Abstract
Psychiatry has always been characterized by a range of different models of and approaches to mental disorder, which have sometimes brought progress in clinical practice, but have often also been accompanied by critique from within and without the field. Psychiatric nosology has been a particular focus of debate in recent decades; successive editions of the DSM and ICD have strongly influenced both psychiatric practice and research, but have also led to assertions that psychiatry is in crisis, and to advocacy for entirely new paradigms for diagnosis and assessment. When thinking about etiology, many researchers currently refer to a biopsychosocial model, but this approach has received significant critique, being considered by some observers overly eclectic and vague. Despite the development of a range of evidence‐based pharmacotherapies and psychotherapies, current evidence points to both a treatment gap and a research‐practice gap in mental health. In this paper, after considering current clinical practice, we discuss some proposed novel perspectives that have recently achieved particular prominence and may significantly impact psychiatric practice and research in the future: clinical neuroscience and personalized pharmacotherapy; novel statistical approaches to psychiatric nosology, assessment and research; deinstitutionalization and community mental health care; the scale‐up of evidence‐based psychotherapy; digital phenotyping and digital therapies; and global mental health and task‐sharing approaches. We consider the extent to which proposed transitions from current practices to novel approaches reflect hype or hope. Our review indicates that each of the novel perspectives contributes important insights that allow hope for the future, but also that each provides only a partial view, and that any promise of a paradigm shift for the field is not well grounded. We conclude that there have been crucial advances in psychiatric diagnosis and treatment in recent decades; that, despite this important progress, there is considerable need for further improvements in assessment and intervention; and that such improvements will likely not be achieved by any specific paradigm shifts in psychiatric practice and research, but rather by incremental progress and iterative integration.
Keywords: Mental disorder, psychiatric nosology, clinical neuroscience, personalized psychiatry, Research Domain Criteria, Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology, deinstitutionalization, community mental health care, evidence‐based psychotherapy, digital phenotyping, digital therapies, global mental health, task‐sharing approaches, paradigm shifts, incremental integration
Psychiatry has over the course of its history been characterized by a range of different models of and approaches to mental disorder, each perhaps bringing forward some advances in science and in services, but at the same time also accompanied by considerable critique from within and without the field.
The shift away from psychoanalysis in the latter part of the 20th century was accompanied by key scientific and clinical advances, including the introduction of a wide range of evidence‐based pharmacotherapies and psychotherapies for the treatment of mental disorders. However, there has also been an extensive critique of pharmacological and cognitive‐behavioral interventions, whether focused on concerns about their “medical model” foundations, or emphasizing the need to build community psychiatry and to scale up these treatments globally 1 .
In the 21st century, global mental health has become an influential novel perspective on mental disorders and their treatment. This emergent discipline builds on advances in cross‐cultural psychiatry, psychiatric epidemiology, implementation science, and the human rights movement 2 . Global mental health has given impetus to a wide range of mental health research as well as to clinical strategies such as task‐shifting, with evidence that these are effective in diverse contexts and may be suitable for roll‐out at scale 3 . It is noteworthy, however, that global mental health has in turn been critiqued for inappropriate and imperial exportation of Western constructs to the global South 4 .
Psychiatric nosology has been a particular focus of both advances in and critique from the field. The 3rd edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM‐III) was paramount, providing an approach that attempted to eschew different models of etiology, focusing instead on reliable diagnostic constructs 5 . These constructs became widely used in epidemiological studies of mental illness, in psychiatric research on etiology and treatment, as well as in daily clinical practice throughout the world. The most recent editions of the DSM (DSM‐5) and of the International Classification of Diseases (ICD‐11) by the World Health Organization (WHO) have drawn on and given impetus to a considerable body of work in nosological science6, 7.
Early on, psychoanalytic psychiatry criticized DSM diagnostic constructs for missing core psychic phenomena. With increasing concerns that these constructs have insufficient validity, neuroscientifically informed psychiatry has put forward approaches to assessing behavioral phenomena that emphasize laboratory models 8 . Despite the growing body of nosology science instantiated by the DSM‐5 and ICD‐11, many have argued for new paradigms of classification and assessment – e.g., the Research Domain Criteria (RDoC), the Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP) and other novel statistical approaches, and digital phenotyping.
Where do things stand currently with regard to psychiatry's models of and approaches to mental disorder? What are current clinical practices? What novel perspectives are being proposed, and what is the evidence base for them? To what extent will newly introduced models of clinical intervention, such as shared decision‐making or transdiagnostic psychotherapies, and novel approaches in psychiatric research, such as the use of “big data” in neurobiological research and treatment outcome prediction, have transformative impact for clinical practice in the foreseeable future?
In this paper we discuss proposed shifts to clinical neuroscience and personalized pharmacotherapy, innovative statistical approaches to psychiatric nosology and assessment, deinstitutionalization and community mental health care, the scale‐up of evidence‐based psychotherapy, digital phenotyping and digital therapies, and global mental health and task‐sharing approaches. We chose these novel perspectives because they have achieved particular prominence recently, and because many have argued that they will significantly impact psychiatric practice and research in the future.
We consider the extent to which proposed transitions from current practices to these novel perspectives reflect hype or hope, and whether they represent paradigm shifts or iterative progress in psychiatric research and practice. Although the contrast between hype and hope is itself likely oversimplistic, with many newly proposed models and approaches in psychiatry representing neither of these polar extremes, our point of departure is that false promises of paradigm shifts in health care may entail significant costs, while hope may justifiably be considered an important virtue for health professions 9 . We begin with a brief consideration of current models and approaches in psychiatric practice.
CURRENT MODELS AND APPROACHES IN PSYCHIATRY
Current practice in psychiatry varies in different parts of the world, but there are some important universalities. The duration and depth of training in psychiatry during the undergraduate and postgraduate years also differ across countries, but typically a general training in medicine and surgery is followed by specialized training in psychiatry, with exposure to both inpatient and outpatient settings. Globally, inpatient psychiatry focuses predominantly (but not exclusively) on severe mental disorders such as schizophrenia and bipolar disorder, while outpatient psychiatry focuses predominantly (but again not exclusively) on common mental disorders such as depression, anxiety disorders, and substance use disorders. In inpatient settings, psychiatrists are often leaders of a multidisciplinary team, with the extent and depth of this multidisciplinarity dependent on local resources. There are differences in sub‐specialization across the globe, but in many countries recognized sub‐specialties include child and adolescent psychiatry, geriatric psychiatry, and forensic psychiatry 10 .
A particularly important shift in the 20th century has been the process of deinstitutionalization, particularly in high‐income countries. Thus, there has been a decrease of bed numbers in specialized psychiatric hospitals, but an increase of these numbers in general medical hospitals, with variable strengthening of community services. It has been argued that, when it comes to mental health services, all countries are “developing”, since there is a relative underfunding of such services in relation to the burden of disease 1 .
Currently, the two major classification systems in psychiatry are the DSM‐5 and the ICD‐11. The DSM system is more commonly used by researchers, while the ICD is a legally mandated health data standard. The operational criteria and diagnostic guidelines included in the DSM‐III, the ICD‐10, and subsequent editions of the manuals have exerted considerable influence on modern psychiatry. They not only increase reliability of diagnosis, but also have clinical utility, since they provide clinicians with an approach to conceptualizing disorders and to communicating about them11, 12. They have also played a key role in research, ranging from studies of the neurobiology of mental disorders, through to studies of interventions for particular conditions, and on to clinical and community epidemiological surveys.
However, there has also been considerable critique of the reliance of modern psychiatry on the DSM and the ICD. The notion that psychiatric diagnosis is itself “in crisis” has come both from within the field and from external critics. Two somewhat contradictory critiques have been that in daily practice the DSM and ICD criteria or guidelines are seldom applied formally by clinicians, and that over‐reliance on those criteria or guidelines leads to a checklist approach to assessment that ignores relevant symptoms and important contextual issues falling outside the focus of the nosologies. Additional key critiques have been that psychiatric diagnoses lack scientific validity, and that current nosologies are biased by influences such as that of the pharmaceutical industry13, 14.
When thinking about etiology, many clinicians and researchers currently default to a biopsychosocial model acknowledging that a broad range of risk and protective factors are involved in the development and perpetuation of mental disorders. This model was introduced by G. Engel in an attempt to move from a reductionistic biomedical approach to include also psychological and social dimensions 15 . The model has important strengths insofar as it takes a systems‐based approach that considers a broad range of variables influencing disease onset and course, and attends to both the relevant biomedical disease and the patient's experience of illness 16 .
Nevertheless, the biopsychosocial approach has received significant critique. In particular, it has been argued that the biomedical model critiqued by Engel is a straw man, and that the biopsychosocial approach is overly eclectic and vague. By saying that all mental disorders have biological, psychological and social contributory factors, we are unable to be specific about any particular condition, and to target treatments accordingly17, 18. While there are few data available on how rigorously psychiatrists consider the range of risk and protective factors in clinical work, a review of the research literature indicates ongoing work on multiple “difference‐makers”, distributed across a wide range of categories 19 .
Psychiatrists are trained to provide a range of both pharmacological and psychological interventions. However, data from psychiatric practice networks and from epidemiological surveys indicate that there has been a growing emphasis on pharmacotherapy interventions 20 , albeit with some exceptions 21 . Furthermore, the number of psychiatrists varies considerably from country to country, and from region to region within any particular country 22 . While primary care practitioners are also trained to deliver mental health treatments, and indeed provide the bulk of prescriptions for mental disorders in some regions, there is considerable evidence of underdiagnosis and undertreatment of such conditions in primary care settings.
Indeed, despite the development of a range of evidence‐based pharmacotherapies and psychotherapies in the last several decades, current data point to both a treatment gap and a research‐practice gap in mental health. The treatment gap refers to findings that, across the globe, many individuals with mental disorders do not have access to mental health care 23 . The research‐practice gap, also known as the “science‐practice” or “evidence‐practice gap”, refers to differences between treatments delivered in standard care and those supported by scientific evidence 24 . In particular, clinical practitioners have been criticized for employing an eclectic approach to choosing interventions, for not sufficiently adhering to evidence‐based clinical guidelines, and for not employing measurement‐based care.
The treatment gap and the research‐practice gap are of deep concern, given evidence of underdiagnosis and undertreatment, of misdiagnosis and inappropriate treatment, and of inadequate quality of treatment25, 26. There are, however, some justifiable reasons for a gap between practice and research, including that the evidence base is relatively sparse for the management of treatment‐refractory and comorbid conditions, the relative lack of pragmatic “real‐world” research trials in psychiatry, and the possibly modest positive impact of guideline implementation on patient outcomes27, 28. Indeed, several scholars have emphasized that including clinical experience and addressing patient values are key components of appropriate decision‐making27, 29.
Considerably more research is needed to inform our knowledge of current psychiatric practice and its outcomes. Data from psychiatric practice networks have been useful in providing fine‐grained information in some settings, but much further work is warranted along these lines 30 . Data from randomized controlled trials indicate that psychiatric treatments are as effective as those in other areas of health care, but further evidence should be acquired using pragmatic designs in real‐world contexts 31 . Epidemiological data from across the globe suggest that individuals with mental disorders who received specialized, multi‐sector care are more likely than other patients to report being helped “a lot”, but there is an ongoing need for more accurate estimates of effective treatment coverage globally 32 .
In the interim, evidence of the treatment gap and the research‐practice gap in current mental health services has given impetus to the development of a number of novel diagnostic and treatment models and approaches, ranging from clinical neuroscience through to global mental health. Some of these models and approaches have achieved particular prominence in recent times, with proponents arguing that they will significantly impact psychiatric practice and research in the future. At times advocates for these perspectives and proposals have limited aims, while at other times they speak of paradigm shifts that will drastically alter or wholly reshape current clinical practices33, 34, 35, 36. We next consider a number of these perspectives and proposals in turn.
CLINICAL NEUROSCIENCE AND PERSONALIZED PHARMACOTHERAPY
A key shift in 20th century psychiatry, at least in some parts of the world, was from psychoanalytic to biological psychiatry. The serendipitous discovery of a range of psychiatric medications in the mid‐20th century, and advances in molecular, genetic and neuroimaging methods, propelled this shift. More recently, terms such as clinical neuroscience, translational psychiatry, precision psychiatry, and personalized psychiatry have emerged, helping to articulate the conceptual foundations for a proposed psychiatric perspective aiming to replace or significantly augment current practice37, 38, 39.
The proposed paradigm of clinical neuroscience rests in part on a critique of current standard approaches. First, in terms of diagnosis, it has been argued that the DSM and ICD constructs are not sufficiently based on neuroscience 40 . Thus, for example, particular symptoms, which may involve quite specific neurobiological mechanisms, may be present across different diagnoses. Conversely, research findings demonstrate that there is considerable overlap of genetic architecture across different DSM and ICD mental disorders 41 . If current diagnostic constructs are not natural kinds, then arguably attempts to find specific biomarkers and develop targeted treatments for them are doomed to fail42, 43.
The proposed new paradigm views psychiatry as a clinical neuroscience, which should rest on a firm foundation of neurobiological knowledge 44 . With advances in neurobiology, we will be better able to target relevant mechanisms and develop specific treatments for mental disorders. Neuroimaging and genomic research offer opportunities for personalizing psychiatric intervention: those with specific genetic variants may require tailoring of psychopharmacological intervention, while particular alterations in neural signatures may be used to choose a therapeutic modality or to alter parameters for neurostimulation.
The RDoC project, developed by the US National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH), has provided an influential conceptual framework for this proposed new paradigm 8 . Whereas the DSM‐III relied on the Research Diagnostic Criteria (RDC) in order to operationalize mental disorders, the RDoC project emphasizes domains of functioning that are underpinned by specific neurobiological mechanisms. Disruptions in these domains may lead to various symptoms and impairments. Domains of functioning are found across species, and their neurobiological substrates are sufficiently known to allow translational neuroscience, or productive movement from bench to bedside and back. Each domain of functioning can be assessed with specific laboratory paradigms.
The RDoC matrix initially included five domains of functioning and several “units of analysis” for assessing these domains (see Figure 1) 45 . Each domain in turn comprises a number of different “constructs” (or rows of the matrix): these were included on the basis of evidence that they entail a validated behavioral function, and that a neural circuit or system implements the function. Different “units of analysis” (or columns of the matrix) can be used to assess each construct: the center column refers to brain circuitry, with three columns to the left focusing on the genes, molecules and cells that comprise circuits, and three columns to the right focusing on circuit outputs (behavior, physiological responses, and verbal reports). A column to list paradigms is also included.
Figure 1.
The Research Domain Criteria matrix (from Cuthbert 45 )
The RDoC matrix is intended to include two further critical dimensions for integrating neuroscience and psychopathology, i.e. developmental trajectories and environmental effects 45 . Thus, from an RDoC perspective, many mental illnesses can be viewed as neurodevelopmental disorders, with maturation of the nervous system interacting with a range of external influences from the time of conception. Several key “pillars” of the RDoC framework, including its translational and dimensional focuses 8 , have been emphasized.
Anxiety, for example, can be studied in laboratory paradigms, and ranges from normal responses to threat through to pathological conditions. Indeed, a clinical neuroscience approach has contributed to the reconceptualization of several anxiety and related disorders46, 47, 48 and to the introduction of novel therapeutic approaches for these conditions 49 . Further, work on stressors has usefully emphasized that environmental exposures become biologically embedded, with early adversity associated to alterations in both body and brain that occur irrespective of the DSM diagnostic category50, 51.
