). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Kaltenbaek R. et al. Experimental Interference of Independent Photons. Phys. Rev. Lett. 96, 240502 (2006). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Kaltenbaek R., Prevedel R., Aspelmeyer M. & Zeilinger A. High-fidelity entanglement swapping with fully independent sources. Phys. Rev. A 79, 040302(R) (2009). [Google Scholar]
  28. Ionicioiu R., Mann R. B. & Terno D. R. Determinism, independence and objectivity are inconsistent. Preprint at http://arxiv org/abs/1406.3963 (2014).
  29. Branciard C., Gisin N. & Pironio S. Characterizing the nonlocal correlations created via entanglement swapping. Phys. Rev. Lett. 104, 170401 (2010). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Nature Communications are provided here courtesy of Nature Publishing Group

RESOURCES