The NIMH has linked the RDoC to funding applications, and this framework has given impetus to a range of clinical neuroscience research. Translational research will certainly advance our empirical knowledge of the neurobiology of behavior and of psychopathology. The RDoC has also prompted conceptual work related to the neurobiology of mental disorders, and the development of measures and methods. Indeed, to the extent that constructs in the RDoC matrix have validity as behavioral functions, and map onto specific biological systems such as brain circuits, the project summarizes key advances in the field, and provides useful guidance for ongoing research.
At the same time, it is relevant to note important limitations of the RDoC approach. First, the RDoC seems less an entirely new paradigm than a re‐articulation of existing ideas in biological psychiatry. Certainly, the importance of cross‐diagnostic neurobiological investigations of domains of functioning has long been emphasized 52 . Second, the neurobiology of any particular RDoC construct, such as social communication, may be enormously complex, so that alternative approaches to delineating the mechanisms involved in particular mental disorders may provide greater traction 53 . Third, methods used to measure domains in the RDoC framework may not be readily available to clinicians. The further one moves from academic centers to the practice of psychiatry in primary care settings around the globe, the less relevant an RDoC framework may be to daily clinical work.
Personalized and precision psychiatry are important aspirations of clinical neuroscience. The notion that psychiatric interventions need to be rigorously tailored to each individual patient makes good sense, given the substantial inter‐individual variability in the genome and exposome of those suffering from psychiatric disorders, as well as the considerable variation in response to current psychiatric interventions. With advances in genomic methods and findings, and the possibility that whole genome sequencing will become a standard clinical tool, with polygenic risk scores readily available, it is particularly relevant to consider the application of genomics to optimizing pharmacological and other treatments 54 .
The Clinical Pharmacogenetic Implementation Consortium (CPIC) has already provided a range of clinical guidelines for drugs used in psychiatry. For example, a CPIC guideline recommends that, given the association between the HLA‐B*15:02 variant and Stevens‐Johnson syndrome as well as toxic epidermal necrolysis after exposure to carbamazepine and oxcarbazepine, these drugs should be avoided in patients who are HLA‐B*15:02 positive and carbamazepine‐ or oxcarbazepine‐naïve 55 . The evidence base that pharmacogenomic testing improves outcomes is gradually beginning to accumulate, and recent guidelines have started to recommend a number of specific tests 56 .
From an RDoC perspective, particular domains of functioning involve specific neural circuits, which are in turn modulated by a range of molecular pathways. One notable recent development in these fields has been a focus on “big data”. Large collaborations in basic and clinical sciences have been established, which provide sufficient statistical power to advance the field in important ways.
Examples of such “big data” collaborations are the Enhancing Neuroimaging Meta‐analysis Consortium (ENIGMA) 57 , which includes tens of thousands of scans from across the world, and the Psychiatric Genetics Consortium (PGC) 58 , which includes hundreds of thousands of DNA samples from across the globe. The work of ENIGMA and PGC has been at the cutting edge of scientific research in psychiatry, and has provided crucial insights into mental disorders. Certain biological pathways, such as immune and metabolic systems, appear to play a role across different mental disorders, and genomic methods have contributed to delineating causal and modifiable mechanisms underlying these conditions58, 59. At the same time, it must be acknowledged that to date few findings from this work have been successfully translated into daily clinical practice36, 54, 60.
In summary, clinical neuroscience provides an important conceptual framework that may generate some useful clinical insights, and that may be particularly helpful in guiding clinical research. This framework has contributed to the reconceptualization of a number of mental disorders, and has on occasion contributed to the introduction of new therapies 61 . As clinical neuroscience generates new evidence, this may be incorporated in nosological systems in the future. There are already good arguments for including advances in this area in the curriculum of psychiatric training, and for updating clinicians on progress in the field 62 .
At the same time, there are currently few biomarkers with clinical utility in psychiatry, and methods such as functional neuroimaging and genome sequencing, which are key for future advances in frameworks such as the RDoC, are not readily available to or useful for practicing clinicians 63 . The vast majority of clinical neuroscience publications appear to have little link to clinical practice. At best, therefore, we can expect that ongoing advances in clinical neuroscience will contribute to clinical practice via iterative advances in our conceptualization of mental disorders, and via the ongoing introduction of new insights and new molecules that emerge from laboratory studies.
Indeed, the claim that any particular laboratory, neuroimaging or genetic finding will dramatically change clinical practice should raise a red flag. The neurobiology of behaviors and psychopathology is complex, reproducibility of findings is an ongoing important issue, and clinical neuroscience investigations only occasionally impact clinical practice 64 . Indeed, we should be careful not to be over‐optimistic about clinical neuroscience constituting a paradigm shift. Neurobiological research has not to date provided a rich pipeline of accurate biomarkers for mental disorders, nor speedily found new molecular entities that are efficacious for these conditions, and we cannot, for example, expect that the DSM and ICD will be replaced by the RDoC anytime soon.
NOVEL STATISTICAL APPROACHES TO PSYCHIATRIC NOSOLOGY, ASSESSMENT AND RESEARCH
Disease taxonomies are particularly complex, and may not be able to follow historical models of scientific taxonomies, which have defined all elements of a given set. An often‐used example of the latter taxonomies is the periodic table of elements. Another venerable example is Linnaeus’ Systema Naturae and the resulting nomenclature of biological species. The periodic table of elements has the simplicity of small numbers plus the hard and fast rules of chemistry, while the Systema Naturae, despite having to deal with an ever‐expanding number of entities, is arguably based on direct observation of beings. In contrast, a disease taxonomy deals with thousands of unruly entities (versus 118 elements), which cannot be directly observed, apprehended or dissected (as animals or plants can).
Despite these challenges, disease taxonomies have sought to provide a shared, evidence‐based, clinically meaningful, comprehensive classification that is informed by etiology and therapeutics. The notion that underneath the observable syndrome lies a causal entity, that we should investigate and treat, lies at the heart of the practice of medicine 65 . Such “disease entities” have specific characteristics that make them clear and distinct from others (i.e., presentation, etiology, response to intervention), are transparent to the clinician, and are well‐grounded in evidence.
Psychiatry has long faced the challenges of producing a causal nosology that is able to direct treatment 66 . Pinel developed the first comprehensive nosology for people with severe mental disorders, along with moral treatment, the first therapeutic framework of the scientific era 67 . Soon afterward, Kahlbaum, Kraepelin and Bleuler laid a firm groundwork for clinical psychiatry through close observation and systematic documentation of the natural history of severe mental illness. Arguably, Freud further advanced nosology and therapeutics by focusing on a different set of disorders (usually milder but much more prevalent), which he termed neuroses (to highlight their difference from psychoses), and by developing the concept and practice of psychotherapy. These frameworks gave impetus to subsequent advances in our understanding of and interventions for mental disorders.
Perceptions of insufficiently rapid and robust advances in treatments have led to criticism of current nosology 68 . In particular, the DSM and ICD have been criticized for overly focusing on reliability at the expense of validity. In this view, schizophrenia and bipolar disorder may be genuine disease entities, but our syndromic definition lacks specificity, and there are likely different causal pathways that lead to clinically meaningful subtypes of these disorders. Major depressive disorder, on the other hand, is likely to be a hodgepodge of mood syndromes, some non‐dysfunctional (i.e., non‐disorders) or non‐specific (i.e., combining depressive with anxiety symptoms), including only a few true but potentially diverse disease entities (e.g., melancholia, psychotic depression). And when it comes to, say, personality disorders, the disease‐entity concept is even more distant, and the search for new approaches is seen as particularly key.
One such novel paradigm is the HiTOP. This proposes a hierarchical framework that, based on the observed covariation of dimensional traits, is able to identify latent super‐spectra and spectra (supra‐syndromes), syndromes (our current disorders), and lower‐level components69, 70, 71, 72. In this conceptual framework, a dimension consists of a continuous space in which an element occurs in differences of degree, but not of kind, between the normal and the pathological.
The HiTOP relies on factor analysis and related techniques, which tap into the covariation of observable traits to identify an unobserved, common factor that, once included in the model, explains the covariation 73 . Costa and McCrae's studies leading to the identification of five personality domains were a prime example of this approach. There is a common underlying reason that explains a person's tendency to worry about many things, think that the future looks bleak, be bothered by intrusive thoughts, and be grouchy 74 . That unobserved factor was conceptualized as “neuroticism”, and fully explains the covariation of these traits in any given individual. A similar approach to the study of childhood psychopathology led to the binary characterization of an “internalizing” and an “externalizing” dimension to childhood disorders 75 .
The HiTOP paradigm seeks to leverage these well‐established lines of research to develop a data‐driven nosology that is free from the theory‐driven dead weight built into current approaches. The key conceptual departure relies on the premise that, since evidence points towards psychopathological dimensions existing on a continuum, disorders should be similarly conceptualized, and nosology should move away from a focus on categorical entities. Instead of insisting on questionable boundaries, this approach proposes dimensional thresholds, which are empirically determined and do not involve any difference “in kind”. By grouping co‐occurring symptoms within the same syndrome, and non‐co‐occurring symptoms separately, within‐disorder heterogeneity is reduced. And by assigning overlapping syndromes to the same unobserved spectra, excess comorbidity found when using current categories is explained.
The resulting dimensional classification, the proponents of HiTOP argue, is consistent with evidence on risk factors, biomarkers, course of illness, and treatment response 69 . Figure 2 shows a schema of the proposed new nosology. An intriguing element of this approach is what has been termed “p”, or general psychopathology factor (at the top of Figure 2). In addition to super‐spectra and spectra, factor analysis ultimately points towards the existence of a single latent trait that would explain all psychopathology, comparable to the well‐established “g” factor for general intelligence76, 77.
Figure 2.
The Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP) model (from Krueger et al 69 )
If dimensional nosologies seek to overturn categorical ones, network analysis arguably aims to overturn both, insofar as it posits that the notion of an unobserved underlying construct is unwarranted, be it a categorical disease entity or a dimensional latent factor 78 . The network approach to psychopathology holds that mental disorders can be conceived as “problems in living”, and are best understood at the level of what is observable. Rather than by latent entities, disordered states are fully explained by the interaction between signs and symptoms (the “nodes” of the networks). These interactions are themselves the causal elements (i.e., a symptom causes another symptom, then another symptom, and so on), and a disorder is simply an alternative “stable state” of strongly connected symptom networks (as opposed to the “normal” steady state of health).
A conceptualization of disorders as “problems in living” does away with the medical notion of a disease as an underlying causal entity. In this view, deficiencies in our understanding of etiology are not necessarily due to diagnostic limitations or insufficiently accurate models for the unobserved but, on the contrary, may be due to our lack of attention to the surface, i.e. the symptoms themselves, which go about reinforcing each other while we are distracted by peeking behind imaginary curtains.
Unlike dimensional approaches, proponents of network analysis disavow any nosological hierarchy (super‐spectra, spectra, disorders, symptoms, etc.), and posit that there is only one level, that of symptoms, which can all cause and reinforce one another. Of note, network analysis posits that symptoms (or interacting nodes) can be activated by disturbances emerging from the “external field” (i.e., “external” to the symptom network, not necessarily to the body or person), such as the loss of a loved one (which may activate the symptom depressed mood, setting in motion the depressive network) or a brain abnormality (which may activate the symptom hallucination, setting in motion the psychotic network).
Whether an individual develops a new strongly connected network of symptoms in the face of a stressor depends on his/her “vulnerability”, which is based on the network's connectivity. Given a dataset with symptoms and/or signs for disorders, a network analysis can quantify all relevant nodes and interactions, including the frequency and co‐occurrence of symptoms, the strength and number of their associations, and the centrality of each symptom (i.e., the sum of the interactions with other nodes). Empirical work using network analysis potentially provides rigorous accounts of vulnerability to and evolution of mental disorders.
A number of other novel statistical approaches have also been put forward as potentially facilitating paradigm shifts in psychiatry. Psychiatry has long relied on linear models to explore associations and develop theories of risk and resilience for mental disorders. However, causal inference methods have now been developed in statistics, and provide new approaches to delineating causal relationships 79 . In genetics, Mendelian randomization provides an innovative method for addressing the causal relationships of different phenotypes, and has increasingly been employed in psychiatric research 80 . Neural networks and deep learning have played a key role in advancing artificial intelligence, and are increasingly being applied to the investigation of psychiatric disorders, including prediction of treatment outcomes81, 82, 83, 84. While many view such techniques as allowing iterative advances, some are persuaded that they allow an entirely novel perspective and so constitute a paradigm shift in the field 85 .
Work on the HiTOP and network analysis has been important and useful in a number of respects. First, unbiased data‐driven approaches have an important role in strengthening the relevant science, whether of nosology, or of areas such as genetics. A focus on fear‐related anxiety disorders, for example, offers interesting avenues for research, both from a neuroscience and a therapeutic perspective, and network analysis has contributed insights into the presentation of some disorders 48 . Second, some dimensional constructs, including those of internalizing and externalizing disorders, have clinical utility. The “distress” subfactor reflects the notable overlap between depressive and anxious symptoms, and the association between symptoms from two different disorders (e.g., major depressive disorder and generalized anxiety disorder) may be stronger than associations “within” each disorder 86 . Third, the use of novel statistical methods to draw causal inferences has provided important insights into risk for and resilience to mental disorders 59 . For instance, network analysis offers a nuanced foundation for targeted treatment of the core symptoms of some mental disorders (e.g., reframing specific automatic thoughts through cognitive‐behavioral interventions).
At the same time, such approaches have important limitations. Notably, categorical and dimensional approaches are interchangeable: any dimension can be converted into a category, and any category can be converted into a dimension 87 . There is no reason to conceptualize mental disorders as exclusively dimensional. In physics, matter itself is sometimes better conceived in terms of waves (a dimensional concept) and other times in terms of particles (a categorical one). Similarly, in psychiatry, a pluralist approach that allows the employment of a range of different dichotomous and continuous constructs seems appropriate88, 89.
Remarkably, the HiTOP employs DSM terminology at the disorder level. “Number‐driven” psychopathologies and their resulting nosologies may not necessarily lead to a shift in constructs grounded in long‐standing clinical practice and research. In the same vein, network analysis offers a useful model to understand the distribution of symptoms, identify therapeutic targets, and explain the effectiveness of symptomatic interventions. However, network analysis does not specify the particular levels of explanation that underlie a network structure; so, while it may be a useful organizing framework, it is unclear that it will provide novel insights into underlying etiological mechanisms.
Consider a set of patients presenting with the following symptoms, among others: headaches, vomiting and seizures. A factor analysis may point towards a latent factor explaining the covariation among them. Any clinician will know that, unless the cause is substance‐related, the first thing to rule out in these patients is a space‐occupying lesion in the brain, and that this unobserved element is only an intermediary that can itself be caused by multiple disease entities, most notably hemorrhage, infection and cancer. The fact that a latent factor may explain the covariation between anxious and depressive symptoms does not exclude that these symptoms are in fact caused by very different dysfunctions (upstream of the latent factor), and that other accompanying symptoms will hold the clue to the ultimate cause (just as high blood pressure, fever or weight loss would hold clues for a space‐occupying lesion syndrome).
Relatedly, consider the focus of the HiTOP on a general psychopathology factor “p”. This focus can be countered by a reductio ad absurdum argument suggesting that a latent factor “i” explains the covariation of any and all human illnesses. Given some datasets, we may find that the covariation of nausea, hemoptysis, jaundice and myocardial infarction is explained by a latent dimensional trait. We may choose to call this “sybaritism”, dimensionally distributed between one extreme (temperance) and another (debauchery). Readers who focus on values‐based medicine might well criticize the choice of words here, while those focused on evidence‐based medicine are unlikely to be persuaded that an approach that elides disease entities will advance studies of psychiatry, gastroenterology and cardiology 29 .
In a latent class analysis of depressive and anxious syndromes, Eaton et al 90 proposed an approach called “guided empiricism”, whereby they explicitly imposed a theory‐driven structure on various statistical models, compared them, and obtained the best empirical fit. Perhaps using such explicitly theory‐driven constraints is preferable to accepting hidden theoretical constructs. For example, rather than assuming that all the DSM depressive and some anxiety/stress related disorders are explained by a latent factor called “distress”, itself under a spectrum called “internalizing disorders”, a theory‐grounded structure can be imposed on the models to try to identify what is driving the overlap. Indeed, it should be emphasized that purportedly “number‐driven” nosologies all have built‐in qualitative components: from the questions in the scales used to measure traits, to the labels chosen for the latent factors, these classifications are theory‐laden.
In summary, the solution to nosologic challenges in psychiatry may not reside in the building of new nosologies or psychopathologies from scratch 91 , nor in the banishment of the “disease entity” concept, but rather in continuing the humble, laborious, iterative work of systematic clinical observation, painstaking research, and creative thinking, while purposefully comparing dimensional, categorical and hybrid models applied to the same datasets. The claim that a “quantitative” nosology is somehow “atheoretical” raises a red flag: where theory is seemingly absent, it is often hidden. Instead, we need thoughtful and explicit combinations of theories grounded on clinical practice and confirmatory quantitative evidence. Hypothesis formulation is a qualitative, creative, theory‐laden endeavour, while quantitative research helps us discard false theories and refine what we know (by proving hypotheses wrong or quantifying associations).
Similarly, etiological and treatment challenges in psychiatry are unlikely to be addressed merely by the employment of larger and larger datasets, using more and more sophisticated statistical methods. Certainly, big data consortia and sophisticated statistical analyses have yielded valuable insights into the nature of psychiatric disorders. However, it is important to recognize the limitations of any empirical dataset and any analytic method, as well as the value of a wide range of complementary research designs and statistical approaches – including the age‐old single‐case study, which may sometimes provide clinical insights that outweigh those from big data analyses 92 .
Indeed, the claim that a new statistical, bioinformatic or computational method will provide entirely novel insights that enable a paradigm shift in psychiatry should again raise a red flag. Furthermore, where solutions reside within a black box, there is ongoing uncertainty about the extent to which they will be able to provide clinically useful assistance93, 94. Thoughtful and explicit combinations of existing and novel research designs and statistical methods should be employed, with the aim of achieving iterative and integrative progress in our diagnosis and treatment of psychiatric disorders.
DEINSTITUTIONALIZATION AND COMMUNITY MENTAL HEALTH CARE
The last 70 years have seen a seismic shift in models of mental health care delivery around the world. The first half of the 20th century was dominated by the growth of psychiatric hospitals, particularly in high‐income Western countries. By 1955, there were 558,239 severely mentally ill people living in psychiatric hospitals in the US, with a total population of 164 million at the time 95 . In the years that followed, there was a significant reduction in psychiatric hospital bed numbers in many high‐income countries, as part of a trend that came to be known as deinstitutionalization. In the UK, the US, Australia, New Zealand and countries in Western Europe, there was an 80‐90% reduction in psychiatric hospital beds between the mid‐1950s and the 1990s 96 .
Deinstitutionalization refers to the downscaling of large psychiatric institutions and the transition of patients into community‐based care. This is said to include three components: the discharge of people residing in psychiatric hospitals to care in the community, the diversion of new admissions to alternative facilities, and the development of new community‐based specialized services for those in need 97 . More recently, a focus in community‐based care has also been the development of models for integrating mental health into primary care, as well as of shared decision‐making and recovery approaches 98 . To the extent that these models propose new ways of addressing mental illness, as well as extensive scale‐up of community‐based services, many would argue that they constitute a crucial paradigm shift.
Deinstitutionalization was driven by three main forces. First, the introduction of new medications made it increasingly possible for people with severe and enduring mental disorders such as schizophrenia and bipolar disorder to live reasonably well in community settings. Second, the mushrooming of psychiatric hospitals had come with high costs, and deinstitutionalization was seen by many governments as a cost‐saving strategy. Third, the growth of the human rights movement in the 1950s and 1960s generated increasing public concern about practices in psychiatric institutions, including involuntary care. Films such as One Flew over the Cuckoo's Nest drew public attention to the conditions in those facilities and provided support to the idea that people living with mental disorders should have a choice over the nature and locus of their care. This trend was reinforced by research demonstrating that community‐based models of care, including for people with severe mental disorders, could be delivered effectively, in a manner that was more acceptable to service users, and in some cases less costly 97 .
However, in many regions of the world, these developments have not actually occurred. Particularly in many post‐colonial low‐income countries, for example in sub‐Saharan Africa and South Asia, large psychiatric hospitals have been left behind by departing administrations, and have remained the main locus of care. In these countries, there has been little substantial deinstitutionalization, and very limited scaling up of community‐based and primary care mental health services 22 . In low‐income countries, there were 0.02 psychiatric beds per 100,000 population in 2001, and this increased to 1.9 beds per 100,000 population in 2020.
The success of deinstitutionalization programmes in transitioning to community‐based care has been highly varied around the world. In some countries, such as Italy, legislation has mandated the establishment of community‐based services, and consequently these services have been widely implemented, although with substantial variation across the country 99 . In many other countries, funding did not follow people who were discharged from psychiatric hospitals into community settings. For example, in many parts of the US, deinstitutionalization has been associated with a burgeoning population of homeless mentally ill and mentally ill prisoners 95 .
In Central and Eastern Europe, even with recent reforms, studies have criticized the uneven pace of deinstitutionalization, the lack of investment in community‐based care, and the “reinstitutionalization” of many people with severe mental illness or intellectual disability 100 . In a tragic case in South Africa, deinstitutionalization of 2,000 people with severe mental illness or intellectual disability from the Life Esidimeni facility into unlicensed and unregulated community organizations led to the death of over 140 people, sparking a public outcry and a national enquiry by the Human Rights Commission 101 .
Importantly, deinstitutionalization has been associated with “revolving door” patterns of care, in which people are discharged from hospital after admission for an acute episode, but do not have adequate care and support in the community, and therefore relapse and need to be readmitted. Indeed, readmission rates have been an important indicator for service managers to monitor in the post‐deinstitutionalization era, and the focus of several intervention studies 102 .
The WHO has advocated for the development of community‐based services for mental disorders for many decades. In the early 2000s, it produced a set of guidelines for countries to develop national mental health policies, plans and services 103 . This included the now widely cited “optimal mix of services” to guide countries on how to balance hospital‐ and community‐based care. This model proposed a pyramid structure, in which specialist psychiatric inpatient care represents only a small proportion of services at the apex of the pyramid, and is supported by psychiatric services in general hospitals, specialist community outreach, primary care services, and self‐care at the base of the pyramid. Others have developed similar “balanced care” models 104 .
The 21st century has also seen the development of models for integrating mental health into primary care, such as collaborative care models 105 . These latter initially focused on managing people with comorbid depression and other chronic diseases. Subsequently this work has been expanded to include other mental disorders, through models in which a mental health specialist provides support to non‐specialist health care providers, who are the main point of contact for people needing care. The WHO has endorsed this approach, particularly through its flagship mhGAP programme, which provides clinical guidelines for the delivery of mental health care through non‐specialist health care platforms in primary care and general hospital settings 106 . The mhGAP Intervention Guide has now been implemented in over 100 countries.
In parallel, the latter part of the 20th century and early 21st century have seen the rapid development of shared decision‐making and recovery approaches to mental health care. Shared decision‐making involves clinicians and people with mental disorders working together to make decisions, particularly about care needs, in a collaborative, mutually respectful manner 98 . This approach is consistent with an emphasis on human rights, as well as on the importance of patients’ lived experience, explanatory models and specific values, and clearly deserves support107, 108. Recovery models have challenged traditional roles of “patients” to reframe recovery as a way of living a satisfying, hopeful life that makes a contribution even within the limitations of illness 109 . The recovery movement has been highly influential, is now incorporated into mental health policies, and has shaped the design of mental health systems in several countries 109 .
Yet, despite the strong scientific and ethical principles supporting community‐based care, collaborative care and moves towards shared decision‐making and recovery approaches, there remain major challenges, and the proposed paradigm shift remains to a large extent aspirational. While community care models have been developed, tested and shown to be effective in landmark studies, there are few cases of countries systematically investing in these models at scale, in a manner that substantially influences the mental health of populations. In addition, although there are apparent advantages to approaches such as shared decision‐making, a wide range of barriers across individual, organizational and system levels have been reported 110 , and implementation remains limited in mental health care 98 .
Indeed, it has been noticed that the agreement about the concept of shared decision‐making among stakeholders is only superficial 98 . After all, clinicians may not support this approach if it leads to patients being more empowered, but less adherent to treatment recommendations. This example raises broader questions about community‐based care models: is the failure to systematically scale up these models just due to a lack of political will and related scarcity of resources, or are there fundamental concerns with the model? Our view is that both of these may be true.
There is certainly a lack of political will and investment. Despite the courageous campaigning by people with lived experience for their rights to make decisions about their care, together with the robust evidence of improved outcomes associated with community‐based collaborative care models, governments often remain indifferent 1 . In 2020, 70% of total government expenditure on mental health in middle‐income countries was allocated to mental hospitals, compared to 35% in high‐income countries 22 . These differences need to be viewed in the context of massive global inequities in governments’ commitments to mental health more broadly. While high‐income countries spend US$ 52.7 per capita on mental health, low‐income countries spend US$ 0.08 per capita 22 .
On the other hand, it may also be the case that community‐based care does not go far enough in addressing the social determinants of mental health. While many community‐based care models focus on individuals with a mental disorder and their immediate family, very few address the fundamental structural drivers of mental illness in populations, such as inequality, poverty, food insecurity, violence, and hazardous living conditions111, 112. Successful community‐based mental health services arguably require the existence of viable communities.
The strategy of deinstitutionalization was founded on the premise that communities can provide a safe, supportive environment in which people with severe mental illness can thrive. In countries marked by high levels of poverty, inequality, civil conflict and domestic violence, this is certainly not the case. Advocating for community‐based care requires addressing the fundamental social injustices which precipitate and sustain mental illness in populations.
Furthermore, community‐based service planners may have not gone far enough in considering demand‐side drivers of mental health care. For example, in many low‐ and middle‐income countries, traditional and faith‐based healers continue to be major providers of care for people with severe mental disorders, due to the scarcity of mainstream mental health professionals, and shared beliefs about the causes and treatments of such conditions.
The effectiveness and cost‐effectiveness of collaborative shared care models with traditional and faith‐based healers has been documented in Ghana and Nigeria 113 . Similarly, the possibility of addressing demand‐side barriers by implementing a community informant detection tool, based on local idioms of distress and vignettes to identify people with various mental health conditions, has been demonstrated in Nepal 114 . These innovations from low‐ and middle‐income countries provide potential lessons for high‐income countries in developing collaborative care models that are aligned with the belief systems of mental health care users and address demand‐side barriers to care.
In summary, despite the development of community‐based services, collaborative care, shared decision‐making and recovery models, a paradigm shift towards the implementation of well‐functioning and effective community mental health care around the globe has not occurred. A red flag should be raised when plans for community‐based services are under‐resourced (for example, not providing sufficient human resources to do the work), or are over‐optimistic about implementation (for example, overlooking important barriers to shared decision‐making) 115 .
Nevertheless, community‐based models have many strengths, and should be incorporated into attempts to iteratively improve clinical practices and society responses to mental disorder. Indeed, it has been argued that the shift to community‐based services has not been a sudden change, but rather the culmination of a slow, gradual, evolutionary development, which has old historical roots and will hopefully continue over time 116 . Efforts to strengthen community‐based approaches around the world are needed to consolidate and extend the advances that have been achieved.
Taken together, the slow transition from institutional to community‐based mental health care is partly attributable to the failure of governments in low‐, middle‐ and high‐income countries to adequately invest in such care – to mandate the funding to follow people with mental disorders into their communities and provide them with the support and choices they need to live productive meaningful lives – and strategies are needed to persuade them to do so. But, perhaps to an equally important degree, there are shortcomings in models of community care, with unrealistic expectations of a dramatic paradigm shift.
CBT AND THE SCALE‐UP OF EVIDENCE‐BASED PSYCHOTHERAPY
Since its development in the 1970s, cognitive behavioral therapy (CBT) has been at the core of an important shift in clinical practice towards the use of evidence‐based psychotherapies. Hundreds of randomized controlled trials have examined the effects of CBT for a wide range of mental disorders, including depression, anxiety disorders, substance use disorders, bipolar disorder, psychotic disorders, somatoform disorders, eating disorders, personality disorders, and also other conditions, such as anger and aggression, chronic pain, and fatigue 117 . CBT has also been tested across age groups and specific target groups, such as women with perinatal conditions and people with general medical disorders 117 .
Several other types of psychotherapy have also been rigorously investigated, and even psychotherapies that had not traditionally been explored using randomized controlled trials, such as psychoanalytically oriented therapies and experiential therapies, have now also been tested using such methods118, 119, 120. Nevertheless, CBT is by far the best examined type of psychotherapy and therefore dominates the transition of the field towards the use of evidence‐based psychotherapies 121 .
CBT is highly consistent with a neurobiological model of mental disorders, insofar as it focuses on symptom reduction, improvement in functioning, and remission of the disorder. Furthermore, the literature on the neurobiological bases of behavioral and cognitive interventions has become increasingly sophisticated122, 123, and a more recent literature on process‐based CBT aligns well with the focus of RDoC on transdiagnostic mechanisms 124 . CBT can therefore be readily combined with neurobiologically oriented approaches, especially pharmacotherapy.
However, despite the strength of the evidence and its compatibility with other evidence‐based interventions, CBT has not been integrated into mental health systems globally. In many countries, it is still often seen as a reductionist approach that does not tackle the real underlying problems. Psychoanalytic approaches remain dominant, for example, in France and in Latin America 125 .
In low‐ and middle‐income countries, psychotherapies in general are often not available for people suffering from mental disorders, due to lack of resources and trained clinicians. Even in high‐income countries such as the US, the uptake of psychotherapies has declined since the 1990s 20 , while the use of antidepressant medication has increased considerably 126 , despite the fact that most patients prefer psychotherapy over pharmacotherapy 127 .
In most treatment guidelines, CBT is recommended as a first‐line treatment for several mental disorders. However, the actual implementation of such guidelines in routine care has been consistently shown to be suboptimal128, 129, 130. In addition, when CBT is employed, it is unclear whether therapists actually use it as detailed in standardized treatment protocols, or whether they combine it with other approaches.
The Increasing Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT) program in the UK represents the most ambitious attempt to address the barriers faced by evidence‐based psychotherapy, with scaling up of CBT across an entire country. The main goal of the program was to massively increase accessibility to evidence‐based psychotherapies for individuals suffering from common mental disorders, such as depression and anxiety disorders.
An important argument for massively scaling up evidence‐based therapies was economic. Depression and anxiety disorders often start during the working age, and therefore the economic costs associated with them are large, due to production losses and costs of welfare benefits. If these conditions are treated timeously, costs of treatment are balanced by increased productivity and reduced welfare costs 131 . A global return on investment analysis confirmed this assumption cross‐nationally, indicating that every invested US dollar would result in a benefit of 2.3 to 3 dollars when only economic costs are considered, and 3.3 to 5.7 dollars when the value of health returns is included 132 . Hence, the hope was that IAPT would pay for itself.
The IAPT model has a number of key features 133 . First, patients can be referred by a general practitioner or another health professional, but can also be self‐referred. People with depression, generalized anxiety disorder, mixed anxiety/depression, social anxiety disorder, post‐traumatic stress disorder (PTSD), panic disorder, agoraphobia, obsessive‐compulsive disorder, and health anxiety receive a person‐centered assessment that identifies the key problems, and an agreed‐upon course of treatment is defined 131 .
Second, IAPT works according to a stepped‐care model. Patients are first treated with an evidence‐based low‐intensity intervention, typically a self‐help intervention based on CBT. Only if this is not appropriate or patients do not recover, they receive a high‐intensity psychological treatment. Low‐intensity therapies are delivered by “psychological well‐being practitioners” who are trained to deliver guided self‐help interventions, either digitally, by telephone, or face to face. High‐intensity therapies are delivered by therapists who are fully trained in CBT or other evidence‐based interventions.
Third, the therapies offered by IAPT are those recommended by the UK National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE). When the NICE recommends different therapies for a mental disorder, patients are offered a choice of which therapy they prefer. This means that IAPT does not only deliver CBT, although a recurring criticism has been that the program is overly focused on that type of psychotherapy.
Fourth, outcome data are routinely collected in IAPT. Patients are asked to fill in various validated questionnaires before each session, so that clinicians can review the outcomes and use them in treatment planning.
Between April 1, 2019 and March 31, 2020, 1.69 million patients were referred to IAPT, of whom 1.17 million started treatment, with 606 thousand completing treatment, and 51% of them reporting recovery. The proportion of those recovered, however, is substantially lower (26%) when it is calculated based on those who started treatment (assuming that dropouts did not recover), and it has been argued that IAPT outcomes have been reported in an overly positive way134, 135.
An important issue is that the outcomes vary considerably across IAPT services. In 2015/2016, the lowest recovery rate was 21% and the highest was 63%. There is some evidence that recovery rates are higher with an increasing number of sessions and more patients stepping up to more intensive therapy 136 . Other variables that are associated with better outcomes include shorter waiting times, lower number of missed appointments, and a greater proportion of patients who go on with treatment after assessment 137 .
A recent systematic review and meta‐analysis of the IAPT program identified 60 open studies, of which 47 could be used to pool pre‐post outcome data 138 . Large pre‐post treatment effect sizes were found for depression (d=0.87, 95% CI: 0.78‐0.96) and anxiety (d=0.88, 95% CI: 0.79‐0.97), and a moderate effect for functional impairment (d=0.55, 95% CI: 0.48‐0.61).
The IAPT program arguably represents the state‐of‐the‐art for implementation of evidence‐based psychotherapy in routine clinical care. Indeed, it has served as a model for the development of similar programs in other countries 138 , including Australia 139 , Canada 140 , Norway 141 , and Japan 142 . More broadly, IAPT indicates recognition of the importance of mental health and of the allocation of sufficient resources to treatment of mental disorders, as well as acknowledgement of the importance of psychotherapies and their role in addressing mental disorders.
There are other large scale implementation programs of CBT, especially in digital mental health care. For example, MoodGYM 143 , an online CBT program for depression, had acquired over 850,000 users by 2015. Psychological task‐sharing interventions developed by the WHO, especially Problem Management Plus, have been tested in several randomized trials and are now being implemented in low‐ and middle‐income countries on a broad scale144, 145. However, the IAPT program is still the largest systematic implementation program of psychotherapies across the world.
Given the ambitiousness of IAPT, with extensive and rigorous roll‐out across an entire country, it seems reasonable to raise the key question of whether this program has had real‐world impacts, including a reduction in the disease burden of mental disorders. A first issue, however, is that comparison of IAPT with other treatment services would require a community intervention trial in which people are randomized to either IAPT or “regular” mental health care. Such a trial has not been conducted and probably never will be. Thus, although it is possible to claim on the basis of outcome data from routine care that other services are as effective as IAPT 146 , or that IAPT services may not provide interventions that match the level of complexity of the problems of patients 147 , it is difficult to validate such claims.
A second issue is whether any mental health treatments, including IAPT, are truly capable of reducing the disease burden of mental disorders. A key modeling study has estimated that current treatments only reduce about 13% of the disease burden of mental disorders at a population level 148 . In optimal conditions, in which all those with a mental disorder receive an evidence‐based treatment, this percentage can be increased to 40%. So, even under optimal conditions of 100% uptake and 100% evidence‐based treatments, reduction of disease burden is not expected to be more than 40%. This is true for IAPT as well as other programs disseminated on a broad scale.
The limited ability of current treatments to reduce the disease burden of mental disorders raises the so‐called “treatment‐prevalence paradox” 149 . This refers to the fact that clinical treatment rates have increased in the past decades, while population prevalence rates of mental disorders have not decreased. Increased availability of treatments could shorten episodes, prevent relapses, and reduce recurrences, in turn leading to lower point prevalence estimates of depression, but this has not transpired. Most meta‐analyses indicate stable prevalence rates or even small increases in prevalence, despite increased uptake of services 150 and the demonstrated efficacy of psychiatric treatments 31 .
There are several possible explanations for this “treatment‐prevalence paradox” 149 . First, it is possible that prevalence rates of depression have dropped, but that at the same time incidence has increased due to societal changes. Second, it is possible that prevalence rates have dropped, but that emotional distress has been more often diagnosed as a depressive disorder over the past decades, thereby masking the drop. Third, it is possible that prevalence rates have not dropped, because treatments may not be as effective as the field would like 151 . Indeed, treatment effects may be overestimated in trials due to publication bias, selective outcome reporting, use of inappropriate control groups, or the allegiance effect. Moreover, treatments may not benefit chronic depressive patients, or treatments may have iatrogenic effects that block natural recovery and prolong depressive episodes 152 .
Taken together, the development of evidence‐based psychotherapies has been a remarkable step forward for psychiatry, and the scale‐up of such effective psychotherapies in IAPT and other large‐scale implementation programs has contributed to consolidating this advancement. That said, the several criticisms of IAPT suggest that it is by no means a panacea. Instead, the implementation of evidence‐based psychotherapies is arguably best conceptualized as representing incremental progress. The impact of evidence‐based treatments on the disease burden of mental disorders currently appears to be modest; and the time horizons for introduction of interventions that are notably more successful is unclear.
DIGITAL PHENOTYPING AND DIGITAL THERAPIES
Rapid technological advances and the expansion of the Internet have spurred the development and widespread use of a host of digital devices with the potential to transform psychiatric research and practice 153 . Indeed, the fourth industrial revolution and the nudge towards telepsychiatry by the COVID‐19 pandemic have already revealed that digital technologies provide novel opportunities to improve psychiatric diagnosis, expand the delivery of mental health care, and collect large quantities of data for psychiatric research154, 155.
There are many examples of how these advances have enabled digital solutions in psychiatry156, 157. To name a few, virtual reality can facilitate exposure therapy for phobias and PTSD 158 , chatbots can deliver remote CBT anonymously day‐and‐night 159 , computer analysis of closed circuit television (CCTV) images can identify suicide attempts in progress at suicide hot‐spots 160 , voice and facial recognition software may enhance psychiatric diagnosis161, 162, wearable devices may enable real‐time monitoring and evaluation of patients 163 , analyses of human‐computer interaction may detect manic and depressive episodes in real‐time 164 , and suicide risk may be assessed by analysis of social media posts 165 .
Furthermore, the widespread use of digital medical records, the collection of vast quantities of data from individuals via smart devices, the ability to link multiple databases, and the use of machine learning algorithms have redefined the use of big data in psychiatry with the promise of overcoming the failures of conventional statistical methods and small samples to capture the underlying heterogeneity of psychiatric phenotypes81, 82, 83. The ability to access, store and manipulate data, together with the use of machine learning algorithms, promises to advance the practice of individualized medicine in psychiatry by allowing matching of patients with the most appropriate therapies81, 82, 83.
Smartphone use is now ubiquitous even in remote and resource‐constrained environments across the globe 166 , making these devices a powerful medium to improve access to psychiatric care 167 . Smartphones are already being used to deliver interventions for common mental disorders168, 169, 170, 171, and more than 10,000 mental health apps are available in the commercial marketplace 172 . There is considerable potential to turn smartphones into cost‐effective and cost‐efficient treatment portals by literally placing mental health interventions in the hands of the 6,378 billion people who own these devices (i.e., 87% of the world's population), many of whom do not currently have access to mental health care.
As communication devices, smartphones can be used to facilitate peer support, deliver personalized messages, provide access to psychoeducational resources, and facilitate timely referrals to appropriate in‐person clinical care 153 . The communication capabilities of smartphones have enabled the expansion of telepsychiatry via high‐quality low‐cost voice and video calls 173 , with evidence indicating that the use of video conferencing is not inferior to in‐person psychiatric consultations 174 .
Because smartphones are equipped with a range of sensors and the ability to store and upload data, they can be easily used to collect real‐time active data (i.e., data which the user deliberately and actively provides in response to prompts). Active data collected via smartphones are already being used in psychiatry for ecological momentary assessments, cognitive assessments, diagnosis, symptom monitoring, and relapse prevention175, 176. Beyond these clinical applications, smartphones are also powerful tools for data collection in psychiatric research177, 178.
Digital devices, including smartphones and wearables, can also collect and store a host of passive data (that is, data generated as a by‐product of using the device for everyday tasks, without the active participation of the user) with near zero marginal costs. These passive data have been likened to fingerprints or digital footprints. They provide objective continuous longitudinal measures of individuals’ moment‐to‐moment behavior in their natural environments and could be used to develop precise and temporally dynamic markers of psychiatric illness, a practice known as digital phenotyping155, 179.
If digital phenotyping delivers on its promises, it will enable continuous inexpensive surveillance of mental disorders in large populations, early identification of at‐risk individuals who can then be nudged to access psychiatric treatment, and early identification of treatment failure to prompt timely individualized treatment decisions 180 . These potential applications are important, given the dearth of accurate real‐time psychiatric surveillance systems in many parts of the world, individuals’ reluctance to seek treatment at the early stages of psychiatric illness, and the high rates of treatment failure which necessitate timely adjustments to management.
Identifying digital markers for mental disorders is, however, not without potential pitfalls, that will need to be mapped and navigated before digital phenotyping can realize its full potential. There are still unanswered questions about the sensitivity, reliability and validity of smartphone sensors for health monitoring and diagnosis 181 . Furthermore, there appears to be a bias in measurement of everyday activities from smartphone sensors, because of variations in how people use their devices 182 . It still remains to be seen if actuarial models developed from population level digital footprints are clinically useful at the level of individual patients, as well as how digital phenotyping can be meaningfully integrated into routine clinical practice, and how patients will respond to and accept passive monitoring of their day‐to‐day activities180, 183.
Digital solutions are not without shortcomings, and a digital intervention is not necessarily better than no intervention184, 185, 186. Reviews of the quality and efficacy of mental health apps indicate that there is often little evidence to support the effectiveness of direct‐to‐consumer apps184, 185, 186. Even when mental health apps seem to be useful, data indicate that many of them suffer from high rates of attrition and are not used long enough or consistently enough to be effective 187 .
Concerns about data privacy and security are a significant obstacle to expanding the use of digital technologies in psychiatric practice and research188, 189. Psychiatry is often concerned with deeply personal, sensitive, and potentially embarrassing information, that requires secure data storage and stringent privacy safeguards. The risks associated with collecting and storing digital mental health information need to be clearly articulated in terms that patients understand, so that they can provide informed consent. Privacy policies in digital solutions such as smartphone apps are unfortunately often written in inaccessible language and “legalese”, making them incomprehensible to many users 189 , and there is as yet insufficient regulation of mental health apps and no minimum safety standards 188 .
While digital technology use has increased across the globe, there are ongoing inequalities in the access to these technologies within and between countries 166 . The rapid digitalization of psychiatry may unintentionally exacerbate health inequalities if digital mental health solutions cannot be shared 190 . Psychiatry will need to grapple with thorny questions about how to share digital technologies with those most in need of access to mental health care, and how to develop digital solutions for culturally diverse resource‐constrained environments. High data costs, unstable Internet connections, and bandwidth limitations can create logistical constraints on the utilization of digital mental health solutions in low‐income countries 191 .
The development of digital mental health solutions has typically been driven by the information technology industry and commercial interests 172 . On the other hand, the demand for mental health apps has been largely driven by consumers through social media, personal searches, and word of mouth, rather than professional recommendations 192 . Commercialization of health care and the repositioning of patients as customers has certainly created some efficiencies in health care delivery 193 . However, the profit motive is not always aligned with good patient care, as illustrated by the recent opioid crisis 194 .
Ensuring that clinicians are part of the process of digitalization of psychiatry will entail training them to understand, use and develop digital technologies; establishing ethical guidelines for the use of these technologies; ensuring independent evaluation of the effectiveness of digital interventions by researchers who have no commercial interest in the products; and protecting patient safety by ensuring that the claims made about the benefits of digital solutions are supported by robust evidence.
Emerging evidence suggests that screen time may be associated with mental health problems, although most of the work in this area focuses on children and adolescents195, 196, 197. While research is mostly cross‐sectional, there are a small number of longitudinal studies showing that screen time has small to very small effects on subsequent depressive symptoms, and that these associations depend on device type and use198, 199. If screen time is bad for mental health, would it be wise to promote the use of digital mental health interventions that entail more time online or in front of a screen? This is not an easy question to answer, and the answer is likely not a simple yes or no.
The challenge is to think about how digitizing psychiatry can be balanced with a careful understanding of the potential for digital devices to harm mental health. Few interventions in psychiatry are without potential side effects, and it would be naïve to think that digital ones are different. As with any psychiatric treatment, the prescription of digital interventions needs to be accompanied with consideration of the contraindications, advice about how to use the intervention to its maximum benefit, and warnings about potential side effects and how to manage them. To enable this we require data, which we do not yet have, about the contraindications and side effects of digital interventions 188 .
We already have evidence to show that digital technologies can be at least as effective as traditional practices in making a psychiatric diagnosis, identifying appropriate individualized interventions, and teaching psychological skills such as mindfulness and attentional training180, 200, 201. Yet, most clinicians would likely agree that psychiatric practice is fundamentally relational and that most mental illnesses have an interpersonal dimension. The increasing use of technology in psychiatry will change the relationship between physician and patient in ways that we probably do not yet understand and cannot anticipate.
How technology is utilized in psychiatry will be a function of how central we think relationships are in diagnosis and treatment, and whether or not we see digital technologies as primarily a tool to enhance the therapeutic relationship, or simply a conduit to deliver content or collect and process information 202 . Theories will need to be developed to conceptualize and understand the digital therapeutic relationship, while we hold in mind the potential to harness technology to deepen the relationship between clinicians and patients. Indeed, evidence suggests that digital interventions are most effective when they have at least some person‐to‐person interaction179, 200.
Digital technologies may change the way psychiatry is practiced, but to date much of the research in this area has been experimental, with proof‐of‐concept and clinical trials in highly controlled settings using very small samples 172 . The translational potential of these technologies has not yet been realized, and we still have some way to go to bring digital advances in mental health “from code to clinic” 172 . There are relatively few examples of digital technologies other than teleconferencing being used routinely in everyday real‐world psychiatric practice, and there is an urgent need for pragmatic trials and translational research to understand the barriers to adoption and implementation of new technologies 203 . The attitudes of clinicians and patients towards digital solutions in psychiatry and their perceptions of the effectiveness and safety of these devices are important determinants of how widely new technologies will be adopted.
Taken together, the science is still too young to let us know the extent to which the introduction of digital technologies will truly constitute a paradigm shift in psychiatric diagnosis and treatment, and whether these technologies will deliver on their promise to reduce the burden of disease caused by mental disorders. The available evidence gives cause for optimism and suggests that these technologies could assist in iteratively progressing the science and practice of psychiatry. However, there are many red flags when it comes to digital psychiatry, including overpromising with regards to efficacy and overlooking the human relationship. In order for iterative progress to happen, we will need continuous critical reflection, with an ongoing emphasis on equitable access, appropriate regulation, and quality assurance 204 .
GLOBAL MENTAL HEALTH AND TASK‐SHARING
The concept of global health emerged in the aftermath of World War II, when cross‐national organizations were needed to coordinate health efforts, particularly against infectious diseases 205 . The WHO was established in 1948, and became a key advocate for global health, exemplifying the key pillars of this approach, including the recognition that health is a public good requiring support from all sectors of the governments, that health involves a continuum ranging from wellness to illness, and that the determinants of health are biological, sociocultural and environmental 206 . Global health saw the protection of human rights as a central concern of all action concerning health, and expected that action to improve health includes the formulation of working policies addressing upstream social determinants of health, and a strengthening of health services 207 .
With growing recognition of the burden of non‐communicable diseases, including mental, neurological and substance use disorders, global mental health became an important focus. B. Chisholm, a psychiatrist who was the first WHO Director General, introduced the mantra “No health without mental health” 208 . An early 4x4 model of non‐communicable diseases emphasized the comorbidity of cardiovascular diseases, diabetes, cancer and respiratory diseases with tobacco use, unhealthy diet, physical inactivity and harmful alcohol use as risk factors for these conditions. A later 5x5 approach has emphasized that these non‐communicable diseases are commonly comorbid with mental disorders, and that childhood adversity is an important common risk factor 209 .
Over the past several decades, global mental health has become a significant discipline, with specific departments established at several leading universities, textbooks and journals devoted to the subject, and significant support for research obtained from funders 210 . In addition to a focus on mental health as a public good and human right, on mental health as entailing a continuum and a life course approach, on the importance of social determinants of mental health, and on the need of strengthening mental health services, work in global mental health has emphasized the efficacy of task‐shifting interventions, the importance of addressing stigma, and the value of including service users’ perspectives in research and planning1, 2.
Early work by the WHO, and subsequent work by others in global mental health, has led to important contributions. A first key contribution has been the recognition of the burden of mental disorders, and advocacy that this burden needs to be urgently and appropriately addressed. There are far too few mental health clinicians in low‐ and middle‐income countries, where the vast majority of the world's population resides 22 .
A second key contribution has been a focus on addressing mental health in primary care. In the 1970s, the WHO conducted a multinational collaborative study demonstrating the feasibility and effectiveness of offering community‐based mental health care, delivered by primary health care workers, in developing countries 211 . A few years later, in 1978, the Primary Health Care Conference in Alma Ata, composed of representatives of almost all countries in the world, included the promotion of mental health into the list of essential components of primary health care.
Nevertheless, global health in general and global mental health in particular have faced many challenges. Early hopes were that globalization would entail a border‐free world with easy communication, trade, and mutual support. However, globalization has also arguably allowed unidirectional unloading of products of the North to the less industrially developed South, and a simultaneous migration of many individuals, including health professionals, from the global South to the North. Colonial practices, including large psychiatric hospitals, have remained in existence in many low‐income countries. Rapid urbanization and breakdown of traditional communities, which provided some support to vulnerable individuals, have further complicated the provision of health care. The introduction of digital technologies – which has been considered as a potential equalizer – also runs the risk of creating a new divide, the digital divide.
In terms of the clinical practice of psychiatry, while the numbers of psychiatrists and other mental health care workers has significantly increased across the globe, their inequitable distribution has not significantly improved 22 . There are still many countries with only a few psychiatrists, and the brain drain – the movement of fully trained psychiatrists from the global South to the North – continues 212 . Training programs which can be used for primary health care providers in mental health have been produced by the WHO and other agencies, and the situation has improved in some countries, but the numbers of those left with no adequate care remain high. Primary care practitioners are not always willing to accept responsibility for the treatment of mental disorders, and many well‐trained psychiatrists have continued to work in private health care services that reach only a minority of those who need help.
Earlier sections of this paper considered some of the concerns about current psychiatry nosology raised by neurobiologically‐focused and “number‐driven” researchers. But even from a public health perspective, application of key aspects of the chapter on mental disorders of the ICD rises problems 213 . First, most practicing clinicians feel that in daily work the number of diagnostic categories proposed for use should follow the number of options for therapeutic interventions, and so ICD approaches may be too complex. Second, reporting about inpatient mental health services to national authorities in most instances follows the guidelines provided by hospitals, which do not allow for the collection of sufficiently detailed or validated data. The interpretation of findings may be made even more difficult by the fact that in federal countries the rules of reporting to the central authority differ from area to area.
Global mental health has been crucially important in putting forward a number of innovative models and approaches. At the same time, critics might suggest that the strategies of global mental health are not so much an entirely new paradigm but instead a re‐packaging of long‐standing ideas in the field, and that each of these strategies has important limitations which deserve emphasis.
First, global mental health has focused on the notion of “task‐shifting”. This involves the use of non‐specialized health care workers, who are trained and supervised by mental health specialists. Systematic reviews have concluded that there is now considerable evidence for the efficacy of this approach3, 214. Nevertheless, this strategy is not a panacea. There are limits to what can be done by untrained personnel. The treatment of more complex conditions, such as treatment‐refractory mental disorders, requires well‐trained clinicians. Moreover, significant supervision and monitoring may be required, and this entails human and financial resources. There is now interest in how to assess therapist competence in task‐shifting trials215, 216. Finally, there is a difference between demonstration projects conducted by academic researchers and real‐life scale‐up projects undertaken by governments. Pharmacotherapy outcomes are worse in real‐world pragmatic trials than in academic‐centre explanatory trials, and we might expect that the same will hold true in the case of task‐shifting research.
A second important strategy of global mental health has been to build the investment case for mental health, demonstrating the return on investment for countries scaling up community‐based care. As noted earlier, this gave key impetus to the implementation of psychotherapies in the UK. However, a number of challenges remain. Many economic returns accrue to sectors outside ministries of health, which traditionally hold mental health budgets. Economic returns on scaled‐up mental health care are likely to accrue through improved labour market participation, reduced homelessness, and savings to correctional services and police services, and not necessarily to the health sector. Moreover, such savings might only be realized at some time in the future, creating what has been termed pernicious “diagonal accounting” 217 . Finally, it must be conceded that not all investment in mental health – for example, care for those with severe neurodevelopmental disorders – will yield significant economic returns.
A third key strategy of global mental health has been to focus on building stronger, better coordinated advocacy, with partnerships between people with lived experience and clinicians to campaign for better and more resources for mental health care. It has been argued that ongoing dialogue between the various stakeholders involved in community‐based care is essential to reach common ground on service development priorities. This should also include maximizing opportunities for leadership from people with lived experience, to address demand‐side barriers to community‐based mental health care. Nevertheless, there are key barriers to advocacy work, including low mental health literacy of policy‐makers, and a gap in frameworks linking research to policy 218 .
A fourth key strategy of global mental health has been to focus on stigma reduction strategies. Certainly, reducing stigma and discrimination against people living with mental illness is vital if we are to promote care in the community. Furthermore, there is a growing evidence base for the positive impact of stigma reduction campaigns for mental health, such as the World Psychiatric Association's “Open the Doors” program. At the same time, there are important challenges to acknowledge. Much more needs to be done to both improve the effectiveness of these interventions and extend stigma reduction programmes to a range of different countries 219 . Stigma reduction strategies should not deny the dysfunction that accompanies severe mental disorders (services for such conditions remain sorely needed), and they need to also highlight that individuals suffering from psychiatric disorders have “responsibility without blame” 220 . Finally, it is notable that, in some contexts, providing neurobiologically focused information increases rather than decreases stigma 221 .
A fifth key strategy of global mental health is to address social determinants of mental disorders. Governments need to address fundamental social injustice such as rampant inequality, high unemployment, civil conflict and violence, particularly gender‐based violence, that drive mental disorders in populations 222 . That said, the evidence base for population‐level interventions to address the social determinants of mental health is rather sparse and of low quality 223 . Ironically, global mental health has been accused of ignoring key contextual data 224 , and of perpetuating some of the sociopolitical inequities it critiques 225 . Less contentiously, while some clinicians may well contribute to efforts focused on social determinants, the majority will focus on providing direct clinical care. Public mental health skills are needed to supplement, rather than replace, standard clinical training.
Taken together, it is clear that the concepts and methods of global mental health have many strengths, have contributed to important advances, and should be incorporated into further attempts to incrementally improve health policies as well as clinical practice. As always, discourse about a paradigm shift and over‐optimism about the extent of envisaged change raise red flags. Indeed, the key strategies of global mental health that may facilitate ongoing incremental progress may themselves require iterative attention: we need to continue to be innovative about task‐sharing, to gradually strengthen the investment case, to steadily develop better advocacy strategies, to further reduce stigma about mental disorders and increase mental health literacy, and to better address social determinants of these conditions.
DISCUSSION
Kuhn's notion of scientific paradigms has been extraordinarily influential 226 . He argued that most of science is “normal”: scientists have a particular conceptual framework, with various exemplars that are key for the field, which allows them to address a range of relatively minor “puzzles” 227 . However, from time to time, there is a paradigm shift, with an entirely new conceptual framework and new exemplars coming to fore and causing a “crisis”, and so entailing a major revolution in the field. Thus, for example, at one point phlogiston was thought to explain combustion, but this paradigm was replaced by one that emphasized the importance of oxygen, providing an entirely new perspective. Notably, from a “critical” perspective, scientific paradigms are incommensurable; those who adopt different paradigms are really talking past one another, and the shift from one paradigm to another happens not because of scientific advancement, but rather due to a sociopolitical shift in the field228, 229.
From this perspective, psychiatry has been characterized by a history of continual paradigm shifts, with the field lurching over time from one set of models to another, with no substantive scientific advances in our knowledge, but rather merely a responsiveness to the prevailing sociopolitical winds of the day 229 . Thus, as noted earlier, psychiatry has seen movements from psychodynamic approaches to neuroscientific ones, and from institutional care to community‐based care. While a good deal of the critique of psychiatry has come from external fields, there is a significant contribution from within the discipline, with proponents of new paradigms at times being very critical of current practices. The idea that psychiatry is in crisis seems to be prevalent and persistent in both the professional literature and in social media230, 231, 232, 233, 234.
We would argue strongly against this view of psychiatry. This is not to disagree that there have been important shifts in the field over its history: there certainly have been. Nor is it to disagree with the valid points that sociopolitical and sociocultural factors are key to such issues as determining budgets for mental health services, and in influencing the experience and expression of mental disorders 235 . Nor is to deny or downplay the many crucial challenges that continue to face psychiatry as a profession, and psychiatrists as practitioners236, 237. And perhaps most importantly, it is not to ignore or to minimize the enormity of the treatment and the research‐practice gaps discussed in detail earlier in this paper. Clearly, considerably more needs to be done to improve mental health care services, and to effectively address the burden of disease due to mental disorder.
However, we wish to emphasize that there has been a gradual accretion of knowledge about mental disorders, and that our understanding of their causes and our ability to manage them has significantly increased over time. We also wish to argue that the different proposals for the field discussed in this paper are not necessarily incommensurable paradigms, but rather are important perspectives that can productively be drawn on and integrated into contemporary practice 238 . The integration of clinical neuroscience and global mental health, for example, may facilitate advances in precision public mental health 239 . Space precludes a detailed consideration of a range of other innovative perspectives that may also contribute to the incremental and integrative advance of psychiatric practice, including collaborative care 240 , preventive psychiatry 241 , evolutionary psychiatry 242 , positive psychiatry 243 , intergenerational psychiatry 244 , and welfarist psychiatry 245 .
Perhaps most importantly, we would wish to problematize the notion that psychiatry is in perennial and perpetual crisis. Tools provided by “critical” authors, who emphasize the sociopolitical aspects of science and medicine, may be in fact be useful in investigating why psychiatry is so often viewed in this way, and why a view of psychiatry as steadily accreting knowledge and improving clinical practices is less often put forward than seems reasonable, even from within the field. Are there specific interests that stand to gain from negative views of the psychiatric profession? What are the benefits to particular authors of being overly critical of existing practices and of promising entirely novel or disruptive solutions? What can be done to encourage those without and within the field to emphasize that scientific progress is often iterative and incremental, with gradual consolidation of knowledge, with inclusion and integration of a range of different models and approaches?
We have noted in this paper a number of red flags, which seem indicative of overly optimistic promises of a paradigm shift in psychiatry practice and research, and that may inadvertently even support an antipsychiatry position that discourages patients from seeking sorely needed professional care, or policy‐makers from funding desperately needed mental health care services. A few of these red flags deserve particular emphasis here.
First, given the complexity of mental disorders, and the need to avoid both a brainless and a mindless psychiatry 246 , various forms of reductionism serve as red flags, whether these involve neuro‐reductionism (e.g., mental disorders are merely brain disorders) or culturalism (e.g., mental disorders merely reflect social inequalities). As a field, we should promote the breadth and depth of psychiatric concepts and findings, emphasizing that psychiatry builds bridges across biological, psychological and social domains, and that – despite the complexity of mental disorders – this has allowed important insights into their phenomenology and etiology, and has facilitated the development of a broad range of different evidence‐based treatment modalities and types of intervention. The complexity of mental disorders may, however, mean that there are few “silver bullets” in psychiatry: any individual mental health intervention may have only modest effect sizes, and reduction of disease burden due to mental disorders is a massive goal, likely requiring a broad range of interventions 247 .
Second, economic over‐optimism may be a red flag: bringing new drugs to market requires significant financial investment, deinstitutionalization is not an inexpensive option, and it is a challenge to demonstrate that large‐scale implementation programs such as IAPT save money. While a range of different metaphors may be useful in describing psychiatric work, and in encouraging policy‐makers to fund mental health services, we need perhaps to be particularly careful of seeing patients as merely consumers, and psychiatry as simply providing a return on investment. Similarly, while a collaborative relationship between professional clinicians and patient partners may be useful in encouraging shared decision‐making, this metaphor of psychiatric work and mental health services may miss some aspects of the clinical encounter. The metaphor of clinicians providing care is a crucial one, and we need to call for more such care, even if at times it is somewhat expensive 115 .
Third, calls for a radical transformation of psychiatry's research agenda are a red flag. Hubris may result in downplaying what has already been achieved over decades, or in overly focusing on one or other favoured perspective. A more humble position that emphasizes how difficult is to know what approaches and models will lead to the largest advances, that encourages a broad range of promising work, that insists on principles of reproducible science including the common metrics agenda, and that acknowledges the key role of serendipity, is appropriate64, 248, 249. Analogously, calls for a radical transformation or narrowing of the training curriculum also constitute a red flag: psychiatry trainees need exposure to a broad range of concepts and methods, including neuroscience, statistics, evidence‐based psychotherapy, digital psychiatry, and public mental health. The field needs well‐rounded graduates who are able to access and employ the full range of concepts and findings from our rich discipline.
How can we facilitate an ongoing focus on incremental advances in clinical practice, with integration of a range of different perspectives and findings? It may be useful to approach the issues discussed in this paper with a particular knowledge of how science works, and with a particular attitude towards progress.
From the perspective of knowledge, it seems useful to emphasize that concepts of scientific crisis and paradigm shifts often serve as rhetorical devices, that in sciences ranging from physics to psychiatry multiple approaches and models are potentially useful, and that in psychiatry there is a particular need for pluralistic and pragmatic approaches that integrate a range of different concepts, methods and findings229, 250. From the perspective of attitude, we would emphasize the value of staying hopeful, avoiding hype, and committing to the important work of closing the treatment gap as well as the research‐practice gap.
Thus, in terms used earlier in this paper, the solution to challenges in psychiatric diagnosis and treatment is unlikely to lie in entirely novel paradigms, but rather in the humble, laborious, iterative work of systematic clinical observation, painstaking research, and creative thinking. In the case of psychiatric assessment, for example, we have elsewhere argued for the need for more work on post‐diagnostic assessments and measures that are consistent with measurement‐based care and that promote personalized psychiatry251, 252, 253. In the case of psychiatric treatment, addressing the treatment and the research‐practice gaps will require more attention to expanding innovative delivery models that will reach more people in need 254 , systematic adoption and roll‐out of integrated evidence‐based interventions 255 , and an iterative discovery‐confirmation process to assess and improve efficacy 256 .
In conclusion, this review of a range of proposed approaches to and models of diagnosis and treatment of mental disorders suggests caution in concluding that we are facing a crisis in psychiatry which necessitates a disruptive transitioning from traditional to new practices. We argue instead that an approach which emphasizes paradigm shifts should be replaced by one that focuses on the importance and value of incremental and integrative advances. In particular, we caution against an advocacy for paradigm shifts that inadvertently represents a disguised manifestation of antipsychiatry, and we instead suggest the need for a position that emphasizes both the accomplishments and limitations of psychiatric diagnosis and treatment, and that is cautiously optimistic about their future.
FORUM – PSYCHIATRIC PRACTICE AND RESEARCH: THE VALUE OF INCREMENTAL AND INTEGRATIVE ADVANCES
REFERENCES
- 1. Patel V, Saxena S, Lund C et al. The Lancet Commission on global mental health and sustainable development. Lancet 2018;392:1553‐98. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2. Collins PY. What is global mental health? World Psychiatry 2020;19:265‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3. van Ginneken N, Chin WY, Lim YC et al. Primary‐level worker interventions for the care of people living with mental disorders and distress in low‐ and middle‐income countries. Cochrane Database Syst Rev 2021;8:CD009149. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4. Mills C. Decolonizing global mental health: the psychiatrization of the majority world. London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- 5. Wilson M. DSM‐III and the transformation of American psychiatry: a history. Am J Psychiatry 1993;150:399‐410. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6. Kendler KS. A history of the DSM‐5 scientific review committee. Psychol Med 2013;43:1793‐800. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7. Reed GM, First MB, Kogan CS et al. Innovations and changes in the ICD‐11 classification of mental, behavioural and neurodevelopmental disorders. World Psychiatry 2019;18:3‐19. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. Cuthbert BN, Insel TR. Toward the future of psychiatric diagnosis: the seven pillars of RDoC. BMC Med 2013;11:126. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9. Deyo RA, Patrick DL. Hope or hype: the obsession with medical advances and the high cost of false promises. J Clin Invest 2005;115:2960. [Google Scholar]
- 10. Weissman SH. The evolution of psychiatric subspecialties. Psychiatr Q 1991;62:145‐52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11. First MB. Clinical utility in the revision of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM). Prof Psychol Res Pr 2010;41:465‐73. [Google Scholar]
- 12. First MB, Gaebel W, Maj M et al. An organization‐ and category‐level comparison of diagnostic requirements for mental disorders in ICD‐11 and DSM‐5. World Psychiatry 2021;20:34‐51. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13. Moynihan R. Selling sickness: how the world's biggest pharmaceutical companies are turning us all into patients. New York: National Books, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- 14. Clark LA, Cuthbert B, Lewis‐Fernández R et al. Three approaches to understanding and classifying mental disorder: ICD‐11, DSM‐5, and the National Institute of Mental Health's Research Domain Criteria (RDoC). Psychol Sci Public Interest 2017;18:72‐145. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15. Engel G. The need for a new medical model: a challenge for biomedicine. Science 1977;196:129‐36. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16. Álvarez AS, Pagani M, Meucci P. The clinical application of the biopsychosocial model in mental health: a research critique. Am J Phys Med Rehabil 2012;91:S173‐80. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17. Ghaemi SN. The rise and fall of the biopsychosocial model: reconciling art and science in psychiatry. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- 18. Bolton D, Gillett G. The biopsychosocial model of health and disease: new philosophical and scientific developments. Cham: Palgrave Pivot, 2019. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19. Kendler KS. The dappled nature of causes of psychiatric illness: replacing the organic–functional/hardware‐software dichotomy with empirically based pluralism. Mol Psychiatry 2012;17:377‐88. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20. Olfson M, Marcus SC. National trends in outpatient psychotherapy. Am J Psychiatry 2010;167:1456‐63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21. Hadjipavlou G, Hernandez CAS, Ogrodniczuk JS. Psychotherapy in contemporary psychiatric practice. Can J Psychiatry 2015;60:294‐300. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22. World Health Organization . Mental health atlas 2020. Geneva: World Health Organization, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- 23. Munk‐Jørgensen P, Blanner Kristiansen C, Uwawke R et al. The gap between available knowledge and its use in clinical psychiatry. Acta Psychiatr Scand 2015;132:441‐50. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24. Andrade LH, Alonso J, Mneimneh Z et al. Barriers to mental health treatment: results from the WHO World Mental Health surveys. Psychol Med 2014;44:1303‐17. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25. Zimmerman M. A review of 20 years of research on overdiagnosis and underdiagnosis in the Rhode Island Methods to Improve Diagnostic Assessment and Services (MIDAS) Project. Can J Psychiatry 2016;61:71‐9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26. Vigo D, Haro JM, Hwang I et al. Toward measuring effective treatment coverage: critical bottlenecks in quality‐ and user‐adjusted coverage for major depressive disorder. Psychol Med 2020; doi: 10.1017/S0033291720003797. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27. Möller HJ, Maier W. Evidence‐based medicine in psychopharmacotherapy: possibilities, problems and limitations. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 2010;260:25‐39. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28. Girlanda F, Fiedler I, Becker T et al. The evidence‐practice gap in specialist mental healthcare: systematic review and meta‐analysis of guideline implementation studies. Br J Psychiatry 2017;210:24‐30. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29. Fulford KWM. Values‐based practice: a new partner to evidence‐based practice and a first for psychiatry. Mens Sana Monogr 2008;6:10‐21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30. Pincus HA, Zarin DA, Tanielian TL et al. Psychiatric patients and treatments in 1997: findings from the American Psychiatric Practice Research Network. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1999;56:441‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31. Leucht S, Hierl S, Kissling W et al. Putting the efficacy of psychiatric and general medicine medication into perspective: review of meta‐analyses. Br J Psychiatry 2012;200:97‐106. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32. Harris MG, Kazdin AE, Munthali RJ et al. Perceived helpfulness of service sectors used for mental and substance use disorders: findings from the WHO World Mental Health Surveys. Int J Ment Health Syst 2022;16:6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33. Chapman A, Williams C, Hannah J et al. Reimagining the mental health paradigm for our collective well‐being. Health Hum Rights 2020;22:1‐6. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34. Penzenstadler L, Khazaal Y, Fleury MJ. Editorial: Community‐based outreach treatment for addictions and concomitant disorders: time for a change of paradigm. Front Psychiatry 2020;11:2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35. Fu CHY, Costafreda SG. Neuroimaging‐based biomarkers in psychiatry: clinical opportunities of a paradigm shift. Can J Psychiatry 2013;58:499‐508. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36. Leichsenring F, Steinert C, Ioannidis JPA. Toward a paradigm shift in treatment and research of mental disorders. Psychol Med 2019;49:2111‐7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37. Cˇ ešková E, Šilhán P. From personalized medicine to precision psychiatry? Neuropsychiatr Dis Treat 2021;17:3663‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38. Salazar de Pablo G, Studerus E, Vaquerizo‐Serrano J et al. Implementing precision psychiatry: a systematic review of individualized prediction models for clinical practice. Schizophr Bull 2021;47:284‐97. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39. Perna G, Grassi M, Caldirola D et al. The revolution of personalized psychiatry: will technology make it happen sooner? Psychol Med 2018;48:705‐13. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40. Hyman SE. Can neuroscience be integrated into the DSM‐V? Nat Rev Neurosci 2007;8:725‐32. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41. The Brainstorm Consortium , Anttila V, Bulik‐Sullivan B et al. Analysis of shared heritability in common disorders of the brain. Science 2018;360:eaap8757. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42. Hyman SE. Psychiatric disorders: grounded in human biology but not natural kinds. Perspect Biol Med 2021;64:6‐28. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43. Kapur S, Phillips AG, Insel TR. Why has it taken so long for biological psychiatry to develop clinical tests and what to do about it? Mol Psychiatry 2012;17:1174‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44. Insel TR, Quirion R. Psychiatry as a clinical neuroscience discipline. JAMA 2005;294:2221‐4. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45. Cuthbert BN. The RDoC framework: facilitating transition from ICD/DSM to dimensional approaches that integrate neuroscience and psychopathology. World Psychiatry 2014;13:28‐35. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46. Fox AS, Kalin NH. A translational neuroscience approach to understanding the development of social anxiety disorder and its pathophysiology. Am J Psychiatry 2014;171:1162‐73. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47. Dougherty DD, Brennan BP, Stewart SE et al. Neuroscientifically informed formulation and treatment planning for patients with obsessive‐compulsive disorder: a review. JAMA Psychiatry 2018;75:1081‐7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48. Ressler KJ. Translating across circuits and genetics toward progress in fear‐ and anxiety‐related disorders. Am J Psychiatry 2020;177:214‐22. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49. Mataix‐Cols D, Fernández de la Cruz L, Monzani B et al. D‐Cycloserine augmentation of exposure‐based cognitive behavior therapy for anxiety, obsessive‐compulsive, and posttraumatic stress disorders: a systematic review and meta‐analysis of individual participant data. JAMA Psychiatry 2017;74:501‐10. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50. Pollak SD. Developmental psychopathology: recent advances and future challenges. World Psychiatry 2015;14:262‐9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51. Teicher MH, Gordon JB, Nemeroff CB. Recognizing the importance of childhood maltreatment as a critical factor in psychiatric diagnoses, treatment, research, prevention, and education. Mol Psychiatry 2022;27:1331‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52. Van Praag HM, Asnis GM, Kahn RS et al. Nosological tunnel vision in biological psychiatry. A plea for a functional psychopathology. Ann NY Acad Sci 1990;600:501‐10. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53. Stein DJ. An integrative approach to psychiatric diagnosis and research. World Psychiatry 2014;13:51‐3. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54. Murray GK, Lin T, Austin J et al. Could polygenic risk scores be useful in psychiatry?: A review. JAMA Psychiatry 2021;78:210‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55. Phillips EJ, Sukasem C, Whirl‐Carrillo M et al. Clinical Pharmacogenetics Implementation Consortium guideline for HLA genotype and use of carbamazepine and oxcarbazepine: 2017 update. Clin Pharmacol Ther 2018;103:574‐81. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56. Bousman CA, Bengesser SA, Aitchison KJ et al. Review and consensus on pharmacogenomic testing in psychiatry. Pharmacopsychiatry 2021;54:5‐17. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57. Thompson PM, Jahanshad N, Ching CRK et al. ENIGMA and global neuroscience: a decade of large‐scale studies of the brain in health and disease across more than 40 countries. Transl Psychiatry 2020;10:100. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58. Sullivan PF, Agrawal A, Bulik CM al et. Psychiatric genomics: an update and an agenda. Am J Psychiatry 2018;175:15‐27. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59. Choi KW, Stein MB, Nishimi KM et al. An exposure‐wide and Mendelian randomization approach to identifying modifiable factors for the prevention of depression. Am J Psychiatry 2020;177:944‐54. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60. Weinberger DR, Radulescu E. Finding the elusive psychiatric “lesion” with 21st‐century neuroanatomy: a note of caution. Am J Psychiatry 2016;173:27‐33. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61. Gordon JA. From neurobiology to novel medications: a principled approach to translation. Am J Psychiatry 2019;176:425‐7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62. Arbuckle MR, Travis MJ, Eisen J et al. Transforming psychiatry from the classroom to the clinic: lessons from the National Neuroscience Curriculum Initiative. Acad Psychiatry 2020;44:29‐36. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63. Carvalho AF, Solmi M, Sanches M et al. Evidence‐based umbrella review of 162 peripheral biomarkers for major mental disorders. Transl Psychiatry 2020;10:152. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 64. Munafò MR, Nosek BA, Bishop DVM al et. A manifesto for reproducible science. Nat Hum Behav 2017;1:0021. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65. Hucklenbroich P. “Disease entity” as the key theoretical concept of medicine. J Med Philos 2014;39:609‐33. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 66. Shorter E. The history of nosology and the rise of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. Dialogues Clin Neurosci 2015;17:59‐67. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67. Kendler KS. Philippe Pinel and the foundations of modern psychiatric nosology. Psychol Med 2020;50:2667‐72. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68. Ghaemi SN. DSM‐5 and the miracle that never happens. Acta Psychiatr Scand 2014;129:410‐2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 69. Krueger RF, Kotov R, Watson D et al. Progress in achieving quantitative classification of psychopathology. World Psychiatry 2018;17:282‐93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 70. Kotov R, Jonas KG, Carpenter WT et al. Validity and utility of Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP): I. Psychosis superspectrum. World Psychiatry 2020;19:151‐72. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71. Krueger RF, Hobbs KA, Conway CC et al. Validity and utility of Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP): II. Externalizing superspectrum. World Psychiatry 2021;20:171‐93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72. Watson D, Levin‐Aspenson HF, Waszczuk MA et al. Validity and utility of Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP): III. Emotional dysfunction superspectrum. World Psychiatry 2022;21:26‐54. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 73. Kotov R, Krueger RF, Watson D et al. The Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP): a dimensional alternative to traditional nosologies. J Abnorm Psychol 2017;126:454‐77. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 74. McCrae RR, Costa PT. Validation of the five‐factor model of personality across instruments and observers. J Pers Soc Psychol 1987;52:81‐90. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 75. Achenbach TM. The classification of children's psychiatric symptoms: a factor‐analytic study. Psychol Monogr 1966;80:1‐37. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 76. Caspi A, Moffitt TE. All for one and one for all: mental disorders in one dimension. Am J Psychiatry 2018;175:831‐44. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 77. Pettersson E, Larsson H, D'Onofrio BM et al. The general factor of psychopathology: a comparison with the general factor of intelligence with respect to magnitude and predictive validity. World Psychiatry 2020;19:206‐13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 78. Borsboom D. A network theory of mental disorders. World Psychiatry 2017;16:5‐13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 79. Ohlsson H, Kendler KS. Applying causal inference methods in psychiatric epidemiology: a review. JAMA Psychiatry 2020;77:637‐44. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 80. Richmond RC, Davey Smith G. Mendelian randomization: concepts and scope. Cold Spring Harb Perspect Med 2022;12:a040501. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 81. Dwyer DB, Falkai P, Koutsouleris N. Machine learning approaches for clinical psychology and psychiatry. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2018;14:91‐118. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 82. Rutledge RB, Chekroud AM, Huys QJ. Machine learning and big data in psychiatry: toward clinical applications. Curr Opin Neurobiol 2019;55:152‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 83. Koppe G, Meyer‐Lindenberg A, Durstewitz D. Deep learning for small and big data in psychiatry. Neuropsychopharmacology 2021;46:176‐90. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 84. Checkroud AM, Bondar J, Delgadillo J et al. The promise of machine learning in predicting treatment outcomes in psychiatry. World Psychiatry 2021;20:154‐93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 85. Bourla A, Ferreri F, Ogorzelec L et al. Psychiatrists’ attitudes toward disruptive new technologies: mixed‐methods study. JMIR Ment Health 2018;5:e10240. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 86. Cramer AOJ, Waldorp LJ, van der Maas HLJ et al. Comorbidity: a network perspective. Behav Brain Sci 2010;33:137‐50. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 87. Kessler RC. The categorical versus dimensional assessment controversy in the sociology of mental illness. J Health Soc Behav 2002;43:171‐88. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 88. Potuzak M, Ravichandran C, Lewandowski KE et al. Categorical vs dimensional classifications of psychotic disorders. Compr Psychiatry 2012;53:1118‐29. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 89. Fulford KWM, Handa A. Categorical and/or continuous? Learning from vascular surgery. World Psychiatry 2018;17:304‐5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 90. Eaton WW, McCutcheon A, Dryman A et al. Latent class analysis of anxiety and depression. Sociol Methods Res 1989;18:104‐25. [Google Scholar]
- 91. Kendler KS, First MB. Alternative futures for the DSM revision process: iteration v. paradigm shift. Br J Psychiatry 2010;197:263‐5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 92. Kratochwill TR, Horner RH, Levin JR et al. Single‐case design standards: an update and proposed upgrades. J School Psychol 2021;89:91‐105. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 93. London AJ. Artificial intelligence and black‐box medical decisions: accuracy versus explainability. Hastings Cent Rep 2019;49:15‐21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 94. Quinn TP, Jacobs S, Senadeera M et al. The three ghosts of medical AI: can the black‐box present deliver? Artif Intell Med 2022;124:102158. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 95. Torrey EF. Out of the shadows: confronting America's mental illness crisis. Chichester: Wiley, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- 96. Lamb HR, Bachrach LL. Some perspectives on deinstitutionalization. Psychiatr Serv 2001;52:1039‐45. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 97. Knapp M, Chisholm D, Astin J et al. The cost consequences of changing the hospital‐community balance: the mental health residential care study. Psychol Med 1997;27:681‐92. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 98. Slade M. Implementing shared decision making in routine mental health care. World Psychiatry 2017;16:146‐53. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 99. Lora A. An overview of the mental health system in Italy. Ann Ist Super Sanita 2009;45:5‐16. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 100. Mladenov T, Petri G. Critique of deinstitutionalisation in postsocialist Central and Eastern Europe. Disabil Soc 2020;35:1203‐26. [Google Scholar]
- 101. Lund C. Mental health and human rights in South Africa: the hidden humanitarian crisis. S Afr J Hum Rights 2016;32:403‐5. [Google Scholar]
- 102. Vigod SN, Kurdyak PA, Dennis CL et al. Transitional interventions to reduce early psychiatric readmissions in adults: systematic review. Br J Psychiatry 2013;202:187‐94. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 103. World Health Organization . Mental health policy, plans and programmes. Geneva: World Health Organization, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- 104. Thornicroft G, Tansella M. The balanced care model for global mental health. Psychol Med 2013;43:849‐63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 105. Unützer J, Carlo AD, Collins PY. Leveraging collaborative care to improve access to mental health care on a global scale. World Psychiatry 2020;19:36‐7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 106. World Health Organization. mhGAP intervention guide for mental, neurological and substance use disorders in non‐specialized health settings: mental health Gap Action Programme (mhGAP). version 2.0. Geneva: World Health Organization, 2016. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 107. Coulter A, Entwistle VA, Eccles A et al. Personalised care planning for adults with chronic or long‐term health conditions. Cochrane Database Syst Rev 2015;3:CD010523. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 108. Fulford KWM, Handa A. New resources for understanding patients’ values in the context of shared clinical decision‐making. World Psychiatry 2021;20:446‐7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 109. Slade M, Amering M, Farkas M et al. Uses and abuses of recovery: implementing recovery‐oriented practices in mental health systems. World Psychiatry 2014;13:12‐20. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 110. Waddell A, Lennox A, Spassova G et al. Barriers and facilitators to shared decision‐making in hospitals from policy to practice: a systematic review. Implement Sci 2021;16:74. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 111. Roberts T, Miguel Esponda G, Torre C et al. Reconceptualising the treatment gap for common mental disorders: a fork in the road for global mental health? Br J Psychiatry 2022; 10.1192/bjp.2021.221 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 112. Arango C, Dragioti E, Solmi M et al. Risk and protective factors for mental disorders beyond genetics: an evidence‐based atlas. World Psychiatry 2021;20:417‐36. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 113. Gureje O, Appiah‐Poku J, Bello T et al. Effect of collaborative care between traditional and faith healers and primary health‐care workers on psychosis outcomes in Nigeria and Ghana (COSIMPO): a cluster randomised controlled trial. Lancet 2020;396:612‐22. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 114. Jordans MJ, Kohrt BA, Luitel NP et al. Proactive community case‐finding to facilitate treatment seeking for mental disorders, Nepal. Bull World Health Organ 2017;95:531‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 115. Stein DJ. Psychiatric practice: caring for patients, collaborating with partners, or marketing to consumers? World Psychiatry 2017;16:156‐7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 116. Talbott JA. Twentieth‐century developments in American psychiatry. Psychiatr Q 1982;54:207‐19. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 117. Hofmann SG, Asnaani A, Vonk IJJ et al. The efficacy of cognitive behavioral therapy: a review of meta‐analyses. Cogn Ther Res 2012;36:427‐40. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 118. Driessen E, Dekker JJM, Peen J et al. The efficacy of adding short‐term psychodynamic psychotherapy to antidepressants in the treatment of depression: a systematic review and meta‐analysis of individual participant data. Clin Psychol Rev 2020;80:101886. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 119. Cuijpers P, Driessen E, Hollon SD et al. The efficacy of non‐directive supportive therapy for adult depression: a meta‐analysis. Clin Psychol Rev 2012;32:280‐91. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 120. Cuijpers P, Quero S, Noma H et al. Psychotherapies for depression: a network meta‐analysis covering efficacy, acceptability and long‐term outcomes of all main treatment types. World Psychiatry 2021;20:283‐93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 121. Cook SC, Schwartz AC, Kaslow NJ. Evidence‐based psychotherapy: advantages and challenges. Neurotherapeutics 2017;14:537‐45. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 122. Wolpe J. The formation of negative habits: a neurophysiological view. Psychol Rev 1952;59:290‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 123. Beck AT. The evolution of the cognitive model of depression and its neurobiological correlates. Am J Psychiatry 2008;165:969‐77. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 124. Hayes SC, Hofmann SG. “Third‐wave” cognitive and behavioral therapies and the emergence of a process‐based approach to intervention in psychiatry. World Psychiatry 2021;20:363‐75. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 125. Amouroux R. Beyond indifference and aversion: the critical reception and belated acceptance of behavior therapy in France. Hist Psychol 2017;20:313‐29. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 126. Olfson M, Marcus SC. National patterns in antidepressant medication treatment. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2009;66:848‐56. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 127. McHugh RK, Whitton SW, Peckham AD et al. Patient preference for psychological vs pharmacologic treatment of psychiatric disorders: a meta‐analytic review. J Clin Psychiatry 2013;74:595‐602. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 128. Grimshaw J, Thomas R, MacLennan G et al. Effectiveness and efficiency of guideline dissemination and implementation strategies. Health Technol Assess 2004;8:iii‐iv. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 129. Barth JH, Misra S, Aakre KM et al. Why are clinical practice guidelines not followed? Clin Chem Lab Med 2016;54:1133‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 130. Gagliardi AR, Brouwers MC, Palda VA et al. How can we improve guideline use? A conceptual framework of implementability. Implement Sci 2011;6:26. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 131. Layard R, Clark D, Knapp M et al. Cost‐benefit analysis of psychological therapy. Natl Inst Econ Rev 2007;202:90‐8. [Google Scholar]
- 132. Chisholm D, Sweeny K, Sheehan P et al. Scaling‐up treatment of depression and anxiety: a global return on investment analysis. Lancet Psychiatry 2016;3:415‐24. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 133. Clark DM. Realizing the mass public benefit of evidence‐based psychological therapies: the IAPT program. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2018;14:159‐83. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 134. Marks DF. IAPT under the microscope. J Health Psychol 2018;23:1131‐5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 135. Scott MJ. Improving Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT) – the need for radical reform. J Health Psychol 2018;23:1136‐47. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 136. Gyani A, Shafran R, Layard R et al. Enhancing recovery rates: lessons from year one of IAPT. Behav Res Ther 2013;51:597‐606. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 137. Clark DM, Canvin L, Green J et al. Transparency about the outcomes of mental health services (IAPT approach): an analysis of public data. Lancet 2018;391:679‐86. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 138. Wakefield S, Kellett S, Simmonds‐Buckley M et al. Improving Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT) in the United Kingdom: a systematic review and meta‐analysis of 10‐years of practice‐based evidence. Br J Clin Psychol 2021;60:1‐37. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 139. Cromarty P, Drummond A, Francis T et al. NewAccess for depression and anxiety: adapting the UK Improving Access to Psychological Therapies program across Australia. Australas Psychiatry 2016;24:489‐92. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 140. Naeem F, Pikard J, Rao S et al. Is it possible to provide low‐intensity cognitive behavioral treatment (CBT Lite) in Canada without additional costs to the health system? First‐year evaluation of a pilot CBT Lite program. Int J Ment Health 2017;46:253‐68. [Google Scholar]
- 141. Knapstad M, Nordgreen T, Smith ORF. Prompt mental health care, the Norwegian version of IAPT: clinical outcomes and predictors of change in a multicenter cohort study. BMC Psychiatry 2018;18:260. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 142. Kobori O, Nakazato M, Yoshinaga N et al. Transporting cognitive behavioral therapy (CBT) and the Improving Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT) project to Japan: preliminary observations and service evaluation in Chiba. J Ment Health Train Educ Pract 2014;9:155‐66. [Google Scholar]
- 143. Twomey C, O'Reilly G. Effectiveness of a freely available computerised cognitive behavioural therapy programme (MoodGYM) for depression: meta‐analysis. Aust N Z J Psychiatry 2017;51:260‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 144. Rahman A, Hamdani SU, Awan NR et al. Effect of a multicomponent behavioral intervention in adults impaired by psychological distress in a conflict‐affected area of Pakistan: a randomized clinical trial. JAMA 2016;316:2609. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 145. Rahman A, Khan MN, Hamdani SU et al. Effectiveness of a brief group psychological intervention for women in a post‐conflict setting in Pakistan: a single‐blind, cluster, randomised controlled trial. Lancet 2019;393:1733‐44. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 146. Timimi S. The diagnosis is correct, but National Institute of Health and Care Excellence guidelines are part of the problem not the solution. J Health Psychol 2018;23:1148‐52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 147. Martin C, Iqbal Z, Airey ND et al L. Improving Access to Psychological Therapies (IAPT) has potential but is not sufficient: how can it better meet the range of primary care mental health needs? Br J Clin Psychol 2022;61:157‐74. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 148. Andrews G, Issakidis C, Sanderson K et al. Utilising survey data to inform public policy: comparison of the cost‐effectiveness of treatment of ten mental disorders. Br J Psychiatry 2004;184:526‐33. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 149. Ormel J, Hollon SD, Kessler RC et al. More treatment but no less depression: the treatment‐prevalence paradox. Clin Psychol Rev 2022;91:102111. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 150. Ferrari AJ, Charlson FJ, Norman RE et al. Burden of depressive disorders by country, sex, age, and year: findings from the Global Burden of Disease study 2010. PLoS Med 2013;10:e1001547. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 151. Leichsenring F, Steinert C, Rabung S et al. The efficacy of psychotherapies and pharmacotherapies for mental disorders in adults: an umbrella review and meta‐analytic evaluation of recent meta‐analyses. World Psychiatry 2022;21:133‐45. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 152. Cuijpers P, Karyotaki E, Reijnders M et al. Was Eysenck right after all? A reassessment of the effects of psychotherapy for adult depression. Epidemiol Psychiatr Sci 2019;28:21‐30. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 153. Torous J, Bucci S, Bell IH et al. The growing field of digital psychiatry: current evidence and the future of apps, social media, chatbots, and virtual reality. World Psychiatry 2021;20:318‐35. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 154. Kinoshita S, Cortright K, Crawford A et al. Changes in telepsychiatry regulations during the COVID‐19 pandemic: 17 countries and regions’ approaches to an evolving healthcare landscape. Psychol Med 2020; 10.1017/S0033291720004584. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 155. Insel TR. Digital phenotyping: a global tool for psychiatry. World Psychiatry 2018;17:276‐7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 156. Bardram JE, Matic A. A decade of ubiquitous computing research in mental health. IEEE Pervasive Comput 2020;19:62‐72. [Google Scholar]
- 157. Hirschtritt ME, Insel TR. Digital technologies in psychiatry: present and future. Focus (Am Psychiatr Publ) 2018;16:251‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 158. Mishkind MC, Norr AM, Katz AC et al. Review of virtual reality treatment in psychiatry: evidence versus current diffusion and use. Curr Psychiatry Rep 2017;19:80. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 159. Abd‐Alrazaq AA, Rababeh A, Alajlani M et al. Effectiveness and safety of using chatbots to improve mental health: systematic review and meta‐analysis. J Med Internet Res 2020;22:e16021. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 160. Onie S, Li X, Liang M et al. The use of closed‐circuit television and video in suicide prevention: narrative review and future directions. JMIR Ment Health 2021;8:e27663. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 161. Rohani DA, Faurholt‐Jepsen M, Kessing LV et al. Correlations between objective behavioral features collected from mobile and wearable devices and depressive mood symptoms in patients with affective disorders: systematic review. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2018;6:e165. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 162. Low DM, Bentley KH, Ghosh SS. Automated assessment of psychiatric disorders using speech: a systematic review. Laryngoscope Investig Otolaryngol 2020;5:96‐116. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 163. Sano A, Taylor S, McHill AW et al. Identifying objective physiological markers and modifiable behaviors for self‐reported stress and mental health status using wearable sensors and mobile phones: observational study. J Med Internet Res 2018;20:e210. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 164. Ghosh S, Sahu S, Ganguly N et al. EmoKey: an emotion‐aware smartphone keyboard for mental health monitoring. Presented at the 11th International Conference on Communication Systems & Networks, Bangalore, January 2019.
- 165. O'Dea B, Larsen ME, Batterham PJ et al. A linguistic analysis of suicide‐related twitter posts. Crisis 2017;38:319‐29. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 166. Silver L. Smartphone ownership is growing rapidly around the world, but not always equally. Pew Research Center, February 5, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- 167. Huckvale K, Nicholas J, Torous J et al. Smartphone apps for the treatment of mental health conditions: status and considerations. Curr Opin Psychol 2020;36:65‐70. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 168. Lecomte T, Potvin S, Corbière M et al. Mobile apps for mental health issues: meta‐review of meta‐analyses. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2020;8:e17458. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 169. Torous J, Wisniewski H, Liu G et al. Mental health mobile phone app usage, concerns, and benefits among psychiatric outpatients: comparative survey study. JMIR Ment Health 2018;5:e11715. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 170. Firth J, Torous J, Nicholas J et al. The efficacy of smartphone‐based mental health interventions for depressive symptoms: a meta‐analysis of randomized controlled trials. World Psychiatry 2017;16:287‐98. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 171. Firth J, Torous J, Nicholas J et al. Can smartphone mental health interventions reduce symptoms of anxiety? A meta‐analysis of randomized controlled trials. J Affect Disord 2017;218:15‐22. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 172. Torous J, Haim A. Dichotomies in the development and implementation of digital mental health tools. Psychiatr Serv 2018;69:1204‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 173. Connolly SL, Hogan JB, Ecker AH et al. Telepsychiatry and video‐to‐home (including security issues). In: Stein D, Fineberg N, Chamberlain S (eds). Mental health in a digital world. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2022:147‐67. [Google Scholar]
- 174. Zulueta J, Ajilore OA. Beyond non‐inferior: how telepsychiatry technologies can lead to superior care. Int Rev Psychiatry 2021;33:366‐71. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 175. Targum SD, Sauder C, Evans M et al. Ecological momentary assessment as a measurement tool in depression trials. J Psychiatr Res 2021;136:256‐64. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 176. Weizenbaum E, Torous J, Fulford D. Cognition in context: understanding the everyday predictors of cognitive performance in a new era of measurement. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2020;8:e14328. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 177. Torous J, Kiang MV, Lorme J et al. New tools for new research in psychiatry: a scalable and customizable platform to empower data driven smartphone research. JMIR Ment Health 2016;3:e16. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 178. Gaggioli A, Pioggia G, Tartarisco G et al. A mobile data collection platform for mental health research. Pers Ubiquitous Comput 2013;17:241‐51. [Google Scholar]
- 179. Torous J, Hsin H. Empowering the digital therapeutic relationship: virtual clinics for digital health interventions. NPJ Digit Med 2018;1:16. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 180. Huckvale K, Venkatesh S, Christensen H. Toward clinical digital phenotyping: a timely opportunity to consider purpose, quality, and safety. NPJ Digit Med 2019;2:88. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 181. Majumder S, Deen MJ. Smartphone sensors for health monitoring and diagnosis. Sensors 2019;19:2164. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 182. Keusch F, Wenz A, Conrad F. Do you have your smartphone with you? Behavioral barriers for measuring everyday activities with smartphone sensors. Comput Hum Behav 2022;127:107054. [Google Scholar]
- 183. Bauer M, Glenn T, Geddes J et al. Smartphones in mental health: a critical review of background issues, current status and future concerns. Int J Bipolar Disord 2020;8:2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 184. Nicholas J, Larsen ME, Proudfoot J et al. Mobile apps for bipolar disorder: a systematic review of features and content quality. J Med Internet Res 2015;17:e198. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 185. Wilson H, Stoyanov SR, Gandabhai S et al. The quality and accuracy of mobile apps to prevent driving after drinking alcohol. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2016;4:e98. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 186. Mani M, Kavanagh DJ, Hides L et al. Review and evaluation of mindfulness‐based iPhone apps. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2015;3:e82. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 187. Torous J, Nicholas J, Larsen ME et al. Clinical review of user engagement with mental health smartphone apps: evidence, theory and improvements. Evid Based Ment Health 2018;21:116‐9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 188. Larsen ME, Huckvale K, Nicholas J et al. Using science to sell apps: evaluation of mental health app store quality claims. NPJ Digit Med 2019;2:18 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 189. Powell A, Singh P, Torous J. The complexity of mental health app privacy policies: a potential barrier to privacy. JMIR mHealth uHealth 2018;6:e158. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 190. Watts G. COVID‐19 and the digital divide in the UK. Lancet Digit Health 2020;2:e395‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 191. Carter H, Araya R, Anjur K et al. The emergence of digital mental health in low‐income and middle‐income countries: a review of recent advances and implications for the treatment and prevention of mental disorders. J Psychiatr Res 2021;133:223‐46. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 192. Schueller SM, Neary M, O'Loughlin K et al. Discovery of and interest in health apps among those with mental health needs: survey and focus group study. J Med Internet Res 2018;20:e10141. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 193. Hanson K, Gilson L, Goodman C et al. Is private health care the answer to the health problems of the world's poor? PLoS Med 2008;5:e233. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 194. Keefe PR. Empire of pain: the secret history of the Sackler Dynasty. Toronto: Bond Street Books, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- 195. Martin A, Pugmire J, Wells V et al. Systematic literature review of the relationship between adolescents’ screen time, sleep and mental health. Edinburgh: Scottish Government, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- 196. Ashton JJ, Beattie RM. Screen time in children and adolescents: is there evidence to guide parents and policy? Lancet Child Adolesc Health 2019;3:292‐4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 197. Sohn SY, Rees P, Wildridge B et al. Prevalence of problematic smartphone usage and associated mental health outcomes amongst children and young people: a systematic review, meta‐analysis and GRADE of the evidence. BMC Psychiatry 2019;19:356. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 198. Tang S, Werner‐Seidler A, Torok M et al. The relationship between screen time and mental health in young people: a systematic review of longitudinal studies. Clin Psychol Rev 2021;86:102021. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 199. Wang X, Li Y, Fan H. The associations between screen time‐based sedentary behavior and depression: a systematic review and meta‐analysis. BMC Publ Health 2019;19:1524. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 200. Ebert DD, Van Daele T, Nordgreen T et al. Internet‐ and mobile‐based psychological interventions: applications, efficacy, and potential for improving mental health. Eur Psychol 2018;23:167‐87. [Google Scholar]
- 201. Bader CS, Skurla M, Vahia IV. Technology in the assessment, treatment, and management of depression. Harv Rev Psychiatry 2020;28:60‐6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 202. Bantjes J, Slabbert P. The digital therapeutic relationship: retaining humanity in the digital age. In: Stein D, Fineberg N, Chamberlain S (eds). Mental health in a digital world. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2022:223‐37. [Google Scholar]
- 203. Mohr DC, Weingardt KR, Reddy M et al. Three problems with current digital mental health research… and three things we can do about them. Psychiatr Serv 2017;68:427‐9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 204. Stein DJ, Naslund JA, Bantjes J. COVID‐19 and the global acceleration of digital psychiatry. Lancet Psychiatry 2022;9:8‐9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 205. Chen X. Understanding the development and perception of global health for more effective student education. Yale J Biol Med 2014;87:231‐40. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 206. Brown TM, Cueto M, Fee E. The World Health Organization and the transition from “international” to “global” public health. Am J Public Health 2006;96:62‐72. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 207. Salm M, Ali M, Minihane M et al. Defining global health: findings from a systematic review and thematic analysis of the literature. BMJ Glob Health 2021;6:e005292. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 208. Kolappa K, Henderson DC, Kishore SP. No physical health without mental health: lessons unlearned? Bull World Health Organ 2013;91:3‐3A. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 209. Stein DJ, Benjet C, Gureje O et al. Integrating mental health with other non‐communicable diseases. BMJ 2019;364:l295. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 210. Becker AE, Kleinman A. Mental health and the global agenda. N Engl J Med 2013;369:1380‐1. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 211. Sartorius N, Harding TW. The WHO collaborative study on strategies for extending mental health care, I: The genesis of the study. Am J Psychiatry 1983;140:1470‐3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 212. Gureje O, Hollins S, Botbol M et al. Report of the WPA task force on brain drain. World Psychiatry 2009;8:115‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 213. Sartorius N. Methodologic problems of common terminology, measurement, and classification. 11. Modifications and new approaches to taxonomy in long‐term care: advantages and limitations of the ICD. Med Care 1976;14(Suppl. 5):109‐15. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 214. Singla DR, Kohrt BA, Murray LK et al. Psychological treatments for the world: lessons from low‐ and middle‐income countries. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2017;13:149‐81. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 215. Kohrt BA, Jordans MJD, Rai S et al. Therapist competence in global mental health: development of the ENhancing Assessment of Common Therapeutic factors (ENACT) rating scale. Behav Res Ther 2015;69:11‐21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 216. Kohrt BA, Schafer A, Willhoite A et al. Ensuring Quality in Psychological Support (WHO EQUIP) developing a competent global workforce. World Psychiatry 2020;19:115‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 217. Knapp M, Wong G. Economics and mental health: the current scenario. World Psychiatry 2020;19:3‐14. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 218. Votruba N, Grant J, Thornicroft G. The EVITA framework for evidence‐based mental health policy agenda setting in low‐ and middle‐income countries. Health Policy Plan 2020;35:424‐39. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 219. Thornicroft G, Mehta N, Clement S et al. Evidence for effective interventions to reduce mental‐health‐related stigma and discrimination. Lancet 2016;387:1123‐32. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 220. Pickard H. Responsibility without blame for addiction. Neuroethics 2017;10:169‐80. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 221. Lebowitz MS, Appelbaum PS. Biomedical explanations of psychopathology and their implications for attitudes and beliefs about mental disorders. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2019;15:555‐77. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 222. Lund C, Brooke‐Sumner C, Baingana F et al. Social determinants of mental disorders and the Sustainable Development Goals: a systematic review of reviews. Lancet Psychiatry 2018;5:357‐69. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 223. Shah N, Walker IF, Naik Y et al. National or population level interventions addressing the social determinants of mental health – an umbrella review. BMC Public Health 2021;21:2118. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 224. Misra S, Stevenson A, Haroz EE et al. ‘Global mental health’: systematic review of the term and its implicit priorities. BJPsych Open 2019;5:e47. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 225. Osborn TL, Wasil AR, Weisz JR et al. Where is the global in global mental health? A call for inclusive multicultural collaboration. Gen Psychiatry 2020;33:e100351. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 226. Richards RJ, Daston L (eds). Kuhn's structure of scientific revolutions at fifty: reflections on a science classic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 227. Kuhn TS. Structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- 228. Morris E. The Ashtray (or the man who denied reality). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- 229. Stein D. Problems of living: perspectives from philosophy, psychiatry and cognitive‐affective science. Cambridge: Academic Press, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- 230. Goldberg D. Findings from “London's Mental Health”: a service in crisis. Acta Psychiatr Scand 2000;101:57‐60. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 231. Wise J. Mental health: patients and service in crisis. BMJ 2017;356:j1141. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 232. Melnyk BM. The child & adolescent mental health crisis: closing the service gap. Imprint 2007;54:58‐63. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 233. Kirwin P. Canary in a coal mine: geriatric psychiatry in crisis. Am J Geriatr Psychiatry 2016;24:690‐2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 234. Jablensky A. Psychiatry in crisis? Back to fundamentals. World Psychiatry 2010;9:29‐29. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 235. Kleinman A. Rethinking psychiatry: from cultural category to personal experience. New York: Free Press, 1988. [Google Scholar]
- 236. Katschnig H. Are psychiatrists an endangered species? Observations on internal and external challenges to the profession. World Psychiatry 2010;9:21‐8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 237. Bhugra D, Tasman A, Pathare S et al. The WPA‐Lancet Psychiatry Commission on the Future of Psychiatry. Lancet Psychiatry 2017;4:775‐818. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 238. Stein DJ, He Y, Phillips A et al. Global mental health and neuroscience: potential synergies. Lancet Psychiatry 2015;2:178‐85. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 239. Desmond‐Hellmann S. Progress lies in precision. Science 2016;353:731. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 240. Overbeck G, Davidsen AS, Kousgaard MB. Enablers and barriers to implementing collaborative care for anxiety and depression: a systematic qualitative review. Implement Sci 2016;11:165. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 241. Fusar‐Poli P, Correll CU, Arango C et al. Preventive psychiatry: a blueprint for improving the mental health of young people. World Psychiatry 2021;20:200‐21. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 242. Nesse RM, Stein DJ. How evolutionary psychiatry can advance psychopharmacology. Dialogues Clin Neurosci 2019;21:167‐75. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 243. Jeste D, Palmer B. Positive psychiatry: a clinical handbook. Washington: American Psychiatric Association Publishing, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- 244. Duarte CS, Monk C, Weissman MM et al. Intergenerational psychiatry: a new look at a powerful perspective. World Psychiatry 2020;19:175‐6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 245. McConnell D, Savulescu J. Welfarist psychiatry goes global. In: Stein D, Singh I (eds). Global mental health and neuroethics. London: Elsevier/Academic Press, 2020:37‐54. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 246. Eisenberg L. The subjective in medicine. Perspect Biol Med 1983;27:48‐61. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 247. Stein DJ. Is there a “mosquito net” for anxiety and mood disorders? Curr Psychiatry Rep 2009;11:264‐5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 248. Ban TA. The role of serendipity in drug discovery. Dialogues Clin Neurosci 2006;8:335‐44. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 249. Krause KR, Chung S, Sousa Fialho MDL et al. The challenge of ensuring affordability, sustainability, consistency, and adaptability in the common metrics agenda. Lancet Psychiatry 2021;8:1094‐102. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 250. Zachar P, Kendler KS. The philosophy of nosology. Annu Rev Clin Psychol 2017;13:49‐71. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 251. Maj M, Stein DJ, Parker G et al. The clinical characterization of the adult patient with depression aimed at personalization of management. World Psychiatry 2020;19:269‐93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 252. Maj M, van Os J, De Hert M et al. The clinical characterization of the patient with primary psychosis aimed at personalization of management. World Psychiatry 2021;20:4‐33. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 253. Stein DJ, Craske MG, Rothbaum BO et al. The clinical characterization of the adult patient with an anxiety or related disorder aimed at personalization of management. World Psychiatry 2021;20:336‐56. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 254. Kazdin AE. Addressing the treatment gap: a key challenge for extending evidence‐based psychosocial interventions. Behav Res Ther 2017;88:7‐18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 255. Graham BM, Callaghan BL, Richardson R. Bridging the gap: lessons we have learnt from the merging of psychology and psychiatry for the optimisation of treatments for emotional disorders. Behav Res Ther 2014;62:3‐16. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 256. Kessler RC, Luedtke A. Pragmatic precision psychiatry – a new direction for optimizing treatment selection. JAMA Psychiatry 2021;78:1384‐90. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]